Econ 522 Economics of Law

44
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2012 Lecture 2

description

Econ 522 Economics of Law. Dan Quint Spring 2012 Lecture 2. Logistics. If you’re still trying to get into the class, get your name on the yellow pad TA sections begin this Friday “Fake homework” for Wednesday on website. Monday, we…. defined law and economics - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Transcript of Econ 522 Economics of Law

Page 1: Econ 522 Economics of Law

Econ 522Economics of Law

Dan Quint

Spring 2012

Lecture 2

Page 2: Econ 522 Economics of Law

2

If you’re still trying to get into the class, get your name on the yellow pad

TA sections begin this Friday

“Fake homework” for Wednesday on website

Logistics

Page 3: Econ 522 Economics of Law

3

defined law and economics

saw some brief history of the common law

and the civil law

and discussed ownership of dead whales

Monday, we…

Page 4: Econ 522 Economics of Law

4

what is efficiency?

is efficiency a good goal for the law?

Today: efficiency

Page 5: Econ 522 Economics of Law

5

What is“efficiency”?

Page 6: Econ 522 Economics of Law

6

a Pareto improvement is any change to the economy which leaves… everyone at least as well off, and someone strictly better off

example of a Pareto improvement your car is worth $3,000 to you, $4,000 to me I buy it for $3,500

an outcome is Pareto superior to another, or Pareto dominates it, if the second is a Pareto improvement over the first

First concept: Pareto improvement

Vilfredo Pareto(1848-1923)

Page 7: Econ 522 Economics of Law

7

Pareto improvements are “win-win” but most new laws create some winners and some losers so the Pareto criterion usually can’t tell us whether one policy is

“better” than another even the car example might not be a true Pareto-improvement

so we need another way to compare outcomes

Pareto superiority is not that useful a measure for evaluating a legal system

Page 8: Econ 522 Economics of Law

8

a Kaldor-Hicks improvement is any change to the economy which could be turned into a Pareto improvement with monetary transfers also called potential Pareto improvement

car example again your car is worth $3,000 to you and $4,000 to me government seizes your car and gives it to me

I’m better off, you’re worse off combined with me giving you $3,500, it’s a Pareto improvement so me getting your car is a Kaldor-Hicks improvement

a Kaldor-Hicks improvement may create winners and losers, but gains outweigh the losses I’m $4,000 better off, you’re $3,000 worse off, $4,000 > $3,000

Next concept: Kaldor-Hicks improvement

Page 9: Econ 522 Economics of Law

9

You and I are neighbors, you want to throw a party The party would make me $100 worse off… …and make you $50 better off… …and make each of your 30 guests $5 better off

Is the party a Pareto improvement? No – it makes you and your guests better off, makes me worse off

Is the party a Kaldor-Hicks improvement? Yes – because the party, combined with the appropriate money transfers,

would be a Pareto improvement (Example: you throw the party, you give me $40, each of your guests gives

me $3 – that’s a Pareto improvement)

Example

Page 10: Econ 522 Economics of Law

10

To check if something is a Kaldor-Hicks improvement, we can…

look for transfers that turn it into a Pareto-improvement…

…or, just count up the gains of the winners and the losses of the losers, and see which is bigger

a change in the economy is a Kaldor-Hicks improvement if the winners’ gains outweigh the losers’ losses if you have the party… I’m $100 worse off You’re $50 better off 30 guests are each $5 better off – $100 + $50 + 30 X $5 = $100 > 0 Gains outweigh losses, so party is a Kaldor-Hicks improvement

Page 11: Econ 522 Economics of Law

11

So…

A Kaldor-Hicks improvement is any change that“creates value…”

…where value is equated with willingness to pay We said the party made me $100 worse off We equated my disutility from you making noise with the amount

of money that would replace the inconvenience – if you threw the party and gave me $100, I’d be just as well off as before

By equating utility with money, we create a way to compare utility across individuals

Page 12: Econ 522 Economics of Law

12

we will call a change to the economy efficient if it is a Kaldor-Hicks improvement

we’ll say law A is more efficient than law B if moving from B to A is a Kaldor-Hicks improvement

and we’ll say a situation is efficient if there are no available Kaldor-Hicks improvements an efficient situation is when there’s no way to make some people

better off, without making some others worse off by more we’re already getting maximal value out of all available resources

Efficiency

Page 13: Econ 522 Economics of Law

13

Example: is it efficient for me to drive to work instead of taking the bus?

Bus to campus from where I live is free

Driving is more convenient, but costs me $1 (gas)

Driving also imposes costs on other people: there’s more traffic, less parking, more pollution Suppose when I drive to work, it makes 1,000 other people worse off by

$0.01 each

By driving to work, I create $11 of total costs

It’s efficient for me to drive to work if the benefit I get is more than $11 If the benefit is less than $11, it’s inefficient for me to drive

Page 14: Econ 522 Economics of Law

14

our definition of efficiency: actions are taken when total benefits outweigh total costs “goal” is to achieve all Kaldor-Hicks improvements

Ellickson: efficiency is “minimizing the objective sum of

(1) transaction costs, and

(2) deadweight losses arising from failures to exploit potential gains from trade”

Posner: “wealth maximization”

Polinsky: “Efficiency corresponds to ‘the size of the pie’”

Some other, similar measures

Page 15: Econ 522 Economics of Law

15

What forces lead to inefficiency

Page 16: Econ 522 Economics of Law

16

To see whether something’s efficient…

Compare gains to everyone in society (total social benefit)…

…to costs to everyone (total social costs)

Example we already saw (me driving to work): Total social cost = $1 (gas) + 1,000 X $0.01 = $11 Total social benefit = whatever I gain by driving to work So we just said: it’s efficient for me to drive to campus whenever

the value I get from driving is more than $11

Page 17: Econ 522 Economics of Law

17

But what do people actually do?

When people decide how to act…

…they consider the cost and benefit to themselves, not to everyone private benefit and private cost

Driving only costs me $1 so I’ll drive whenever benefit to me is more than $1

On days when value I get from driving is more than $1 but less than $11, I drive to work even though that’s inefficient

Page 18: Econ 522 Economics of Law

18

So externalities cause inefficiency

I’ll do something whenever private benefit > private cost

Efficiency depends on whether social benefit > social cost

If I was the only one affected by my choices, then social benefit = private benefit and social cost = private cost when I’m deciding which movie to watch on Netflix, nobody else is effected

by my choice, so my choice will be efficient

But when my choices affect other peoples’ payoffs… social benefit private benefit, or social cost private cost so actions I choose to take may not be efficient

Page 19: Econ 522 Economics of Law

19

A classic example of this: the Tragedy of the Commons

Hardin (1968), “The Tragedy of the Commons”

Picture a small fishing village on a lake The more fish I catch, the fewer

fish are left in the lake… …and the harder it is for everyone

else in the village to catch fish So my fishing imposes an

externality on everyone else So everyone ends up fishing

more than the efficient amount

Page 20: Econ 522 Economics of Law

20

Tragedy of the Commons – example

20 fishermen Cost of fishing is 8 fish per hour Notation

h = how many hours I fish H = combined hours everyone fishes H = hours everyone but me fishes

Fishermen catch 260 – H fish per hour

(a) What is the efficient level of fishing? How much utility does that give to each fisherman?

6.3 hours per day per fisherman; 793.8 fish/day

(b) Left to their own devices, how much will each person fish? How much utility will each person get?

12 hours per day per fisherman; 144 fish/day

Hours fishing, per day, per fisherman

Total fish caught

0 1263 9

“Maximum Sustainable Yield”

Efficient Level of Fishing

“Equilibrium” Level of Fishing

H (260 – H)

Page 21: Econ 522 Economics of Law

21

What’s going on here?

Fishing imposes a negative externality on other fishermen Each one ignores this externality when deciding how much to fish… …so they all end up fishing more than the efficient amount

Same thing happens with other communal resources Cattle grazing, whaling, overhunting, oyster beds Aristotle: “That which is common to the greatest number has the least

care bestowed upon it” Elinor Ostrom, who shared the 2009 Nobel Prize in Economics, studies

how different societies solve this problem

Positive externalities work the opposite way Activities which create positive externalities are naturally done less than

the efficient amount

Page 22: Econ 522 Economics of Law

22

Without some sort of regulation/intervention… Activities which impose a negative externality will be done more

than the efficient amount… …and activities which impose a positive externality will be done

less than the efficient amount

One idea we’ll see several times in this class:

if we want the law to lead to efficient outcomes,

we can try to design the law to eliminate externalities! “Internalization”

So externalities can lead to inefficiency

Page 23: Econ 522 Economics of Law

23

Other forces which lead to inefficiency

Page 24: Econ 522 Economics of Law

24

Cuban cigars Suppose I’d pay $15 each for Cohibas They cost $2 each to make, and another

$3 each to transport from Cuba to Madison Clearly, it’s efficient for me to smoke Cohibas But trade embargo on Cuba makes it illegal for me to buy them

Anything that prevents me from buying something I want can be a source of inefficiency One approach to property law: make it as easy as possible for

people to trade among themselves (This may seem like an obvious point; but then, there are lots of

things we’re not allowed to sell…)

Another thing that leads to inefficiency:barriers to trade

Page 25: Econ 522 Economics of Law

25

I value my free time at $40/hour

Working in a factory, I can build things worth $50/hour

Clearly, it’s efficient for me to work Each hour I work creates $10 of new value Doesn’t matter who gets it – it’s efficient for me to work

But if income tax is 25%, then it won’t happen Factory owner can’t pay me more than $50/hour But $50/hour pre-tax is only $37.50 after-tax… …and I’d rather stay home than earn $37.50 an hour So I don’t get hired, which is inefficient

Another thing that leads to inefficiency: taxes

Page 26: Econ 522 Economics of Law

26

This is a new BMW that’s been cut in half

Taxes distort behavior away from efficiency

Another example of taxes leading to inefficiency

Page 27: Econ 522 Economics of Law

27

CS

Profit

Example Demand for some good

given by P = 100 – Q Monopolist can produce

good for $40/unit Monopoly price is 70,

demand is 30 Deadweight loss is

inefficiency Customers willing to pay

more than marginal cost but unable to trade

Another thing that leads to inefficiency: monopoly

P* = 70P = 100 – Q

Q* = 30

MC = 40DWL

(or private information)

Page 28: Econ 522 Economics of Law

28

For example we just said taxes lead to inefficiency… …but without taxes, there’s be far too few public goods, which is also

inefficient we just said monopoly leads to inefficiency… …but we’ll study patents, which are legal monopolies used to get

companies to innovate

But also, we’ve defined “efficient”, but we haven’t claimed that “efficient = good”

Which brings us to…

But, saying these things lead to inefficiency doesn’t automatically mean they’re bad

Page 29: Econ 522 Economics of Law

29

Is efficiency a good goal for the law?

Page 30: Econ 522 Economics of Law

30

positive statements are statements of fact can be descriptive: “in 2007, U.S. GDP was $13.8 trillion” can be theoretical predictions: “if prices rise, demand will fall” “economics of what is”

normative statements contain value judgments for example, “less inequality is better” or, “government should encourage innovation” “economics of what ought to be”

Important distinction: positive versus normative economics

Page 31: Econ 522 Economics of Law

31

Predicting behavior, and outcomes, that follow from a law or legal system is positive economics “Law X will lead to more car accidents than law Y” “Law X will lead to more efficient outcomes than law Y”

But in the background, we’d like some sense of what is the normative goal of the legal system “Law X is better than law Y”

One candidate for that normative goal is efficiency

Most of this class will be positive analysis

Page 32: Econ 522 Economics of Law

32

“The central question [in this book]… is a simple one: what set of rules and institutions maximize the size of the pie? What legal rules are economically efficient?

There are at least three reasons why that is the question we ask.

The first is that while economic efficiency… is not the only thing that matters to human beings, it is something that matters quite a lot to most human beings.

The second reason is that there is evidence that considerable parts of the legal system we live in can be explained as tools to generate efficient outcomes… It is a lot easier to make sense out of a tool if you know what it is designed to do.

A final reason is that figuring out what rules lead to… efficient outcomes is one of the things economists know how to do –

and when you have a hammer, everything looks like a nail.”

- Friedman, Law’s Order, p. 312

Friedman gives a few arguments for studying efficiency

Page 33: Econ 522 Economics of Law

33

This answers the question, “Why is it interesting to study efficiency?”

Not the question, “Should the law be designed with the goal of achieving efficiency?”

To answer this latter question…

But…

Page 34: Econ 522 Economics of Law

34

Richard Posner (1980), The Ethical and Political Basis of Efficiency Norm in Common Law Adjudication

Starts with the observation: if you buy a lottery ticket and don’t win anything, you can’t complain

Imagine before we all started driving, everyone in the world got together and negotiated a liability rule for traffic accidents

If one rule is more efficient than another, we’d all vote for that rule ex-ante – ex-ante consent

Posner gives us one argument why the law should aim to be efficient

Page 35: Econ 522 Economics of Law

35

Suppose there are two candidate rules for accident liability One favors pedestrians, one favors drivers The one favoring car drivers is more efficient

Posner’s point: before we know who we’ll be, everyone would unanimously agree to the second rule

Ex-ante consent – simple example

-40-60-20Negligence rule

-500-100Strict liability rule

Expected payoff if you don’t know which one

you’ll be

Expected payoff,

pedestrians

Expected payoff, drivers

Page 36: Econ 522 Economics of Law

36

People without cars would prefer a less efficient system if it meant drivers were responsible

Posner deals with heterogeneity with a different example

Landlord-friendly versus tenant-friendly laws Might think tenants would prefer pro-tenant laws But rents are determined competitively If laws become more tenant-friendly, rents might go up to compensate And if tenant-friendly law is less efficient, it could make both sides

worse off!

Things are a little more complicated…

Page 37: Econ 522 Economics of Law

37

Suppose tenants get $1000 value from apartment, minus rent Landlords pay $100 for heat, $600 in other costs Without this law, tenants would pay for their own heat They’d heat apartment less, get $980 value and pay $60 for heat Might think tenants would prefer inefficient tenant-friendly law… But rents are set competitively, would go up to compensate… So both landlords and tenants do better under the old law!

Example: new law requiring landlords to pay for their tenants’ heat

760 – 600= 160

980 – 60 – 760= 160

rent – 600980 – 60 – rentTenant pays for heat

850 – 600 – 100= 150

1000 – 850= 150

rent – 600 – 1001000 – rentLandlord pays for heat

LandlordsTenantsLandlords’

payoffsTenants’ payoffs

Page 38: Econ 522 Economics of Law

38

Posner’s basic argument: if we choose the most efficient legal system, everyone is “compensated ex-ante” for the choice, and should willingly accept the outcome they get

Of course, all this consent is hypothetical…

…and it does have certain limitations

Ex-ante consent, ex-ante compensation

Page 39: Econ 522 Economics of Law

39

The “lottery ticket” analogy requires risk neutrality 50% chance at $1,000,000 is just as good as 50% chance at

$900,000 and 50% chance at $100,000 If $100,000 is “worth more to you” when you’re broke than when

you already have $900,000, this argument doesn’t work

Counterpoint to Posner: Hammond (1982) Efficiency is really a special case of utilitarianism, and subject to

the same limitations “Value” = “willingness to pay” $1 worth the same to everyone

Limitations to Posner’s argument

Page 40: Econ 522 Economics of Law

40

efficiency is not equity efficiency is not fairness efficiency is not maximizing happiness

“Suppose that pituitary extract is in very short supply… and is therefore very expensive. A poor family has a child who will be a dwarf if he doesn’t get some of the extract, but the family cannot afford the price [or borrow the money].

A rich family has a child who will grow to normal height, but the extract will add a few inches more, and his parents decide to buy it for him.

In the sense of value used in this book, the pituitary extract is more valuable to the rich family… because value is measured by willingness to pay, but the extract would confer greater happiness in the hands of the poor family.”

- Posner, Economic Analysis of Law

This highlights some of the things efficiency is not

Page 41: Econ 522 Economics of Law

41

Cooter and Ulen (textbook ch. 1)

Efficiency should not necessarily be the goal of society

But efficiency should be the goal of the legal system

If redistribution is desirable, it’s better to make the legal system efficient, and address distribution through taxes Cooter and Ulen offer four reasons why the tax system is a better

way to redistribute wealth than the legal system

A more pragmatic defense of efficiency as a goal for the law

Page 42: Econ 522 Economics of Law

42

1. Taxes can target “rich” and “poor” more precisely than the legal system can

2. Distributional effects of legal changes are harder to predict

3. Lawyers are more expensive than accountants

4. More narrowly-targeted taxes cause greater distortion than broad-based taxes

Four reasons the tax system is a better way to redistribute wealth than the legal system

Page 43: Econ 522 Economics of Law

43

We’ve seen two arguments in favor Posner: it’s what we all would have agreed on ex-ante C&U: if you want to redistribute, it’s better to do it through taxes

But there are definitely some problems with efficiency Distribution matters; not everything is monetizable; people might care

about procedural fairness

My take In this class, we’ll mostly focus on the positive questions But in the background, I think of efficiency as a “pretty good”, but

definitely imperfect, measure of “goodness”

So, summing up… is efficiency a good goal for the law?

Page 44: Econ 522 Economics of Law

44

One argument from C&U for why law should focus on efficiency, redistribution should be done through taxes:

“narrow taxes cause more distortion than broad taxes” Wednesday, we’ll work through an example of this “Optional homework problem”

If you want to read ahead, look atRonald Coase, “The Problem of Social Cost”(although we probably won’t get to Coase till Wednesday)

See me if you’re not yet registered

For Monday…

That’s it for today – see you next week