Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

37
149 Difficult Questions for Pro-Choice Persons Question 1. I assume that you think that we human beings have human rights. Your position, in fact, is that among the rights a human being has is the right to control one's reproduction. Well, at what point do you think that a human being, with human rights, comes into existence? Is it at birth, or earlier? I could ask the question more concretely of you yourself: you have human rights—did you acquire them only when you were born? Surely you must have had them earlier, since premature babies are human beings with human rights, and the only difference between, say, a baby who is born prematurely by two weeks, and one who is still in the womb two weeks before term, is that the one is inside its mother, and the other is not; and the one that is inside, if taken out, will live just as much as the one born prematurely. Then is it at what is called "viability" that you acquired human rights, that is, when you were capable of remaining alive, if you were taken out of your mother? Or do you think it happened when your brain waves were first detectable (at about 6 weeks after conception)? For the moment, I'll put aside the obvious objections to these criteria; for the question I really wish to pursue is the following. Whatever answer you give—viability, brain waves, whatever--Why don't you oppose abortion after this time? I don't mean, simply, "why don't you refrain from seeking an abortion for yourself, or for a friend, after that time". I mean, rather, "why do you do nothing to stop those human beings with human rights--as you have concede--from being killed"? It is your view that, after viability, say, the fetus is a human being with human rights, equal in dignity and importance to you and me. There are 150,000 abortions in this (The Augustine Club, Columbia University, NY, 1990)

description

Philosophy

Transcript of Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

Page 1: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

149

Difficult Questions for Pro-Choice Persons

Question 1.

I assume that you think that we human beings have human rights. Your position, in fact, is that

among the rights a human being has is the right to control one's reproduction. Well, at what point

do you think that a human being, with human rights, comes into existence? Is it at birth, or earlier?

I could ask the question more concretely of you yourself: you have human rights—did

you acquire them only when you were born? Surely you must have had them earlier, since

premature babies are human beings with human rights, and the only difference between, say, a

baby who is born prematurely by two weeks, and one who is still in the womb two weeks before

term, is that the one is inside its mother, and the other is not; and the one that is inside, if taken

out, will live just as much as the one born prematurely.

Then is it at what is called "viability" that you acquired human rights, that is, when you

were capable of remaining alive, if you were taken out of your mother? Or do you think it

happened when your brain waves were first detectable (at about 6 weeks after conception)?

For the moment, I'll put aside the obvious objections to these criteria; for the question I

really wish to pursue is the following. Whatever answer you give—viability, brain waves,

whatever--Why don't you oppose abortion after this time? I don't mean, simply, "why don't you

refrain from seeking an abortion for yourself, or for a friend, after that time". I mean, rather, "why

do you do nothing to stop those human beings with human rights--as you have concede--from

being killed"? It is your view that, after viability, say, the fetus is a human being with human

rights, equal in dignity and importance to you and me. There are 150,000 abortions in this

(The Augustine Club, Columbia University, NY, 1990)

Page 2: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

150

country each year after viability. This is, on your account, a massive violation of human rights.

Why do you do nothing at all to stop this? You are pro-choice, yes, but you are pro-choice, I

presume, only for abortions which are not, on your account, violations of human rights.

Do you do nothing because you do not wish to impose your views on others? But of

course then I could ask of you why you ever act morally, since that will always require that you

impose your views? When you act against racism, for example, you similarly impose your view on

others who disagree. Is it that you are uncertain—you merely believe abortion is wrong after

viability, but you have little confidence in your belief? I wonder whether you truly have little

confidence in it—and, if you do, whether you are at all justified in having little confidence. And I

would note, furthermore, that this "lack of confidence" of yours, and this—shall we say—paralysis

that you suffer, in not doing anything about what, on your account, is a gross violation of human

rights, is itself a consequence of legalized abortion, of the abortion mentality, and constitutes an

argument against legal abortion--because legal abortion has clearly numbed your moral

sensibility, and that of others as well.

But—returning to the line of argument—suppose it is the case that you lack confidence in

your belief. I fail to see why that should hold you back, if the other person is not more certain.

And I don't think it is the case that people who seek abortions after viability, or the physicians

who do them, are more confident that what they are doing is right, than you are that they are

wrong. Or perhaps it isn't a matter of confidence at all, but you simply regard your view about

when a human being with human rights comes into existence as somehow something "purely

subjective". But then, I wonder: why isn't your view about born human beings having human

rights similarly "purely subjective"? If the view that rights begin to exist at a certain time is purely

Page 3: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

151

subjective, then the view that they continue to exist after that time must also be purely subjective.

But then it seems that you do not really believe that there are such things as human rights, and, in

particular, you cannot really believe that there is such a thing as a right to privacy or a right to an

abortion—and your lack of confidence, and paralysis, in opposing those who would abort human

beings after viability, should, at least, be matched by a similar lack of confidence, and paralysis, in

opposing those who would prevent abortion before viability.

If you are to be consistent, your confidence in working for legal abortion before the time

you think a human being comes into existence, cannot be greater than your confidence in

working against legal abortion after the time you think a human being comes into existence--that

is, if your view that viability marks the transition from not having rights to having human rights,

is anything other than a mere rationalization.

Question 2.

Pro-choice people argue that the lack of consensus about when life begins implies that abortion

should be legal until birth. By why only until birth? Why not after birth--that is, why do we not

allow infanticide? My concern is: what keeps us from legalizing infanticide? Is it only because there

happens to be a consensus that infants are human beings with human rights? But what if that

consensus should change? And it is not naive to suppose it might change. There have been many

cultures throughout history which have condoned infanticide, just as many cultures have

condoned slavery and human sacrifice. There are philosophers who have argued that there are no

good reasons for favoring abortion but opposing infanticide. And reasoning like that used to

Page 4: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

152

support abortion has already been used in many cases to argue for infanticide of Downs

Syndrome children.

Well, suppose this way of thinking did become more widespread, and a sizable section of

our population began to think that it is unfortunate but necessary at times to kill newborn infants.

There would no longer, then, be a consensus. So would you concede that the lack of consensus on

infanticide implied that infants should not be protected from killing--that the parents should have

the right to decide, that it's "their decision", not anyone else's?

If you do concede this, then I would urge that it's not clear that you have any moral

principles at all—since it seems you are willing to give up your moral beliefs, if enough people

disagree with you. You would be, in effect, hostage to how others think. But if you wouldn't

concede this—if you deny that a lack of consensus that it is wrong to kill infants would cause you

to acquiesce in legalized infanticide--then why do you concede that a lack of consensus about

preborn children implies they should not be protected? To put the point another way: if you lived

in the United States in the 1950s, say, when abortion was considered as abominable as infanticide

is today, you presumably would have denied that the wrongness of abortion hinged upon the

consensus against it. So similarly you should deny today that legalized abortion follows from a

lack of consensus against it.

Question 3.

But in general, why does any position, rather than any other, follow from a lack of consensus?

Suppose someone were to argue as follows: "There is a lack of consensus about when human life

begins; therefore, abortion should be prohibited throughout pregnancy." Why is this argument

Page 5: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

153

any more, or less, reasonable than the argument that:"There is a lack of consensus about when

human life begins; therefore, abortion should be allowed throughout pregnancy?"

If the former argument is a non sequitur, then so is the latter. It might be thought that,

given a lack of consensus, the "easier" of two alternatives should be adopted, and it is easier on the

woman to allow abortion than to prohibit it. But this consideration begs the question, by

assuming that there is just one human being—the mother alone and not the child—with respect

to whom we should judge the "ease" or "difficulty" of the two options. You might as well just argue

outright, without this talk about "lack of consensus", that abortion should be legal--because only

the interests of the woman need be considered. But if this is your view, then you very well cannot

turn to the pro-life person and insist that it is wrongheaded for him to press for the illegalization

of abortion, given a lack of consensus on the matter—because, again, you favor its legalization,

given a lack of consensus, which is no more reasonable or unreasonable than favoring

illegalization, given a lack of consensus.

Question 4.

You hold that women should be free to choose what they think is right regarding abortion: if a

woman's conscience tells her that abortion is in her case permissible, then she should be free to

choose to have an abortion. This position has plausibility, because it seems to show respect for the

woman's conscience. But I wonder whether this is just an appearance. What do you think about

cases where the woman's conscience tells her that abortion is not a good thing--because she thinks

she is killing her baby—but she wants an abortion anyway. Why should these abortions be allowed?

Page 6: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

154

You may object that these cases are rare, but in fact they are very common. Various polls

have repeatedly shown that about 50% of Americans think that abortion is tantamount to murder,

and this figure holds for women as for men; so we might expect that about half of the women

seeking an abortion believe it is tantamount to murder. If you are still not convinced, and think

that it would hardly be possible for a woman to seek an abortion on those terms, then you should

consider the ample testimonial evidence to the contrary. For example, consider these passages

taken from a book written by a pro-choice author (The Ambivalence of Abortion, by Linda Bird

Francke):

(1) "At first I decided to keep the baby. I had had a prior abortion, which I hadn't

told my husband about, which depressed me very much for months later....This

time I couldn't help thinking it was a human being, a living being. At first my

husband wanted to keep it, but as the weeks went by...he changed his mind. The

new baby would interfere with everything. We want to move to the West Coast,

for example. We were convinced that the abortion was the best thing rather than

the right thing. If you asked me how I felt about abortion I would say I was

against it. I feel very hypocritical."(pp. 140-141)

(2) "Women undergoing second-trimester abortions have cause to be disturbed.

In many hospitals, for example, the fetus is expelled (the medical jargon is

'slipped') and left lying on the bed until the afterbirth is also expelled. There is a

natural curiosity for the women to look at the fetus, a curiosity the nurses try to

squelch. 'We tried to avoid the women seeing them,' says Norma Eidelman, who

worked for a short time with second-trimester patients. 'They always wanted to

Page 7: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

155

know the sex, but we lied and said it was too early to tell. It was better for the

women to think of the fetus as an 'it.'"(p. 53)

(3) "I really suffered from that. I was very much against abortion at the time. I

thought I was killing a living thing. And it didn't help much to overhear them

talking in the hospital when I had it, saying, 'Oh, it's a baby boy.'"(p. 120)

(4) "I come in tomorrow. I'm going to go through with it. I hope I feel better than

I do today. I love the baby. I love my husband. I just think it would be better for

him if I have the abortion. I'll get over it. I'm sure there'll be a lot of times when

I'll think about it, but we got so many problems now. So many. I know I can have

another baby someday. But it's this one I love now. I just love her so much .... "(p.

134)

(5) "When I see people having babies now, I envy them. I don't want to ever have

another abortion. It's a very frightening thing. The injection hurt a lot. But mostly

I thought about the baby when they were doing it. I thought, I'm killing another

human being, but then I'd remember that it wasn't even formed yet. I had two

sides going in my mind against each other."(p. 272)

In cases such as these, respect for the woman's conscience won't justify the abortion, but

just the opposite: we would show respect for her conscience by opposing the abortion, just as her

conscience does. And if we allow abortion in such cases, we allow people to do what they think is

tantamount murder, and clearly to have large numbers of citizens commit what they believe is

murder will destroy the moral fabric of our country. (This point holds whether abortion really is

tantamount to murder or not: what is important is that many people think it is.) So shouldn't

Page 8: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

156

even someone who was "pro-choice" agree that it would be preferable to try to screen out cases of

this sort, say, by asking a woman seeking an abortion to sign a statement saying that her

conscience tells her there is nothing wrong with the abortion?

Of course, this is not being done now. The counselors at abortion clinics don't screen out

these cases, since such their role is largely that of trying to quell any concerns a woman might

have about her abortion. Clinic counselors tend to view these doubts of conscience as a nuisance.

They think that the feelings of guilt are the problem--not the action which occasions the guilt. But

we might even argue, from the fact that about half of the women who seek abortion think it is

tantamount to murder, that abortion should be completely illegal. It hardly makes sense to keep

legal a practice which tempts people so violently to override their own consciences, to their own

and to society's detriment.

Question 5.

Pro-choice people claim that the current law about abortion in our country--or perhaps we

should say the absence of law--allows everyone to follow his or her own conscience: people who

are pro-choice can procure abortions, if they wish; and people who are pro-life are free not to

have an abortion, if they wish. After all, there are no compulsory abortions in this country. "If

you're against abortion," as the bumper sticker reads, "don't have one." But are pro-life people in

fact allowed to act in accordance with their convictions? Did Roe v. Wade merely open up a space

for a view that had no standing before--the view that abortion is in some circumstances permissible-

-or did it completely replace one view, the pro-life view, with some other view opposed to it--so that

Page 9: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

157

pro-life people could complain, with justice, that some alien and unjustified view has been imposed

upon them?

Suppose there were a society in which it was forbidden to come to the assistance of

children below the age of 7, when they were being attacked or were in danger. Suppose I lived in

such a society, and I saw a 6 year old child drowning, but I couldn't act to save him, since I was

prohibited by law from doing so, and I would have to spend years in jail and pay huge fines if I

disobeyed.

It would obviously be false to say that, in such a society, I was free to live in accordance

with my conviction that children are precious and have dignity. But similarly it is false to say that,

in our society, pro-life people are free to live in accordance with their conviction that unborn

children are precious and have dignity. The reason for this is that, if I believe that another human

being has dignity, then that belief implies that I help him and save him from harm. But people

who believe that unborn children are precious and have dignity are forbidden to act this way on

their behalf. What I wish to draw your attention to in this regard is a very important sort of

reasoning, which lies at the center of morality—I mean the process by which we reason from our

particular case to all similar cases, and conclude that all such cases should be treated in a similar

way.

For example, suppose I fall sick and spend a week in the hospital, and I notice how

thoughtless and inconsiderate some people are towards me. It is the most natural thing in the

world, and correct, to draw a general conclusion from this, and to decide that all sick persons

ought to be treated in a certain way. Again, suppose I am a parent, and I notice how important it

is that my child learn to read well—this might lead directly to my taking a more active interest in

Page 10: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

158

my child's school, because I see that other children are exactly like my child, and it is equally

important that they, too, learn how to read. Finally, suppose I am a pregnant woman, or the

husband whose wife is pregnant, and I am pro-life, and I see the dignity and preciousness of my

child in the womb—so that I would resist to the death anyone who threatened to harm that child.

By a process of reasoning like that in the other two cases I mentioned, I should conclude that any

child in utero is equal in dignity and preciousness to my own, and that I should work to prevent

the destruction of such children.

So the question I wish to pose to pro-choice people is the following, conditional question:

If you were pro-life, then wouldn't it be right for you to be concerned as well for other unborn

children, and not just for your own? Wouldn't this be consistent with everything else you know

about morality? (After all, it would be absurd to suggest that you were in favor of "the right to

choose" only for yourself, and not for people similarly situated, generally.) If you grant, then, that,

if you were pro-life, you might very well try to stop abortions, say, by sidewalk counseling, or

pickets, or even rescues, then you must admit that these activities are part of the pro-life view,

and, if you hold, furthermore, that both pro-life and pro-choice views should be allowed,

shouldn't you oppose any restrictions on these sorts of pro- life activities?

Question 6.

How should we regard a forced abortion of a pro-life woman's fetus? This happens, of course, in

China every day. It also happens occasionally in the United States—there have been several cases

reported of husbands or boyfriends who in effect force a woman to have an abortion, either by

coercing her to go to the clinic (these cases are perhaps not so rare), or by attacking her directly.

Page 11: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

159

For example, one jealous husband, after he found out that his wife was pregnant by another man,

tracked her down when she was in her 7th month, and violently reached up into her uterus and

caused a fatal miscarriage. Another man beat a pregnant woman on the belly with a baseball bat to

kill the unborn child. (These cases are grotesque, but what an abortionist does differs only in

manner, not in end.) Should such men be prosecuted for murder?

If the law concerning abortion should be designed so that "everyone can act in accordance

with one's own beliefs", then presumably just as the law lets some people procure an abortion,

because their beliefs allow it, so it should let the women in these cases, if they are pro-life, bring

charges of murder, because their beliefs require it. So our view ought to be that, if a man were to

force a pro- life woman to have an abortion, the man should be liable to prosecution for murder.

In fact, the California Supreme Court recently rule in just this way: it decided that an assault on a

pregnant woman that kills her fetus, even before viability, is murder. But if this is our view, then

we may ask: How can the question of what the man did—whether he committed a murder or not-

-depend upon how someone else besides the victim, the woman, happens to regard the action?

And how can the woman's mere assessment of the status of the fetus—whether she regards it as a

human being or not--change the fetus's status, from being something who can be a murder victim

(if the abortion is forced), to being a mere lump of tissue (if the abortion is voluntary)?

Or, if the woman's belief that what the man did was equivalent to murder is enough

reason to prosecute him for murder, then why isn't it the case that the woman who believes her

abortion is murder but goes ahead with it anyway—the cases of guilty conscience we discussed

before--why shouldn't such women similarly be liable to prosecution before the law? For what

could possibly be the difference between her husband or boyfriend killing the child, against her

Page 12: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

160

will, and an abortionist killing the child, against her conscience? —But if you find these

consequences objectionable, and so you wish to say, instead, that a man who forces a pro-life

woman to have an abortion cannot be prosecuted for murder: then clearly your are maintaining

that the law should not allow the woman to "act on her own beliefs", since she believes that her

child was murdered, but she cannot prosecute for murder. What you are saying, then, is that the

woman's child can have no greater status than a piece of property, even if the woman, her

husband, and all her family are pro-life.

Question 7.

Suppose a man and woman have intercourse, she becomes pregnant, and the man, who is pro-life,

thinks of the fetus as a human being, but the woman gets an abortion. Why is the abortion not

tantamount to murder in this case? Why is it only the female parent's opinion which determines the

status of the child?

Both man and woman are parents, and the woman carries the child. Yet surely to be a

parent, a generator of the fetus, a procreator, is to have a closer relationship to the fetus than

merely to contain the child physically. And we can raise the question, again, of whether in fact

such a husband is allowed to live out his pro-life convictions in our society. It is not even clear

that the husband is "free not to have an abortion", as the bumper sticker alleges, if his wife wants

to have one. What if his wife is set on aborting every one of his children?

You might say, in response, that it's the husbands fault if she is, because he should have

been careful not to marry anyone who would do such a thing. But suppose his wife didn't have

those beliefs when they married, but later changed her mind. You might say, then, that he should

Page 13: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

161

simply divorce her, if he does not like what she is doing. But why is the burden only on him? Why

can't we say, similarly, to the wife, that her husband's opinion ought to have equal importance

with her own, so that if they can't both agree to procure an abortion, then she can't get one-- and

if she doesn't like that, then she should not have married him, or should get a divorce?

But suppose--to continue an earlier line of thought—that the reason the woman has sole

right to decide to have an abortion is that the status of the fetus somehow depends upon how she

chooses to regard it: thus, the fetus is not a child until the mother decides that it is, say, at some

point later in pregnancy. But then a consequence of this is that the man, through having

intercourse with the woman, does not conceive a child. Rather, he conceives only a fetus, and the

fetus at some later point becomes a child, only because of the woman's deciding that it is. But then

the man's role in intercourse is not a cause of a child. He brought into existence only a fetus, and

it was the woman's decision to "continue the pregnancy through term" that made it a child.

But if so, it is not clear why the man should have any responsibility for the child. How

could the woman bring a claim for paternity support against him? After all, he could rightly reply:

"You decided to regard the fetus as a child; so the child is your responsibility." In short, here is the

dilemma: It is often claimed that the right to an abortion is a part of the right to control one's own

reproductive life. But then it seems that the decision to abort should be made jointly, by both the

father and mother. If we say that the mother alone can decide to have an abortion, then we ought

equally to grant that the husband alone can decide that the pregnancy should end in abortion—at

least he should be able to decide that he "aborts" the child, in the sense that he would have chosen

abortion (if the woman had agreed), and so he has no responsibility to care for the child.

Page 14: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

162

So it seems that either we grant the father an equal role in the abortion decision, or we

must conclude that fathers cannot be held responsible for their offspring. If total responsibility for

abortion rests with the mother, then total responsibility for birth should rest with her also. (This

question points to the connection between the practice of abortion and paternal irresponsibility.)

Question 8.

Suppose a woman who wanted an abortion were first to observe her unborn child through

ultrasound technology. In such images, the hands and feet of the child are typically discernible,

and even within the first trimester, it is common to see the unborn child sucking his or her

thumb. I ask the pro-choice person: Why aren't such images shown to woman, as part of informed

consent preceding abortion?

You might respond that the images are not relevant, but how do you know whether they

are relevant to her or not? I think, rather, your view is that such images are too relevant, that very

few women who saw them would choose to have an abortion. If this is your view, it is in fact

confirmed by experimental data: studies have shown that a kind of rudimentary mother-infant

bonding takes place when pregnant women are seen ultrasound pictures and listen to their

unborn child's heartbeat. And this is the reason why ultrasound facilities have two sets of

explanations, one for women who are seeking abortions, another for women who are carrying the

pregnancy to term.

Now, would you oppose a law requiring that a pregnant woman see ultrasound images of

her fetus before she gets an abortion? Or let's make the law weaker: it merely requires that she be

given the option of seeing those images. If you oppose such laws, then how are you pro-choice

Page 15: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

163

rather than pro-abortion? Again, is it because you think that many women would be swayed from

having an abortion? But then either you are imposing your views on them (because you have

decided in advance what sorts of considerations they should take to be important), or you are

pro-abortion rather than pro-choice (because you think that the most important thing is that the

women get abortions, not that they choose to get them on the proper ground).

And why isn't your position manipulative and deceitful? In general it is deceitful to

withhold information from someone, if you know that, if you released it, the other person would

act very differently. For example, if I am a physician and I know that a certain operation has some

chance of causing paralysis, and I know that my patient may very well not agree to have the

operation, if he knows this, and I don't tell him, then I have deceived and manipulated him. And

this seems to be how pro-choice people act, who are opposed to informed consent.

Question 9.

If you think abortion should be allowed, can you consistently maintain that there any human rights

at all? Human rights are presumably rights that belong to us in virtue of our being human--that is

why they are called "human" rights. They are prior to decision or convention, precisely because

they depend upon our nature. We have them simply because we are human beings, not because of

an acquired characteristic or accomplishment. But if the fetus has no rights, then there are no

human rights, because the fetus is clearly a human being, and if there were rights that followed

from simply being human, the fetus would have them. If there are no human rights, then of

course the so-called "right to privacy" or "right to an abortion" is also not a human right.

Page 16: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

164

So you cannot consistently deny the right to life of the fetus, and assert the right to

privacy of the mother. Talk of brute power, or domination, or "getting your way", if you wish, but

don't misuse the language of human rights, which you in practice reject. In fact we need to ask the

more fundamental question: What distinguishes a claim of expediency or self-interest from a

claim that one has a right? You claim that there is a right to an abortion, but why should anyone

believe this? Why aren't you just saying: "I want this, so you should give it to me?" (And it is a

curious fact that the idea that there is a right to an abortion seemed to arise at just the same time

as the sexual revolution. Before 1970, no one had ever asserted that there was a right to an

abortion. From the point of view of history, it might appear that this rights claim has more to do

with the people conceiving a child in circumstances in which a child would be unwanted--and

abortion happens to be an effective remedy. But this is far from establishing any "right".)

But what is a right? Exactly how many rights are there? Why is the right to an abortion

one of these rights? —Can you give an argument for your view, or is it mere assertion? — How

can there be a human right that only women have, but not men? Are there any other rights that

only one sex possesses? And if abortion is a "necessary evil", as it seems almost everybody grants,

and hence in some sense wrong, then--to raise a question that Lincoln asked Douglas about

slavery-- how can there be a right to do a wrong? Are there any other rights that we know of that

have this feature?

But suppose we say that the so-called "right to an abortion" is not a human right, prior to

convention or human decision. It is therefore a consequence of human law: we could even say

that the Supreme Court created this right, in 1973. But if that is the case, then we cannot argue

that abortion should remain legal because there is a right to an abortion. That would be an

Page 17: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

165

entirely empty argument, equivalent to saying that "abortion should be legal because abortion is

legal."

Question 10

Does the following seem to you a reasonable statement of the pro-choice view?:

If each person will only agree to mind his own business, and leave his neighbors

alone, there will be peace forever between us... I am now speaking of rights under

the constitution, and not of moral or religious rights...It is for women to decide ...

the moral and religious right of the abortion question for themselves within their

own limits.... I repeat that the principle is the right of each woman to decide this

abortion question for herself, to have an abortion or not, as she chooses, and it

does not become a pro-lifer, or anybody else, to tell the her she has no

conscience, that she is living in a state of iniquity... We have enough objects of

charity at home, and it is our duty to take care of our own poor, and our own

suffering, before we go abroad to intermeddle with other people's business.

I arrived at that quotation by taking one of Stephen Douglas's defenses of slavery, and substituting

"abortion" for "slavery"; "woman" for "state"; and "a pro-lifer" for "Mr. Lincoln."

I've done the same with the following response from Lincoln:

The doctrine of freedom of choice is right--absolutely and eternally right--but it

has no just application, as here attempted. Or perhaps I should rather say that

whether it has such just application depends upon whether a fetus is not or is a

human being. If it is not a human being, why in that case, she who is a human

Page 18: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

166

being may, as a matter of freedom of choice, do just as she pleases with it. But if

the fetus is a human being, is it not to that extent, a total destruction of freedom

of choice, to say that it too shall not have freedom of choice itself? ... If the fetus is

a human being, why then my ancient faith teaches me that 'all men are created

equal;' and that there can be no moral right in connection with one human

being's aborting another.

Doesn't the similarity between your defense of abortion, and Douglas' defense of slavery, bother

you in any way? Does it raise in your mind any suspicions at all that you might just be on the

wrong side?

Question 11

There is another argument against abortion, analogous to an argument of Lincoln. Lincoln said,

famously, that "as I would not be a slave; so I would not be a master". He also remarked that,

although he had heard many people defend slavery as a good thing, he had never yet met a man

who wanted to become a slave himself. So we can ask: Does anyone wish that his mother had

chosen abortion for him? And, if not, then how can he consistently wish that any mother choose

abortion for anyone else?

Question 12

Developing the analogy with slavery, we might wonder how abortion is at all compatible with the

idea that all human beings are equal. After all, it is inconsistent with equality that one person have

his fundamental rights conferred upon him by someone else. Indeed, the phrase "conferring

Page 19: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

167

fundamental rights" has the appearance of an oxymoron. Consider how this worked in practice in

the antebellum United States: when a white man freed a black slave, the black man would be "free"

and enjoy "rights", yet even so, he would not, and he could not, be equal to the white man, for his

freedom was originally granted to him by the white man. The reason for this is that, when one

person grants rights to another, the former is a superior, the latter is an inferior, and they remain

so, in spite of their both having rights, and even if this granting of rights is legally irrevocable.

Similarly, as we saw, in our current practice of legal abortion, the unborn child has rights

only if they are granted by the mother. For if the mother wishes to have an abortion, then the

child has no rights, and its death is considered inconsequential; but if the mother wishes to

continue her pregnancy, then an attack on the child is considered unlawful and even murderous.

Hence the child--and presumably also the adult who grows from the child--has rights only

because they have been originally granted by the mother. But this, as we have seen, is

incompatible with the fundamental equality of all human beings.

As a consequence, even though it may not be consciously recognized or understood, it

must be practically impossible that people who are pro-choice regard the following generation as

equal in dignity and worth to them. And I would suggest that many of the evident problems of the

post-Roe v. Wade generations of children arise from this.

Question 13

Developing the analogy with slavery even more, we can ask: Why isn't legal abortion outright

discrimination? I think "discrimination" occurs in its clearest form when someone bases a decision

about another person's rights, privileges, or position, on some arbitrary and irrelevant feature of

Page 20: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

168

that other person. In its clearest form, perhaps, discrimination is practiced by one class of human

beings against another, and the class that practices it benefits from it. For instance, if white

persons, for their own advantage, treat blacks differently from whites, and deny them human

rights, privileges, or positions, because of their black skin color, they are practicing

discrimination.

But if we look at legal abortion objectively, doesn't it satisfy this description? By legal

abortion, one class of human beings--born human beings--deny human rights and the protection

of the law to another class of human beings--unborn children--because of a feature inessential to

our humanity, viz. whether one is living inside or outside one's mother's womb. The difference

between being unborn and being born seems just as accidental to a human being as the difference

between having white and having black skin--as does the criterion of viability, which is arbitrary,

external to the unborn child, and a function of the sort of medical technology available in the

mother's community. (Abortion is thought to be justifiable before viability, because up to that

time the fetus is completely dependent upon the mother. But why should someone's being

completely dependent upon another imply that he or she can be killed? Suppose a mother and her

newborn baby are stranded on a desert island. The baby is completely dependent upon her. How

does it follow that the mother has a right to kill the baby?)

Question 14

Suppose we bracket for the moment the idea that the unborn child is a human being with human

rights. Let's suppose that these things are uncertain, which in fact they are not. Even so: wouldn't

legal abortion be contrary to responsible principles of decision under uncertainty? If it were true that

Page 21: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

169

we "don't know when human life begins," it would follow, of course, that we don't know that the

fetus is not a living human being; that is, we don't know that abortion is not morally equivalent to

murder. But isn't that precisely what we ought to know, before allowing abortion?

An analogy: there is a discarded refrigerator box in my yard; and I wish to practice

shooting with a my new archery equipment. Before shooting arrows at the box, I am both morally

and legally obliged to make sure that there is no child playing in the box, and without this

certainty, I shouldn't proceed. The reason is that it is wrong even to do something which might be

tantamount to killing another. But pro-choice people admit that abortion might be tantamount to

killing another--because they admit that we don't know that life doesn't begin before abortions

take place. So then, until you reach greater clarity, shouldn't you agree that it is morally wrong,

should also be legally wrong?

Question 15

But it is important that we not overstate our degree of ignorance. We know that the thing in the

womb is alive: it has a heart beat from 2 weeks after conception; it has detectable brain waves

from 6 weeks--and abortions don't take place before 6 weeks. So the thing in the womb is, at least,

a living animal. And it might very well, from an early period, be capable of feeling pain--certainly

it moves and responds to stimuli, and movement and perception, it might be argued, must be

couple with some rudimentary ability to feel pleasure and pain. So then, I assume that you think

that people ought to be compassionate towards animals. Perhaps you are even a vegetarian and

opposed to killing animals on principle. How, then, can you consistently support legal abortion?

Page 22: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

170

In every abortion the fetus is cut into pieces, ripped or torn apart, or poisoned. No one

would want to treat a small kitten or puppy in that manner, nor does the law allow to do so, so why

should we allow anyone to treat immature human beings in that way? Imagine that, instead of

paying money for an abortion, the price was to take a newly born puppy, the size of a peanut, and

put it in a meat grinder. This an action quite comparable to what takes place in an abortion. How

many people would pay that price? Then is it only the hidden character of abortion that makes it

seem acceptable?

Question 16

Why is an abortion traumatic, but an appendectomy is not? If the fetus really is just a clump of

tissue, why should there be any fuss about abortion? Indeed, if an abortion were in reality just like

an appendectomy, how would it be possible for pro-life people to get others agitated about it? The

very fact that there is a dispute at all about abortion seems to show that the pro-life view is correct

and that abortions should not be performed.

Question 17

Why is it that doctors are allowed to do abortions? Even if abortions should be legal, shouldn't they

be performed by some other sort of agent? Just as we do not allow doctors to administer

injections for capital punishment, shouldn't we also bar doctors from doing abortions? The

reason for this is that doctors should not engage in actions that are contrary to the aims of the

practice of medicine, and these are to heal and relive pain. But someone who performs an

Page 23: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

171

abortion does neither of these things: he kills a living being; creates pain; and acts violently against

the natural process of pregnancy.

Question 18

Suppose a genetic marker for homosexuality is found, and a test is devised for this, and couples

begin to abort fetuses with this marker. Should this practice be made illegal? If so, then why not

sex-selection abortions also? And why not abortions for handicaps? But if some abortions are

wrong and should be illegal, this implies that abortion is not in every case to be allowed simply

because it was decided upon by the mother. But then aren't there also other reasons for abortion

that are clearly unacceptable?

Question 19

Suppose the Supreme Court had decided in Roe v. Wade that the Constitution states that abortion

must be illegal, that any law which allowed abortion was unconstitutional. What would your

reaction have been? But the constitutional basis for a decision of that sort would have been just as

strong as the constitutional basis for the actual holding of Roe., that any law which restricts or

prohibits abortion is unconstitutional.

Suppose that, in decided some case, the Supreme Court decides to dispense with

argument and legal reasoning and instead rolls dice to decide whether a laws is unconstitutional.

Would its decision in that case have had any authority? But what if the Court doesn't role dice but

also gives no constitutional reasons for its conclusion? In fact it gave no reasons in Roe v. Wade:

Page 24: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

172

the substance of the decision can be summed up in the bald assertions: the right to privacy

contains the right to an abortion; the state has no legitimate interest in fetal life until viability.

But why does such a decision have authority? How does such a decision count as an

instance of constitutional government— that is, government in accordance with some previously

agreed upon rules for ordering public life? And why does the mere authority of the Supreme

Court have any weight? Pro-choice people are concerned that the views of a particular religion

not be imposed on the country as a whole, even through legislation. Why is this? Why does this

seem to us to be incompatible with our form of government?

The reason is that such legislation would be based solely on religious authority, and

therefore it would be arbitrary, to someone who was not a member of that religion, and we could

not reasonably expect him to consent to it. For example, if the Pope were to rule that Catholics

must stop eating meat on Fridays, and Catholics who were in the majority in a certain city passed

a law that meat could not be bought, sold, or consumed on Fridays, this law would be arbitrary, to

someone who did not accept Papal authority, and we could not reasonably expect such a person

to consent to it.

But why doesn't an arbitrary decision by the Supreme Court have the same character.

What is the difference, if the authority is religious or secular? —The important thing is that, in

both cases, the decision is arbitrary. To this you might object that all Americans do and should

accept the authority of the Supreme Court to decide constitutional matters. But the proper reply

to this is that the Court must give reasons in the exercise of its authority, so that it is clear that the

its decisions are based in the constitution, and not in the opinions of members of the court.

Page 25: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

173

Certainly the constitution does not give the Supreme Court the authority to decide constitutional

matters apart from any recognizable appeal to the Constitution.]

Questions for pro-life people, and replies

Question 1

Don't your views on abortion depend upon your religious view? But then wouldn't the separation of

church and state require that you not try to make others live by your religion?

Reply to Question 1

Opposition to abortion need not be based on religious views. The most fundamental reason why

abortion is wrong is that it is contrary to the principle of the natural equality of all human beings.

This principle is not religious; in fact, it lies at the foundation of our form of government.

This point may be made clearer if we make the following distinctions. A belief may be

called religious for one of three reasons:

1. it is strongly or passionately held, e.g. we might say that someone believes "religiously"

that smoking is bad for one's health;

2. it has religious content , e.g. it concerns God or the supernatural realm;

3. it is accepted on the basis of a religious authority , e.g. Christians believe that God is a

Trinity of persons because the Bible and the Church teach this.

Page 26: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

174

Clearly the pro-life view is "religious" in the first sense for many people. But this is obviously a

metaphorical sense of the word "religious", and many political and moral views are "religious" in

this sense. It would be absurd to object to a view simply because it was passionately held.

The pro-life view is not essentially religious in the second sense. Of course it is possible to

state and defend the pro-life view using religious terms, so that it seems as though the view

necessarily has religious content, e.g. someone might argue that all of us are children of God, or

made in the image of God, or the property of God, or that life is a gift of God, so that as a

consequence abortion is very wrong. But the pro-life view can be more than adequately stated

using moral principles that are generally accepted and which even seem to be fundamental in a

free and democratic society. The pro-life view may instructively be compared with the civil rights

movement in this respect: many of the leaders of the civil rights movement were Christian

ministers who argued against segregation and discrimination on religious grounds. Nevertheless,

the reforms they were urging could be defended also on non-religious grounds. In general,

religious people understand justice religiously; non-religiously people understand it non-

religiously. But what counts as justice is the same for both.

It follows that the pro-life view is not religious in the third sense: to see that abortion is

wrong, it is sufficient to use ordinary moral and political reasoning; there is no need to appeal to

special sources of religious insight and revelation, such as the Bible. True enough, the Bible does

teach (through what it implies) that abortion is wrong; likewise it teaches that theft is wrong. And

there are undoubtedly some people who don't steal or seek abortions only because the Bible

teaches this. Yet this fact is irrelevant to the sort of question which must be considered in a debate

about public policy, viz. whether theft is unjust, whether abortion is unjust . Suppose we adopted

Page 27: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

175

this principle: if the Bible teaches that X is wrong, then we cannot outlaw X, for then we would be

imposing a religious view on society. It would follow, absurdly, that we couldn't outlaw murder,

theft, perjury, assault, and rape, since the Bible teaches that all of these are wrong. But what holds

in the case of these other injustices holds also in the case of abortion. The view that abortion is

unjust cannot be dismissed as "a religious view" simply because the Bible and Christian teaching

hold that abortion is wrong.

Question 2

But religions differ on abortion. Some religions actually would mandate that a woman have an

abortion in certain circumstances, e.g. some rabbis think that a woman is obliged to have an

abortion if her life is at stake. You would be denying religious freedom to people of those religions

if abortion were illegal. If pro-life legislation went into effect, wouldn't ministers and rabbis would

be sent to jail for their views on abortion?

Reply to Question 2

Even religious practices can be outlawed if they bring about serious harm to others. For example,

there have throughout history been many religions which have mandated human and especially

child-sacrifice: an Aztec priest was actually required to sacrifice a human being once a day. But

this practice would be illegal, and should be illegal in our country. Not all religious practices can

be tolerated: those that involve serious injustice must be made illegal.

Page 28: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

176

If abortion is taking the life of a human being, then it is a grave injustice, and those

religions (and in fact they are very few in number) which actually mandate abortion in some

circumstances would have to be limited by the law in that respect.

In any case it should be noted that there are dozens of priests and ministers who are in jail

right now because of their views on abortion. They believe that their religion requires them to act

in non-violent ways to hinder the practice of abortion. The law currently decides against them

and sentences them to jail. It seems that, unfortunately, disagreement by religious people over

abortion is deep and fundamental, so that however the law is decided, some sincere persons will

end up going to jail. But it is mere self-deception to think that current laws avoid this

consequence.

Question 3

Isn't it ludicrous to say that a newly fertilized egg is a person, equal in dignity and importance to

you and me?

Reply to Question 3

Note first of all that this is not a reasoned objection but rather something like an exclamation. No

doubt some people find this idea ludicrous; but others evidently do not. From these obvious facts

we cannot conclude either that the fertilized egg is a person or that it is not.

In any case, the pro-life position is more accurately expressed as the view that a fertilized

egg is a human being, and that that--namely, its sharing our nature--is what gives even a fertilized

egg a moral significance and indeed a certain human dignity. If by "person" you mean simply a

Page 29: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

177

"human being," then of course the fertilized egg is indeed a "person"--this is not ludicrous at all. If,

however, by "person" you mean an actually thinking and self-aware being, then of course a

fertilized egg is not a person. But then neither is a newborn baby a person in this sense. And it is

clear that our rights and dignity do not depend upon our being "persons" in that sense.

But that a "fertilized egg" is "one of us"--is a part of the human community--needs to be

approached from the first-person case. You yourself were once an unborn child, before that an

embryo, and before that a fertilized egg. If something had been done to damage that "fertilized

egg", then something would have been done to damage you. For example, an alteration bringing

about a birth defect would have brought about a birth defect in you.

Next approach the question from the point of view of a mother. Suppose you are a

mother looking upon a newborn baby. You reflect on how that baby was moments ago living

within your womb. You reflect on how you were concerned early on in pregnancy with what you

ate, since you were aware that most birth defects arise early on in development. Your thinking

that everything went well for the embryo is just your thinking about the baby before you.

In fact it is not impossible, nor even difficult, to come to regard even a very immature

human being, an embryo or "fertilized egg," as having dignity and great significance. Of course we

know that some people consider it ludicrous to regard a fertilized egg as a human being. But the

real question here is: Must it be ludicrous so to regard it? Is it possible for each of us to come to

regard a human embryo as part of the human community? Is this view of things available to all of

us? And I believe that, upon serious reflection, it is clear that this is possible for us, that this

viewpoint is available to us.

Page 30: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

178

Question 4

If a fertilized egg is a person, and killing a fertilized egg is outlawed, then some forms of birth

control will have to be outlawed-- the IUD and some forms of the pill--because these work by

killing the fertilized egg. Also, scientific research on human embryos would have to stop."

Reply to Question 4

The argument under consideration is simply this: suppose some method of birth control works by

somehow destroying the early embryo. Wouldn't this method have to be outlawed, if abortions are?

And how could this be right?

But why should we think that all forms of birth control have to be legal, whatever their

nature and however they work? Why should this be a fixed point in the debate? What's so

objectionable about ruling out some forms of "birth control," if they are in fact abortifacient? One

might just as well argue: "abortion is used by many women as a form of birth control; so if

abortions are illegal, then a form of birth-control will have to be made illegal, which can't be the

case."

Again, why should we think that all forms of research have to be legal? There are of

course tight safeguards regarding research on human subjects. What's absurd about extending

this kind of regulation even to experiments on immature human subjects? Note also that there are

very few experiments on human embryos which couldn't be carried out in some other and

essentially equivalent way without employing human embryos at all.

Page 31: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

179

Question 5

If the pro-lifers have their way, then won't we end up living in a totalitarian state, with Pregnancy

Police checking up on suspiciously missed periods, just as they did in Romania when abortion was

outlawed?

Reply to Question 5

For the most part, people already act as though the unborn child is a human being. Generally, if a

woman decides to "have her baby", she speaks of the child in her womb as "my baby"; she tries to

eat well; she saves the ultrasound picture of her child and shows it to friends; and so on. Indeed, it

is natural and even easy to regard the child in the womb as a member of the human community.

The one exception to this general practice is abortion, in which the unborn child is treated as a

non-entity and a mistake: the fact of its existence is denied, as though it could be taken back or

revoked.

Pro-lifers simply call attention to this self-deception, this inconsistency, and urge that

even unborn children who are unwanted and slated for destruction be regarded as having the

same intrinsic dignity and value as the unwanted child. Thus, it is not burdensome to regard the

unborn child as an equal human being; our society would to a large extent already have achieved

this simply by bringing an end to abortion. Pro-life legislation should be conceived of as the

generalization, to society as a whole, of a way of regarding the unborn that is already practiced by

those who are pro-life. And this way of life is not burdensome.

The objection that pro-life legislation would be totalitarian fails to take into account that

the pro-life movement does not aim merely to pass laws; rather, it is a movement of reform which

Page 32: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

180

aims to change the mores and culture of our society. In order to evaluate correctly the character of

pro-life laws, it is necessary to imagine them as adopted by a society in which the majority of

persons have freely adopted pro-life mores. For such a society, pro-life laws would reflect their

ideals of the human community and would not be totalitarian.

In any case, it should be noted, out of fairness, that any moral ideal whatsoever could

conceivably give rise either to reasonable and liberal legislation or to bizarre, totalitarian

legislation. It is not a fair objection against a movement based on an ideal, that its aims could be

contorted into a totalitarian cast. For example, concern for the environment is a praiseworthy

ideal. There are liberal laws that might reflect this concern, e.g. a mandatory recycling program.

Likewise there are laws of a totalitarian character which might be devised to further this ideal, e.g.

"litter police", who invade your house and search for non-recyclable containers; or "light bulb

police," who conduct examinations to be sure you never leave light bulbs burning unnecessarily.

Of course such laws are ludicrous, and it would be frivolous to object to the environmental

movement, on the ground that environmentalism must lead to these sorts of totalitarian laws.

Similarly, laws implementing "pregnancy police" are ludicrous, and it is frivolous and unfair to

object to the pro-life movement, on the ground that its ideals must lead to totalitarian laws.

I think we can all agree that totalitarianism is bad; pro-lifers hate totalitarianism as much

as anyone else.

Page 33: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

181

Question 6

Aren't pro-lifers inconsistent when they say that abortion is tantamount to murder, but then shrink

from advocating the prosecution and punishment of the millions of women who have gotten

abortions?

Reply to Question 6

This is not necessarily inconsistent. There are various ways in which the two views alluded to

might be held consistently:

1. Someone might think that no woman every freely and without coercion chooses to have

an abortion, just as some people maintain that suicide is never a freely chosen act. If this

is the case, the woman's responsibility for procuring the abortion is considerably

mitigated;

2. Someone might hold that a woman who gets an abortion does something seriously

wrong, and is responsible for it, but that the act itself carries with it its own penalty, since

she loses her child in the abortion. It might be thought that any further penalty is

unnecessary;

3. Someone might hold that, although many abortions merit punishment, still, the state's

decision of whether to punish or not should be made with an eye to the common good,

and the common good would not be served by punishing women who procure abortions.

Why? Because if any were punished then all would have to be; but it would be too harsh to

punish all--the cure would be as bad as the ailment. So none should be punished; rather, the

abortionist should be punished as being a sort of initiator of the abortion.

Page 34: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

182

Question 7

Isn't the pro-life view sectarian? It is a narrow, conservative view, that can only be attractive to

members of the religious right.

Reply to Question 7

Strictly, a viewpoint is conservative if it seeks to preserve the status quo . In this literal sense, it is

the "pro-choice" view, of course, that is conservative, and the pro-life view is, rather, progressive.

The "pro-choice" position wants to preserve business as usual, but the pro-life view aims at a far-

reaching reform of the ideals and policies of our country.

The term "conservative" could also mean a certain view of the nature and limits of

government--that less government is generally better and that people should be "left alone" as

much as possible. This view, in its extreme form, is often called "libertarianism", and when applied

to economic matters, it is strenuously resisted by those who call themselves "liberals." Yet,

curiously, the "pro-choice" view is conservative in this sense: it is essentially a libertarian view,

since it urges that pregnant women should just be left alone to do what they wish, free from any

government interference, regardless of the nature and character of the act of abortion.

Once again, a view may be called "liberal" rather than "conservative" if it is rooted in

principles and ideals typical of the liberal political tradition. That tradition begins with late

medieval speculation about contract theory and is articulated in modern times by J. Locke and

then (though more controversially) J.S. Mill. Liberalism in this sense is egalitarian and benevolent

. Its central principle is the natural equality of all human beings, and it is marked by the expansion

Page 35: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

183

(rather than restriction) of the scope of the moral community. Without doubt, the pro-life view is

"liberal" in this sense, and the "pro-choice" view is illiberal. The pro-life view is grounded on the

idea that it is the humanity of the unborn child which makes him or her the equal of anyone else

in society, i.e. it forcefully asserts the natural equality of all human beings. Furthermore, the pro-

life view aims to extend the scope of moral concern to children before they are born, whereas the

"pro-choice" view is caught up with drawing lines that exclude some human beings from moral

consideration.

Question 8

Well, then, aren't pro-life people inconsistent, and not really pro-life, because although they oppose

abortion, they don't oppose capital punishment or the killing of animals?

Reply to Question 8

It is true that superficially, executing a criminal, slaughtering an animal, and performing an

abortion seem to be of a piece. Each action is an act of destruction; each is an act of harm; each

involves killing a living thing. The question of consistency would therefore seem to be equally

pressing for someone who opposes capital punishment, or who opposes killing animals, but who

is not similarly opposed to abortion.

If it is wrong to kill a guilty murderer, isn't it wrong to kill an innocent and vulnerable

developing human being? If the murderer should be given another chance, shouldn't the unborn

child? If the murderer's life is worth living and not hopeless, isn't the unborn child's also, no

matter how desperate or difficult his or her circumstances may appear? Likewise, if it is wrong to

Page 36: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

184

kill an animal, isn't it wrong to kill the fetus, which is certainly an animal? If convenience,

comfort, or even serious self interest do not justify slaughtering an animal, how can they ever

justify an abortion? Clearly it is inconsistent to be opposed to capital punishment or animal

killing, and yet to favor the "right to choose."

But a pro-lifer who favors capital punishment, does not recognize animal rights, and

opposes abortion is not in the same way inconsistent. For this combination of views follows

consistently from the adoption of the principle that "it is always wrong to take the life of an

innocent human being." Because it is wrong to take the life of an innocent human being, abortion

is wrong, since abortion involves the destruction of an innocent human being. Because a criminal

convicted of a capital crime is not innocent, it is not always wrong to take his or her life through

capital punishment. Because an animal is not a human being, it is not always wrong to take the

life of an animal. This is a perfectly consistent set of views, which all can be accounted for given

the stated principle.

Why would it be wrong to kill human beings but not animals? The reason has to do with

equality: a killing is not an act of equality -- the killer is superior, the killed is inferior, because the

life of the killed is controlled by and indeed terminated by the killer. Thus killing is incompatible

with human equality and therefore unjust. Human beings are in fact equal; killing is incompatible

with this equality. But human beings and animals are not equal. Although human beings and

animals are alike in sentience, i.e. they can both feel pleasure and pain, human beings are superior

in that they have superior powers of knowledge and desire, in particular, they have the ability to

reason and the ability to aim at the good of another. So it is not necessary for human beings to

treat animals as equals; in fact, it is wrong for them to do so, since they are not equals.

Page 37: Difficult Questions for Pro Choice Persons

185

The distinction between human beings and animals is important for our purposes

because it makes it clear that human beings are set apart by their capacities and potential. A

human being is a thing which has the capacity to think, which has the capacity to aim at the

complete good of another. Our value as human beings lies in our potential, not in our

achievements. And this is why it is appropriate to think of the unborn child as having value and in

fact as being the equal of any human being. For human equality is an equality in capability of

reasoning, and the unborn child has this capability. True enough, this capability is not at all

realized--but then, neither is it realized in the case of a newborn baby. A newborn baby has no

distinctive human abilities which the unborn child does not have.