Economics and the Self-Organisation Approach

download Economics and the Self-Organisation Approach

of 18

Transcript of Economics and the Self-Organisation Approach

  • 8/18/2019 Economics and the Self-Organisation Approach

    1/18

     

    Economics and the Self-Organisation Approach: Alfred Marshall Revisited?Author(s): John Foster

    Source: The Economic Journal , Vol. 103, No. 419 (Jul., 1993), pp. 975-991

    Published by: Wiley on behalf of the Royal Economic Society

    Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2234714Accessed: 20-04-2016 21:11 UTC

     

    R F R N S 

    Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:

    http://www.jstor.org/stable/2234714?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents

    You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.

     

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

    http://about.jstor.org/terms

     

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted

    digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about

    JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    Wiley, Royal Economic Society  are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access toThe Economic Journal 

    This content downloaded from 193.227.1.43 on Wed, 20 Apr 2016 21:11:29 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 Economics and the Self-Organisation Approach

    2/18

     The Economic Journal, 103 (July), 975-991. ? Royal Economic Society 1993. Published by Blackwell

     Publishers, io8 Cowley Road, Oxford OX4 iJF, UK and 238 Main Street, Cambridge, MA 02142, USA.

     ECONOMCS AND THE SELF-ORGANSATION

     APPROACH:

     ALFRED MARSHALL REVISITED?*

     John Foster

     Several recent contributions in the loosely-defined field of 'evolutionary

     economics' have focussed upon time irreversibility as the primary source of

     evolutionary change in economic systems (see, for example, Foster, I987;

     David, I988; Arthur, I988; Dosi and Metcalfe, i99i). This interest in time

     irreversibility has been, in part, stimulated by recent developments in the

     natural sciences which seek to understand the order which is maintained in

     systems which have chaotic potential. The second law of thermodynamics (the

     entropy law) is seen by some as the fundamental source of time irreversibility.

     However, it is the relatively new area of non-equilibrium thermodynamics

     which is of interest, rather than traditional equilibrium thermodynamics.

     'Dissipative structures' are viewed as being able to offset the impact of the

     entropy law by importing free energy and exporting entropy. The mechanisms

     developed to do this are, in turn, viewed as being subject to a degree of time

     irreversibility, so that change becomes, necessarily, evolutionary in character.

     Over the past two decades, what has become known as the 'self-organisation'

     approach (Prigogine and Stengers, I984) has come to offer a non-equilibrium

     thermodynamical- alternative to the traditional Newton/Boltzmann mech-

     anical approach to understanding dynamic processes in the natural sciences.

     The emergence of the non-equilibrium thermodynamical approach to self-

     organisation ought to be of interest to those economists who, like natural

     scientists before them, adopted the mechanical approach since:

     it is clear that many empirical phenomena are not covered well by either

     the theoretical or empirical analyses based on linear stochastic systems,

     sometimes not by either. The presence and persistence of cyclical

     fluctuations in the economy as a whole of irregular timing and amplitude

     are not consistent with a view that an economy tends to return to

     equilibrium states after any disturbance (Arrow, I988, p. 278).

     Many economists, primarily of an institutionalist or Schumpeterian

     persuasion, have been well aware of the time irreversible, nonlinear character

     of economic processes for some time and, therefore, have avoided using models

     based upon the conventional mechanical metaphor. However, the problem

     with such a stance is that it often yields informal analysis of economic processes

     * I am indebted to Geoff Harcourt, Geoff Hodgson and two anonymous referees for their valuable

     comments on earlier versions of this paper. I would also like to thank Peter Burley and his colleagues at La

     Trobe University for their very helpful discussions of a preliminary version of the paper at their

     interdisciplinary conference entitled 'Thermodynamical Thinking in Economics' (4 October I99I). The

     usual disclaimer applies.

     [ 975 ]

    This content downloaded from 193.227.1.43 on Wed, 20 Apr 2016 21:11:29 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 Economics and the Self-Organisation Approach

    3/18

     976 THEECONOMCJOURNALJULY

     and evidence which is historically descriptive. Economists who hold con-

     ventional views as to what constitutes science tend to reject such evidence and,

     thus, it has little impact in the mainstream of the discipline. Consequently,

     some economists have preferred to adopt a pragmatic approach whereby the

     mechanical approach is retained, because of its usefulness in the construction

     of formal models, but heavily qualified to allow for time irreversibility and

     evolutionary change.

     It is argued in this paper that an outstanding example of the latter was

     Alfred Marshall, despite his textbook reputation as one of the founding fathers

     of time reversible, non-evolutionary neoclassical economics. This view is shared

     by, for example, Rostow (I989) who, on reviewing several contributions to the

     nonlinear dynamic perspective on economic processes states that:

     For the purposes of this occasion, Alfred Marshall is the most important

     economist of the past two and a half centuries. He, more than any of his

     predecessors or successors, understood and lucidly articulated the inherent

     tension between the use of the concept of stable equilibrium in economics

     and the nonlinear, irreversible character of 'the conditions of real

     economic life' (Rostow, i989, p. 36).

     Economic historians are not generally as well-disposed towards Marshall's

     economics as this. Furthermore, neoclassically-inclined economists have tended

     to disagree with the proposition that Marshall was lucidly articulate. In this

     paper, it is contended that Marshall has been widely misinterpreted by many

     neoclassical economists, simply because they could not grasp the centrality of

     time irreversibility in his economic analysis. Thus, progress in implementing

     th'e scientific agenda set out by Marshall has been limited to only the early

     stages which he identified as achievable in his own time. The subsequent stages,

     in Marshall's view, were to involve the emergence of evolutionary approaches

     in economics, drawing upon evolutionary biology. However, here again, it will

     be contended that misinterpretation, this time by 'evolutionary' economists,

     has been prevalent.

     It will be argued that Marshall was neither a neoclassical economist nor an

     evolutionary economist, in the contemporary usage of these terms, but one who

     saw time irreversibility as the central problem with which economic science

     must deal. To Marshall, the mechanical metaphor was a serviceable one to deal

     with exogenous shocks and related homeostatic reactions in the short period,

     but he saw evolutionary change as a logical implication of the presence of time

     irreversibility in the long period. Over a century after the publication of the first

     edition of the Principles, proponents of the self-organisation approach in the

     natural sciences have reached a similar conclusion. In this paper this surprising

     connection is explored and some assessment is made of the extent to which the

     latter can help to offer the foundations of a new, post-Marshallian economic

     science.

     K Royal Economic Society 1993

    This content downloaded from 193.227.1.43 on Wed, 20 Apr 2016 21:11:29 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 Economics and the Self-Organisation Approach

    4/18

     1993] MARSHALL AND SELF-ORGANISATION 977

     I. MARSHALL AND NEOCLASSICISM

     Much of what is regarded as economic science today stems directly from Alfred

     Marshall's Principles. Milton Friedman, Paul Samuelson and, of course,

     Maynard Keynes all acknowledged that Marshall founded a science of

     economics, but all three offer different views as to what it constituted. It is

     argued here that Marshall's approach, influenced strongly by his background

     and ongoing interest in the natural sciences, was not fully developed by any of

     these three great disciples.

     Most students of economics have been persuaded, since Samuelson (I946),

     that Marshall was a founding father of neoclassical economics. However,

     although Marshall appeared to defend neoclassical economics on many

     occasions in the lectures that he delivered, it was really a defence of economic

     science against political economy as he saw it in his time. Marshall did not see

     economic science as being at the interface of economics and politics but, rather,

     at the interface of economics and ethics (Reisman, I990). To him, economists

     bore a heavy moral responsibility to apply economic science dispassionately

     and fairly, with social welfare in mind, as a counter to the sectional interests

     which dominated the political arena. This position was to have a considerable

     influence on Keynes's economics and his view of the economist's role in society.

     For Samuelson, at a much greater distance in time and space from Marshall,

     this position was reduced to the simpler task of making economics more

     scientific, in the sense that the term is used in the natural sciences. Undeterred

     by Shove's (I942) authoritative assessment of Marshall's economic theory, he

     set himself the task of developing what he saw as the most scientific aspects of

     the Principles in its technical footnotes and appendices.

     Samuelson was part of a wave of mathematicians and scientists who

     colonised economics from the I 930S on and seemed to have little appreciation

     of the historical origins of neoclassical thinking. In particular, they wasted little

     time in asking why so many scientists, such as Jevons, Walras, Edgeworth,

     Fisher and Pareto, who were all trained in physics, had entered the field of

     political economy from about I 870 on, to develop a formal representation of

     neoclassical economics. They all imported a particular physical metaphor into

     neoclassical economics: that of equilibrium in a field of force and its purpose

     was to give mathematical precision to the progressive, free-market ideas of

     Adam Smith (I986). As Darwinians stirred controversy, in both biology and

     sociology, and political economy spawned Marxism, with its disturbing picture

     of social dynamics, economists were offered an approach which was ahistorical

     and safe, offering ideological support to capitalism but no science of the

     unfolding of economic events. Marginalism, with its abstract portrayal of

     incremental precision, offered a stark contrast to the upheaval of political

     revolutions and the bloody struggle of natural selection. It was a matter of taste

     as to whether the resultant neoclassical general equilibrium system was viewed

     as involving the invisible hand of God or of natural selection.

     Today, mathematical economists, such as Debreu (i99i), offer little in the

     way of an indication that it may have been economic ideology, more than

     K Royal Economic Society I993

    This content downloaded from 193.227.1.43 on Wed, 20 Apr 2016 21:11:29 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 Economics and the Self-Organisation Approach

    5/18

     978 THEECONOMCJOURNALJULY

     scientific requirements, which swept neoclassical economics to prominence in

     the twentieth century. As Mirowski (i 99I ) reminds us, early marginalists were

     soon taken to task with regard to their scientific pretensions, by other

     mathematicians and physicists who pointed out the incorrectness, in a scientific

     sense, of the application of the chosen physical metaphor to economics. As

     ideology, of course, technical objections did not matter and, indeed, many in

     the second wave of neoclassical economists in the early 20th century were not

     trained in mathematics and even viewed formalism with some suspicion.

     At around the turn of the century, Thorstein Veblen asked his famous

     question: Why is economics not an evolutionary science? It was an

     unreasonable question because biology itself had hardly become an evol-

     utionary science at that time. All this was clear to Alfred Marshall who also

     argued that economic science would have to become evolutionary, in the

     Spencerian more than the Darwinian sense of the term (Hodgson, I993), but

     that statical analogies of the physical kind would have to suffice until new

     biological analogies could be operationalised satisfactorily in economics.

     Marshall's solution was to adopt a pragmatic approach to the application of

     the mechanical analogy, keeping it in the domain of real world application by

     confronting the question, not of evolution, but of time irreversibility.

     Milton Friedman seemed to understand, much better than Paul Samuelson,

     Marshall's pragmatic approach to the application of theoretical principles in

     scientific economics. However, Friedman did not dwell upon Marshall's

     attempts to deal with the difficulties presented by time irreversibility for

     neoclassical analysis. Instead, he adopted Marshall's time frames as a way of

     dgfining partial equilibrium in an abstract short run, thus eliminating the

     historical time in Marshall's period distinctions. Correspondingly, he accepted

     the ideological construct of a timeless Walrasian general equilibrium. Marshall,

     the scientist, did not:

     in the first edition ... the titles of the books and chapters, a well as the text

     itself, follow the mathematical framework very closely. In later versions,

     the connection became somewhat blurred by the author's restless quest

     after realism and the increasing prominence given to the element of time

     and to the absence of anything which can be properly be called a position

     of long-period equilibrium where increasing returns prevail (Shove, I942,

     P. 300).

     Because evolutionary economics was something for the future and

     comparative static economics was his present, Marshall focussed on the

     problem of time irreversibility rather than evolution. This was entirely sensible

     because it was the inadequate treatment of time irreversibility in the mechanical

     approach which caused so much difficulty in economic applications. Marshall

     argued in his Principles that all systems could be viewed at different levels and

     that the mechanical one was the firm backbone of reason and analysis (p. 769,

     7th edn), but that the element of time ... is the centre of the chief difficulty of

     almost every economic problem' (p. vii, 7th edn). The experience of historical

     time meant that 'every plain and simple doctrine as to the relations between

     K Royal Economic Society 1993

    This content downloaded from 193.227.1.43 on Wed, 20 Apr 2016 21:11:29 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 Economics and the Self-Organisation Approach

    6/18

     1993] MARSHALL AND SELF-ORGANISATION 979

     cost of production, demand and value is necessarily false' (p. 368, 8th edn).

     Statical theory is so limited that there is a danger in throwing it into definite

     form at all' (p. 46, 8th edn).

     Samuelson would attribute these warnings to confusion and tend to ignore

     them as he helped to develop the modern formal version of neoclassical

     economics, even at a time when it was clear that physicists themselves had

     become concerned with the validity of their time reversible approach to field

     force equilibrium. Take, for example, Samuelson's (I972) view of the

     applicability of hysteresis in economics: 'when the equilibrium of a system

     depends on (and is dictated by) its path towards equilibrium, the scientist has

     an uncomfortable feeling' (p. 441). Thus, modern neoclassical economics

     gradually eliminated historical time and expunged Marshall's economics of its

     most important element:

     Marshall s endeavours to incorporate time as an essential component of his

     analysis are responsible for much of the careful imprecision so charac-

     teristic of the Principles... and it is no accident that the modern striving for

     rigour has produced models which are strictly timeless. Even the recent

     extensions of equilibrium theory to include markets distinguished by date

     are devices for evading, rather than dealing with, the difficulties which

     Marshall had in mind (Loasby, I978, p. 2).

     Apart from the more obvious quotations from the Principles concerning habits

     and other time-dependent processes, it is little appreciated that, even when

     explaining the determinants of demand, using the example of tea, he is careful

     not to use timeless marginal utility theory. Utility is derived from the act of

     purchasing tea not consuming it. Thus, utility is related intimately to the time

     spent upon purchase, juxtaposed against alternative uses of time, not to the

     utility yielded by future consumption: 'if, instead of buying it he makes the

     thing himself, then its marginal utility is the utility of that part which he thinks

     only just worthwhile to make (Marshall, 7th edn, p. 93). If the unit in question

     had been, say, a small packet of tea, the distinction between the utility of

     purchase and that of future consumption could, perhaps, be overlooked.

     However, Marshall deliberately selects the decision to buy annually, so his

     demand curve is for a stock, not a flow (see, for example, the Principles, 4th edn,

     pp. i69-72) and, in essence, involves a timing decision: 'The total utility of a

     thing to anyone ... increases with every increase in his stock of it, but not as fast

     as his stock increases' (Marshall, 7th edn, p. 93).

     It is, of course, necessary for there to have been a past preference for a flow

     of tea consumption per unit of time, the sum of which helps determine annual

     stock demand, but Marshall proposes a very large range of stock demands at

     different prices which would be very unlikely to be mirrored in everyday acts

     of consumption. What he describes is a speculative decision within a process

     which is occurring 'in' time, where a high price invokes a decision to buy a

     small amount to 'get by' in the immediate future and, when prices are low,

     stockpiling occurs. Notions of 'normal', historically determined, prices and

     quantities loom large in such decision-making, as they do throughout the

     K Royal Economic Society 1993

    This content downloaded from 193.227.1.43 on Wed, 20 Apr 2016 21:11:29 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 Economics and the Self-Organisation Approach

    7/18

     98 THEECONOMCJOURNALJULY

     Principles. Thus, even at the very heart of his treatment of demand, we see the

     'careful imprecision' of Marshall, noted by Loasby (I978), at work to keep

     historical time in his analysis. Marshall's desire to distance himself fromJevons

     is well known and neoclassical economists can only turn legitimately to J. B.

     Clark for theoretical support for flow demand analysis derived formally from

     marginal utility theory.

     II. MARSHALL AND HSTORICISM

     Despite what has been said, the neoclassical economist can point to the fact

     that Marshall did apply marginalism in the context of the firm's decisions.

     However, Marshall did not apply marginalism in the conventional textbook

     sense. Instead, he applied it in an evolutionary manner in his 'principle of

     substitution ' which resulted in a ' tendency to variation [which] is a chief cause

     of progress' (Marshall, 7th edn, p. 355). On p. 356, Marshall gave conventional

     marginalism only a partial role to play. Nevertheless, because of the difficulties

     in operationalising the principle, he retained conventional marginalism and

     attempted to deal with the problem of time irreversibility and evolutionary

     change by breaking up historical time into appropriate periods. Currie and

     Steedman (I990) rally together convincing evidence that Marshall did not

     define the neoclassical short run in terms of fixity of capital, as most textbooks

     imply, rather he was attempting to deal with general decision problems faced

     in actual historical periods. 'Bygones are bygones' because of time irre-

     versibility. Fixity need not occur automatically in the short period, even

     though limited scope for adaptation is a dominating feature of that period.

     Furthermore, Currie and Steedman (i99o) go on to argue that Marshall did

     not confine the problem of time irreversibility to the short period. They remind

     us ofJoseph Schumpeter's assessment, made four decades ago, that Marshall's

     falling long-run supply curves are not theoretical but, rather, historical

     constructions which:

     dealt with an irreversible process and are not at all like the ordinary

     supply curves on which the firm can travel back and forth. They depict

     historical processes in a generalised form (Schumpeter, I 954, p. 995, n. 9).

     Marshall could not draw upon any coherent treatment of time irreversibility

     in the natural sciences of his time so he adapted what was at his disposal,

     namely, field force equilibrium. However, his depiction of the equilibration

     process is concerned with the adjustment of variables to their 'normal' levels

     and, therefore, deals with homeostasis rather than statics. This is the case

     because the normal level of a variable is viewed as historically determined and,

     therefore, not deducible from a static equilibrium model. Thomas (i99i)

     provides a revealing quote from a letter to J. B. Clark in this regard:

     I then [pre-i870] believed it was possible to have a coherent though

     abstract doctrine of economics in which competition was the only

     dominant force; and I then defined 'normal' as that which the

     undisturbed play of competition would bring about: and now I regard

     ? Royal Economic Society I993

    This content downloaded from 193.227.1.43 on Wed, 20 Apr 2016 21:11:29 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 Economics and the Self-Organisation Approach

    8/18

     1993] MARSHALL AND SELF ORGANSATON98

     that position as untenable from an abstract as well as from practical point

     of view (quoted in Thomas, IggI, p. io).

     This shift in Marshall's thinking has been missed by many economists, even

     though it is clearly stated on p. io6, footnote i in the Principles (4th edn).

     Modern economists often find the notion of a historically-determined 'normal'

     level of a variable a puzzling concept and are apt to dismiss it as an ad hoc

     construction. However, Marshall belonged to a Classical tradition where it was

     assumed that any competent economist would have a good understanding of

     the economic and social history of any period under consideration. Economic

     analysis could only be undertaken if historical and institutional features were

     taken as starting values. Thus, he devoted large parts of the main text of the

     Principles to historical and institutional discussion. Given that mathematical

     formalism was consigned to footnotes and appendices, we can only conclude,

     as Shove (I942) did, that he thought history to be more important.

     There has been a great deal of controversy concerning Marshall's treatment

     of history, largely because of his debates with Cunningham. However, as

     Maloney (I985) argues, this debate can only be understood in the context of

     the power struggle which was going on in Cambridge between economists,

     attempting to found an economic science, particularly through the extraction

     of economics from the moral sciences Tripos, and economic historians, who had

     been dominant in both teaching and research in the nineteenth century. The

     future was to show that Cunningham was correct in his fears that the economic

     science promoted by Marshall would lead to a deductive neoclassical economics

     which would sweep away the historical method. However, this was never

     Marshall's intention - the application of his science was conditional upon

     historical circumstance at all times and he always attempted, in a proximate

     manner, to allow for the historical reality of time irreversibility:

     While Jevons fastened his hopes to the division of labour, a break-up of

     science into separate branches or even separate sciences, Marshall's

     counter measure was rather by way of a combination of methods - not

     only history permeated by theory but theory... nourished, modified and

     illustrated by historical and contemporary fact. If any school of thought

     outside the Ricardian tradition set its mark on the Principles it was the

     Historical School, rather than the marginal utility school, that did so

     (Shove, I942, p. 309).

     What Marshall objected to was pure historicism, where all economic co-

     ordination is described in terms of institutional forces and change is viewed as

     the province of political forces with the historian's subjective preferences

     providing explanation. Instead, he argued that the systematic application of

     economic principles, suitably calibrated for particular historical circum-

     stances, provided a more scientific approach to understanding economic co-

     ordination. The longer sweep of history must be analysed in evolutionary

     terms. Describing and interpreting the minutiae of economic history was not

     for Marshall. Interestingly, Veblen (I990) had a similar position with regard

     to historicism to Marshall:

     K Royal Economic Society I993

    This content downloaded from 193.227.1.43 on Wed, 20 Apr 2016 21:11:29 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 Economics and the Self-Organisation Approach

    9/18

     982 THE ECONOMCJOURNAL [JULY

     the Historical School... have attempted an account of developmental

     sequence, but they have followed the lines of pre-Darwin speculations on

     development rather than lines which modern science would recognise as

     evolutionary. They have given a narrative survey of phenomena, not a

     genetic account of an unfolding process (Veblen, I990, p. 72).

     However, in his famous article, Veblen studiously ignores Marshall's

     preoccupation with time irreversibility and his related plea for an evolutionary

     dimension to economic science. Instead, Veblen concentrates upon the

     Marshall's static method because, like Cunningham, he feared, that its

     quantitative nature would lead to a false scientism in economics.

     Although many economic historians still blame Marshall for the near

     elimination of history from economics (Snooks, i99i)), not all economic

     historians have such a negative view of Marshall. Rostow (i989), as we have

     seen, offers an example of an economic historian who understands clearly

     Marshall's commitment to incorporating time irreversibility into economics.

     Nonetheless, Marshall has been criticised by some evolutionary economists for

     engaging in speculation rather than actual analysis of evolutionary processes

     (Thomas, I99I). However, Marshall was all too aware that no evolutionary

     economics could be possible until time irreversibility was properly understood.

     III. GEORGESCU-ROEGEN AND THE ENTROPY LAW

     It can be argued that Marshall's vision of an economic science which could deal

     with time irreversibility and evolutionary change did not really begin to

     materialise until Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen's (I97I; 1976) consideration of

     economic processes in thermodynamic terms:

     Mechanics distinguishes only mass, speed, and position, on which it bases

     the concept of kinetic and potential energy. The result is that mechanics

     reduces any process to locomotion and a change in the distribution of

     energy. The constancy of total mechanical energy and the constancy of

     mass are the earliest principles of conservation recognised by science. A

     few careful economists, such as Marshall, did observe that man can create

     neither matter nor energy. But in doing so, they apparently had in mind

     only the mechanical principles of conservation, for they immediately added

     that man can nevertheless produce utilities by moving and rearranging

     matter. This viewpoint ignores a most important issue: how can man do

     the moving? For anyone who remains at the level of mechanical

     phenomena, every bit of mechanical energy which enters a process must

     come out in exactly the same quantity and quality. Locomotion cannot alter

     either (Georgescu-Roegen, 1976, p. 6).

     Thus, Georgescu-Roegen argues that Marshall did not appreciate the

     importance of invoking the second law of thermodynamics to provide support for

     his arguments concerning time irreversibility in economic systems. Of course,

     this is not surprising given that, in Marshall's time, there was only

     thermodynamics of the equilibrium variety, with its gloomy prediction of an

     irreversible tendency to maximal disorder in systems. This would have hardly

     ? Royal Economic Society 1993

    This content downloaded from 193.227.1.43 on Wed, 20 Apr 2016 21:11:29 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 Economics and the Self-Organisation Approach

    10/18

     I993] MARSHALL AND SELF-ORGANSATION 983

     seemed to him a fruitful basis for understanding the economic co-ordination he

     saw around him and the evolutionary process which economies seemed to

     experience, particularly given the powerful influence of Herbert Spencer upon

     his thinking (Hodgson, I993). Marshall was, of course, familiar with Jevons'

     (i 865) dismal application of the entropy law to economics in The Coal Question

     and duly ignored it in his Principles.

     Georgescu-Roegen takes a different view of the entropy law. He uses its time

     irreversible features to explain why time irreversibility must also be a feature

     of structures which can absorb free energy to offset the entropy process, thus,

     prevent rising disorder. Such structures do this as economically as possible:

     thermodynamics is at bottom a physics of economic value - as Carnot

     unwittingly set it going - and the Entropy Law is the most economic in

     nature of all natural laws (Georgescu-Roegen, I976, pp. 87-9).

     the Entropy Law is the taproot of economic scarcity (Georgescu-Roegen,

     I976, p. 9).

     However, time irreversibility in entropy-thwarting structures is not

     inevitable or complete; it is a matter of marginal costs and benefits as historical

     experience unfolds. All process can, in theory, be reversed if sufficient free

     energy is used. However, the rise in free energy cost necessary to arrest entropy

     growth is nonlinear and the resultant entropy barrier is such that some

     irreversibility must prevail. The economics of entropy also, of course, applies in

     the economic domain - economic structures are created with low entropy

     characteristics, they are used in an economising manner through time and they

     are scrapped when the opportunity cost of maintaining them becomes too high.

     Thus, in Georgescu-Roegen's view, Marshall's economics is a necessary

     consequence of the existence of the entropy law and cannot be intelligible from

     any other perspective. In particular, he emphasises that Marshall's economics

     makes no sense at all in a static neoclassical framework of perpetual motion

     machines.

     Although Georgescu-Roegen provides a thermodynamic basis for dealing

     with time irreversibility in economics, his main quest was to emphasise the

     finite nature of free energy in economic systems. Thus, he did not go on to

     provide a formal analytical framework within which the evolutionary dynamics

     of economic processes could be set. However, he did acknowledge that the

     entropy law implies evolutionary processes, given that, if structures cannot

     reverse easily, then they can only change by evolving. The evolutionary

     dimension of Georgescu-Roegen's energy-based economics was taken up by

     others, such as Boulding (I98I). However, it is fair to say that no consensus

     view has emerged from the energy/entropy perspective as to the precise nature

     of evolutionary dynamics in economic processes. Indeed, some evolutionary

     economists have found the approach to be unconvincing. In particular,

     Mirowski (I988), a member of the institutionalist school that has shown most

     interest in the approach, has expressed some doubts, reminiscent of previous

     institutionalist doubts concerning Marshall's evolutionism, about Georgescu-

     Roegen's work:

     ? Royal Economic Society I993

    This content downloaded from 193.227.1.43 on Wed, 20 Apr 2016 21:11:29 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 Economics and the Self-Organisation Approach

    11/18

     984 THEECONOMCJOURNALJULY

     Although he has periodically promised a work that would sketch the

     outlines of that new bioeconomics, no such tome has issued from his pen.

     Perhaps more disappointingly, Georgescu-Roegen often has seemed to

     pull his punches, never extending his critiques to their most devastating

     conclusions (Mirowski, i988, p. 825).

     However, Georgescu-Roegen's (I984) tribute to the long neglected work of

     Herman Heinrich Gossen seems to refute Mirowski's criticism. He makes it

     very clear as to why he feels that time irreversibility dismantles neoclassical

     economics entirely and, also, why the contribution of Marshall was not a

     narrow neoclassical one:

     Marshall's aim was to show how important novelties make their way into

     the system, a very important part of economic evolution. It is for this

     reason that Marshall s argument (in contrast to that of Hicks and

     Lundberg) was fully dialectical, as is best seen in his notions of short and

     long periods. It was by the same method that Marshall proved the

     irreversibility of time, an issue that still puzzles some of the most illustrious

     physicists (Georgescu-Roegen, I984, p. I 4).

     What this paper also makes clear is that the 'conundrum as to why his

     criticisms have not simply been extended to the neoclassical concept of utility'

     (Mirowski, I 988, p. 826) is not a conundrum at all. The concept of utility used

     is not a strictly neoclassical one: Georgescu-Roegen's subscribes to a Gossenian,

     not a Jevonian, view of utility maximisation. The latter neglects time, the

     former incorporates time and can deal, explicitly, with time irreversibility and

     evolutionary change. Here we get another link with Marshall: Gossen is cited

     twice by Marshall in successive editions of his Principles along with Jevons.

     Jevons' utilitarianism is questioned, Gossen's is not.

     Georgescu-Roegen saw the orthodox economist's neglect of time irre-

     versibility as a much more serious deficiency than neoclassical thinking about

     optimisation. As Lozada (i 99 i) has pointed out, Georgescu-Roegen is strongly

     opposed to statistical mechanics of the Boltzmann/Newton variety in

     modelling dynamics, both in the natural sciences and in economics, and, again,

     adopts a position similar to Marshall:

     Marshall's conception of economic change as 'organic growth' almost

     certainly explains why he never developed a mathematical theory of

     economic dynamics (Shove, I942, p. 3I2).

     There is little doubt that Georgescu-Roegen believes, like Marshall did, that a

     formal representation of economising behaviour can still be of use in time

     irreversible contexts. Neoclassical formalism is not viewed as inadmissible per se

     but simply misapplied when set in non-existent, timeless equilibrium situations.

     In developing a new bio-economics, he confronted the same problem which

     had troubled Marshall, evolutionary biology could still not provide a formal

     basis to understand the unfolding of historical processes in economic contexts.

     In the i 960s and I 970s, when Georgescu-Roegen was making his most

     prominent contributions, biologists were only beginning to consider how non-

     (? Royal Economic Society I993

    This content downloaded from 193.227.1.43 on Wed, 20 Apr 2016 21:11:29 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 Economics and the Self-Organisation Approach

    12/18

     I993] MARSHALL AND SELF-ORGANISATION 985

     equilibrium thermodynamics could be applied, formally, in evolutionary

     biology, through a radical reorientation of statistical mechanics. Georgescu-

     Roegen, like Marshall, was ahead of his time.

     IV SELF-ORGANSATION AND ORGANSATIONAL ECOLOGY

     Since the late I 940S, Ilya Prigogine, along with a number of co-researchers at

     the Solvay Institute in Brussels have been pioneers in the application of non-

     equilibrium thermodynamics to understand the behaviour of structures

     considered to be 'dissipative' in character (see Prigogine and Stengers, I984;

     Nicholis and Prigogine, I977). Since all types of structure, whether chemical,

     biological or socio-economic, include dissipative examples in the face of the

     entropy law, Prigogine and his associates lay claim to have discovered a general

     scientific paradigm, capable of displacing the prevailing mechanical approach

     to dynamics in the natural and social sciences. Prigogine challenges

     conventional attempts to model processes as 'clockwork' mechanisms that obey

     timeless functional laws and are discoverable using a reductionist experimental

     method. However, he also attacks the kind of thermodynamics developed in the

     nineteenth century, characterising all structure as tending irreversibly towards

     a thermodynamic equilibrium state of maximum disorder. This 'heat death'

     view, Prigogine argues, had a profoundly pessimistic effect, in both science and

     art, which has lingered on up to the present day.

     In Prigogine's view, there are many examples, both in the natural and social

     worlds, which contradict both the static mechanical and the thermodynamic

     disordering notions of process. Processes at all levels, he argues, often seem to

     be characterised by increasing, not static or decreasing organisation. Dissipative

     structures, far from thermodynamic equilibrium, are able to achieve a degree

     of' self-organisation' (or autopoiesis) which enables them to export entropy and

     import free energy to maintain themselves and, in the biological domain, to

     facilitate development and reproduction. Thus, the irreversibility implied by

     the entropy law is -countered by organisation, which leads to the formation of

     complex structure that also contains irreversible features. Because of the

     entropy law, a structure must acquire a degree of inflexibility in a spatial sense

     and a degree of irreversibility in a temporal case. Consequently, a dissipative

     structure cannot always go into reverse in the face exogenous shocks, as is the

     case in mechanical models, it may have to either evolve or face destruction.

     Prigogine defines a dissipative structure as a thermodynamic system, whose

     behaviour is determined by its boundary conditions, in contrast to what he

     defines as a dynamic system which is determined by its initial conditions.

     Thermodynamic systems are open, yet partially closed by boundary conditions.

     The exportation of entropy alters the boundary conditions and creates an

     'entropy barrier' (time irreversibility) which ensures that past history

     influences the future behaviour of the structure. Such a dissipative structure

     can only be understood macroscopically because it contains initial conditions

     which are random. Only structures which are dynamic, with non-random

     initial conditions, can be analysed microscopically.

     ( Royal Economic Society I993

    This content downloaded from 193.227.1.43 on Wed, 20 Apr 2016 21:11:29 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 Economics and the Self-Organisation Approach

    13/18

     986 THEECONOMCJOURNALJULY

     Prigogine s characterisation of structure and process echoes Georgescu-

     Roegen s independently developed energy/entropy approach. However,

     Prigogine's priority has been to seek an understanding of the development of

     organisation and attendant complexity in systems. Although this has been very

     successful in chemical applications, Brooks and Wiley (I986) argue that the

     Prigoginian approach to self-organisation is inadequate in biological and, by

     inference, socio-economic contexts. By identifying a state of maximum entropy

     with a state of minimum information, they develop a self-organisation

     approach suitable for biological application by emphasising information flow

     rather than energy flow. Increasing complexity is viewed as inducing a rise in

     entropy, internally, in a dissipative structure. This tendency is not degenerative

     because of the parallel increase in organisation, which requires increasing

     numbers of information connections. Organisation is hierarchical, so in-

     formation becomes embedded in structure. Thus, a biological system is affected

     by its past history for developmental reasons. Initial historical conditions

     matter as well as externally-imposed conditions, stressed by Prigogine.

     There is still controversy in evolutionary biology as to the validity of the

     applying the entropy law in an informational context. However, as Wicken

     (i 986) stresses, this is largely a semantic debate as to whether the term

     'entropy' should be used to describe 'complexity'. As Dyke (I992) points out,

     this debate should not be allowed to diminish in importance the fact that a

     general entropy-like irreversible tendency has been discovered which can be

     used to understand the dynamics of all types of self-organised systems. There is

     little doubt that, in socio-economic contexts, informational considerations are

     even more important than they are in biological contexts (see Clark, i99i, for

     an assessment of the relevance of the Brooks/Wiley approach for economics).

     Indeed, the independent studies of socio-economic evolution by mathematical

     sociologists, Hannan and Freeman (i 989), in the organisational ecology

     tradition, identify similar processes to those identified by Brooks and Wiley

     (I986).

     Once we de-emphasise energy/entropy processes in favour of information/

     complexity processes in self-organising systems we move away from the insights

     of Georgescu-Roegen (I97I) but, at the same time, we move closer to the

     intuitions of Marshall concerning organisational behaviour. The interaction of

     information (or knowledge) and organisation is a central element in Marshall's

     economics, although widely unacknowledged as such:

     Capital consists in a great part of knowledge and organisation; and of this

     some part is private property and other part is not. Knowledge is our most

     powerful engine of production; it enables us to subdue Nature and force

     her to satisfy our wants. Organisation aids knowledge; it has many forms,

     that of various businesses in the same trade, that of various trades

     relatively to one another, and that of the State providing security for all

     and help for many (Marshall, gth edn, pp. I38-9).

     Loasby (i 990) explains how Marshall saw increased organisation and greater

     complexity (through the division of labour) as complementary and heavily

     ? Royal Economic Society I993

    This content downloaded from 193.227.1.43 on Wed, 20 Apr 2016 21:11:29 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 Economics and the Self-Organisation Approach

    14/18

     I993] MARSHALL AND SELF-ORGANISATION 987

     influenced by the availability of knowledge. He argues that the importance of

     knowledge in Marshall's thinking has been largely ignored. Loasby (I990)

     emphasises the distinctiveness of Marshall's approach, in comparison with

     conventional treatments of knowledge in economics, and points to its similarity

     to the Austrian treatment of knowledge. Both are juxtaposed against the

     conventional neoclassical view:

     Jevons' definition of 'the economic problem' which has become the

     commonplace of microeconomic textbooks, ignores the growth of

     knowledge; indeed it ignores the location of knowledge. It is the definition

     of a planning problem, subsequent analysis of which not surprisingly leads

     to the isomorphism of perfect competition and perfect planning. It is

     remarkable how few of our cleverest economists have been able to see that

     this isomorphism demonstrates the irrelevance of both (Loasby, I990,

     Pp . 5-6 .

     Marshall offers a multi-faceted vision of organisational interactions in the

     economic system and they form an essential basis for his arguments concerning

     increasing returns and the related historicalness, or time irreversibility, of long

     run supply curves. The notion of a self-organisational process was clearly

     formed in Marshall's mind:

     The increased subdivision of functions, or 'differentiation', as it is called,

     manifests itself with regard to industry in such forms as the division of

     labour, and the development of specialised skill, knowledge and

     machinery: while 'integration', that is, as growing intimacy and firmness

     of the connections between the separate parts of the industrial organism,

     shows itself in such forms as the increase of security of commercial credit,

     and of the means and habits of communication by sea and road, by

     railway and telegraph, by post and printing-press (Marshall, 7th edn,

     p 24 .

     The similarity of such depictions of organisational development to those found

     in both Brooks and Wiley (I986) and Hannah? and Freeman (I989) is not

     surprising given that Marshall was acutely aware of the socio-economic

     relevance of organisational analogies drawn from biology:

     economists have, in their turn, owed much to the many profound

     analogies which have been discovered between social and especially

     industrial organisation on the one side and the physical organisation of the

     higher animals on the other (Marshall, 7th edn, p. 24I).

     A key aspect of both the self-organisation and organisational ecology

     approaches is the prediction that system growth is nonlinearly density

     dependent. Hannah and Freeman (i 989) offer persuasive empirical support for

     this prediction in various socio-economic contexts. Marshall's argument

     concerning economies of scale in the long period also emphasises organisational

     factors:

     The law of increasing return may be worded thus: an increase of labour and

     capital leads generally to improved organization which increases the

     efficiency of the work of labour and capital (Marshall, 7th edn, p. 318).

     C Royal Economic Society I993

    This content downloaded from 193.227.1.43 on Wed, 20 Apr 2016 21:11:29 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 Economics and the Self-Organisation Approach

    15/18

     988 THE ECONOMCJOURNAL [JULY

     This 'law' can be viewed as a density dependence proposition, although

     Marshall did not, of course, operationalise it terms of the typical nonlinear

     logistic specification favoured by Hannan and Freeman (i989). However, he

     was certainly aware of the fact that scale economies would be most marked at

     low densities and that they would peter out at high densities:

     In turning... wool into blankets [in an old country], an increase in the

     volume of production brings some new economies, but not many; ... any

     new economies are more likely to be the result of new inventions than of

     improved organisation. In a country however in which the blanket trade

     is but slightly developed, these latter may be important; and it then may

     happen that an increase in the production of blankets diminishes the

     proportionate difficulty of manufacturing... and ... where the cost of raw

     materials counts for little ... the law of increasing returns acts almost

     unopposed (Marshall, 7th edn, p. 3I9).

     Once we re-orientate our thinking in terms of self-organisational systems

     which develop, survive and change in ways which can be modelled using non-

     equilibrium thermodynamic constructs, we can see that the neoclassical

     economist s notion of equilibrium is an impossible full-information steady state.

     Marshall's steady states are different, they are homeostatic states in the

     presence of some degree of time irreversibility, induced by the forces of life and

     decay which we can now formalise in non-equilibrium thermodynamic terms.

     Such steady states are not states of imperfect information but states where

     information is greater than zero, as evidenced by the existence of irreversible

     processes. In biological and socio-economic circumstances, identified by Brooks

     arid Wiley (i986), where there is a mixture of dynamic and non-equilibrium

     thermodynamic forces at work, the field force equilibrium notion can be used

     to capture homeostasis, if non-equilibrium abstractions, such as Marshall's

     'representative' firm (Moss, i984), are derived to avoid dealing with the

     nonlinear ranges that an actual firm's parameters can enter. Marshall

     preferred to deal with the latter on a case by case basis rather than to allow

     nonlinearities, which he could not accommodate, to enter his mathematical

     framework. He was clearly dissatisfied with such a limited framework, but it

     still enabled him to depict states much more comparable to those to be derived

     using the self-organisational approach of the future, rather than those of

     equilibrium neoclassical economics.

     The self-organisation approach in the natural sciences has shown us that

     order can exist where entropy-like time irreversibility prevails. Thus, we can,

     as biologists and chemists do routinely, generate tractable nonlinear models of

     dynamic processes applying, in the economic case, Marshallian-style ceteris

     paribus assumptions and Marshallian thinking about marginalist optimisation

     and opportunity cost in the use of time. Because such processes always have

     chaotic potential, empirical studies of them must always be pragmatic and

     conducted with a fully-informed understanding of the historical and systemic

     features of the economic process under consideration. Hannan and Freeman

     (I989) provide an example of this kind of background preparation, which

     ? Royal Economic Society I993

    This content downloaded from 193.227.1.43 on Wed, 20 Apr 2016 21:11:29 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 Economics and the Self-Organisation Approach

    16/18

     I993] MARSHALL AND SELF-ORGANISATION 989

     economists might wish to follow in certain respects. They also show how self-

     organising behaviour in socio-economic contexts seems to be much less subject

     to chaotic outcomes at the macroscopic level than in chemical or biological

     contexts. Inertial forces are found to be extremely powerful in the cases which

     they consider. Marshall's natura non facit saltum seems to apply.

     V BACK TO THE FUTURE?

     Today, some of our most eminent mainstream economic theorists are beginning

     to see evolutionary economics as the future:

     History dependence stares us in the face but it is not the stuff of pure

     theory... Evolutionary theories are beginning to flourish, and they are not

     the sort of theories we have had hitherto ... But while there will be work for

     the computer scientist, I very much doubt that economists will be able to

     establish general propositions in any but very special examples (Hahn,

     I99I, p. 48).

     However, this rather pessimistic view is not derived from the largely non-

     technical literature on evolutionary economics but, instead, from the work of

     mathematicians interested in nonlinear dynamics who have found chaotic

     complexity to be a feature of even very simple nonlinear dynamic systems.

     Computer simulation offers the only route to discover the hidden attractors to

     which chaotic dynamics tend. However, even though chaotic systems with

     determinate, but unpredictable, features are of interest to economists, a cursory

     glance at the historical dynamics of actual economic variables tells us that,

     despite the fact that we observe a great deal of chaotic-like behaviour at the

     microscopic level, there is also much order and predicability at the macroscopic

     level at any point in time. In other words, it is not axiomatic that the complex

     chaotic potential of economic dynamics renders them unanalysable using

     theoretical constructs. The order we see and, indeed, have sometimes modelled

     successfully using simple linear models and methods, ought to be amenable to

     theoretical expression.

     Hahn (i 99 i) is correct in his view that chaotic dynamics offer an impossible

     context for the kind of theorising to which he is accustomed but it does not

     necessarily follow that economic processes are, in fact, very chaotic, despite

     their chaotic potential. In socio-economic systems, many of the homeostatic

     mechanisms we observe are designed, explicitly, to prevent chaotic dynamics

     from occurring. This has been understood intuitively by many economists in

     the past, a good recent example being Leijonhufvud (I98I) with his 'corridor

     hypothesis'. With historical data, it is possible to capture these 'well-behaved'

     nonlinear economic processes in statistical form and to assign probabilities as

     to the limits of homeostatic mechanisms in absorbing exogenous shocks, as

     well as the capacity of structures to continue to take opportunities presented on

     their boundaries. If we view 'dissipative structures' in the economic domain as

     inertially forward-looking, rather than reactive, much in the manner of

     Marshall, then density dependent models, which can be stable over long

     K Royal Economic Society I993

    This content downloaded from 193.227.1.43 on Wed, 20 Apr 2016 21:11:29 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 Economics and the Self-Organisation Approach

    17/18

     99 THEECONOMCJOURNALJULY

     periods, can be estimated econometrically. In economics, we are privileged in

     that we can often measure the informational complexity embodied in economic

     organisation in terms of monetary valuation. Provided irreversibility and

     reproducibility of organisation are in evidence to some degree, then we can

     discover statistical representations of such processes.

     However, as economists, there is a limit to the extent that we can probe into

     the evolutionary change which accompanies time irreversibility in self-

     organising systems. We can make some assessment as to the influence of

     historical conditions on the future of an economic structure from the statistical

     evidence we have (see, for example, Foster, I992). We can be alerted to the fact

     that, for example, over-faithful reproducibility and insufficient absorption of

     micro-novelty is rendering an economic structure increasingly vulnerable to

     being selected out. However, the non-equilibrium thermodynamical approach

     offers us only a statistical viewfinder set to observe the stable interplay of self-

     organisation and entropy-like processes, not evolutionary nonlinearities,

     imperfectly accounted for in the homeostatic mechanisms of the economic

     structures which we choose to study. Like Marshall we must be pragmatic

     about such nonlinearities, allowing for non-economic influences, such as

     political instabilities, in qualitative ways.

     In conclusion, the self-organisation approach, suitably adapted to the

     economic context, seems to offer scientific foundations for a post-Marshallian

     re-orientation of economics. The parallels with Marshall s economics have

     been explored and it has been argued that his insights concerning economic

     processes are highly compatible with this new approach. In attempting to deal

     with time irreversibility, Marshall devised methods which were difficult to

     digest by both neoclassical economists and their evolutionary opponents. It is

     only now that we can see how remarkably far-sighted he was. Because of this,

     his writings still offer one of the best starting points in any attempt to

     understand how the self-organisation approach can be adapted for use in

     economics. One suspects that Marshall would have -been disappointed with the

     slowness with which economics has moved beyond his 'backbone' mechanical

     approach. However, he would have also been capable of understanding why

     ideological and ethical factors have had such a powerful influence on the

     direction and extent of scientific development in economics.

     University of Queensland

     Date of receipt offinal typescript: September I992

     REFERENCES

     Arrow, K. J. (1 988). 'Workshop on the economy as an evolving complex system: summary.' In The Economy

     as an Evolving Complex System (ed. P. W. Anderson, K. J. Arrow and D. Pines), pp. 275-82. Redwood

     City: Addison Wesley.

     Arthur, W. B. (i988). 'Self reinforcing mechanisms in economics.' In The Economy as an Evolving Complex

     System (ed. P. W. Anderson, K. J. Arrow and D. Pines), pp. 9-32. Redwood City: Addison Wesley.

     Boulding, K. E. (I98I). Evolutionary Economics. London: Sage.

     Brooks, D. R. and Wiley, E. 0. (I986). Evolution as Entropy: Toward a Unified Theory of Biology. Chicago:

     Chicago University Press.

     (D Royal Economic Society I993

    This content downloaded from 193.227.1.43 on Wed, 20 Apr 2016 21:11:29 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/18/2019 Economics and the Self-Organisation Approach

    18/18

     I993] MARSHALL AND SELF ORGANSATON99

     Clark, N. (i99i). 'Organisation and information in the evolution of economic systems.' In Evolutionary

     Theories of Economic and Technological Change (ed. P. P. Saviotti and S. Metcalfe). London: Harwood

     Press.

     Currie, M. and Steedman, I. (I990). Wrestling with Time. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

     Debreu, G. (I991). 'The mathematization of economics.' American Economic Review, vol. 8I, pp. I-7.

     David, P. (i 988). 'Putting the past into the future of economics.' Institute for Mathematical Studies in the

     Social Sciences, Stanford University, Technical Report No. 533.

     Dosi, G. and Metcalfe, J. S. (i 99 I). 'On some notions of irreversibility in economics.' In Evolutionary Theories

     of Economic and Technological Change (ed. P. P. Saviotti and J. S. Metcalfe). London: Harwood Press.

     Dyke, C. (I992). From entropy to economy: a thorny path. Advances in Human Ecology, vol. I, pp. I49-76.

     Foster, J. (i987). Evolutionary Macroeconomics. London: Allen and Unwin.

     Foster, J. (I 992). 'The determination of Sterling M3: an evolutionary macroeconomic approach.' ECONOMIC

     JOURNAL, vol. I02, pp. 48I-96.

     Georgescu-Roegen, N. (I97I). The Entropy Law and the Economic Process. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard

     University Press.

     Georgescu-Roegen, N. (I976). Energy and Economic Myths: Institutional and Analytical Economic Essays. New

     York: Pergamon.

     Georgescu-Roegen, N. (i 984). 'Time and value in economics and in Gossen's system.' Mimeo (December).

     Hannan, M. T. and Freeman, J. (i 989). Organisational Ecology. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

     Hahn, F. (i99I). 'The next hundred years.' ECONOMIC JOURNAL, vol. 10I, pp. 47-5I.

     Hodgson, G. M. (I993). 'The mecca of Alfred Marshall.' ECONOMIC JOURNAL, vol. I03, pp. 406-I5.

     Jevons, S. (i865). The Coal Question. London: Macmillan.

     Leijonhufvud, A. (i98i). Information and Co-ordination: Essays in Macroeconomic Theory. Oxford: Oxford

     University Press.

     Loasby, B.J. (1978). 'Whatever happened to Marshall's Theory of Value?' Scottish Journal of Political

     Economy, vol. 25, pp. I-I2.

     Loasby, B.J. (I990). 'Knowledge and organisation: a post-Marshallian research programme.' Mimeo,

     Department of Economics, University of Stirling June).

     Lozada, G. A. ( I990). 'Georgescu-Roegen's critique of statistical mechanics revisited.' Mimeo, Energy and

     Resources Group, University of California, Berkeley (December).

     Maloney, J. (i985). Marshall, Orthodoxy and the Professionalization of Economics. Cambridge: Cambridge

     University Press.

     Marshall, A. (I898, I9I6, I920, i96i). Principles of Economics (4th, 7th, 8th and gth edns). London:

     Macmillan.

     Mirowski, P. (1 988). Energy and energetics in economic theory: a review essay. Journal of Economic Issues,

     vol. 22, pp. 8I I-32.

     Mirowski, P. (i99i). 'The when and how and why of mathematical expression in the history of economic

     analysis.' Journal of Economic Perspectives, vol. 5, pp. I47-57.

     Moss, S. (i984). 'The history of the theory of the firm from Marshall to Robinson and Chamberlin: the

     source of positivism in economics. Economica, vol. 5I, pp. 307-I8.

     Nicholis, G. and Prigogine, I. (i977). Self-Organisation in Non-equilibrium Systems: From Dissipative Structures to

     Order through Fluctuations. New York: John Wiley.

     Prigogine, I. and Stengers, I. (i984). Order Out of Chaos: Man's New Dialogue With Nature. London:

     Heinemann.

     Reisman, D. (I990). Alfred Marshall's Mission. New York: St Martin's.

     Rostow, W. (i989). 'Non-linear dynamics: implications for economics in historical perspective.' Paper

     presented to an International Symposium on Evolutionary Economics and Nonlinear Dynamics, I 6-I 9

     April i989, IC Institute, Austin, Texas.

     Schumpeter, J. A. (I 954). History of Economic Analysis. London: Allen Unwin.

     Samuelson, P. A. (I 946). Foundations of Economic Analysis. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

     Samuelson, P. A. (I972). 'What classical and neoclassical monetary theory really was.' Reprinted in The

     Collected Scientific Papers of Paul A. Samuelson, vol. III (ed. R. C. Merton). Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

     Shove, G. F. (I942). 'The place of Marshall's Principles in the development of economic theory.' ECONOMIC

     JOURNAL, vol. 52, pp. 294-329.

     Smith, A. (I986). The Wealth of Nations. London: Penguin.

     Snooks, G. D. (I99I). 'The lost dimension: economics without time.' Australian National University,

     Mimeo July).

     Thomas, B. (I99I). 'Alfred Marshall on economic biology.' Review of Political Economy, vol. 3, pp. I-I4.

     Veblen, T. B. (i 990). Why is economics not an evolutionary science? Quarterly Journal of Economics, vol. I 2,

     pp. 373-97. Reprinted in T. B. Veblen, The Place of Science in Modern Civilisation. London: Transaction.

     Wicken,J. S. (1 986). Evolutionary self organisation and entropic dissipation in biological and socioeconomic

     systems.' Journal of Social and Biological Structures, vol. 9, pp. 26I-73.

     -( Royal Economic Society I993