Democratic Peace Social and Theory and PoliticsW16-116

22
Democratic Peace/Cold War - Chapter 1 1 The democratic peace : social theory and politics (1.)Introduction p. 1 (2.)The hidden presence of social theory p. 2 (2.1.)The object of inquiry p. 3 (2.2.)Causes and action p. 9 (3.)The politics of the democratic peace p. 13 (4.)Conclusion p. 17 1. Introduction The democratic peace is an observation in political science. It states, first, that democracies fight as many wars as do non-democracies, and, second, that democracies do however not fight each other. It is an important observation. Purportedly, the democratic peace is as close as anything we have to an empirical law in international relations.” 1 Also, the research on it would showcase the possibility of progressive science in International Relations. 2 If the democratic peace holds true, and if it can somehow be implemented, it could also contribute practically to world peace. 3 At the same time, critics of the democratic peace have been no less vocal. Some remain unconvinced that the democratic peace even exists, dismissing it as a statistical artifact. 4 Others question the causal nature of the relationship. 5 Still others worry about the congratulatory subtext of the finding, or fear the policy implications that potentially flow from it. 6 In this chapter, I sketch the contours of existing democratic peace research in some detail. The purpose of this stock-taking exercise is not to an exhaustive discussion of the various contributions to the debate. Given the vast numbers of publications on the subject, this would scarcely be possible anyway. Moreover, very good surveys exist already. 7 The purpose is rather to draw out the social-theoretic premises that make the democratic peace work and to suggest why a different set of premises should be considered. In other words, to the extent that I call for more research on the democratic peace, I am not recommending that we continue to fiddle in the margins 1 Levy 1988, 662. 2 Chernoff 2004. 3 Russett 1993, 357. 4 Spiro 1996a. 5 Layne 1996 ; Rosato 2003. 6 Owen 2005. 7 E.g., Geis and Wagner 2008.

Transcript of Democratic Peace Social and Theory and PoliticsW16-116

Democratic Peace/Cold War - Chapter 1

1

The democratic peace : social theory and politics

(1.)Introduction p. 1

(2.)The hidden presence of social theory p. 2

(2.1.)The object of inquiry p. 3

(2.2.)Causes and action p. 9

(3.)The politics of the democratic peace p. 13

(4.)Conclusion p. 17

1. Introduction

The democratic peace is an observation in political science. It states, first, that democracies fight as

many wars as do non-democracies, and, second, that democracies do however not fight each other.

It is an important observation. Purportedly, the democratic peace is “as close as anything we have to

an empirical law in international relations.”1 Also, the research on it would showcase the possibility

of progressive science in International Relations.2 If the democratic peace holds true, and if it can

somehow be implemented, it could also contribute practically to world peace.3 At the same time,

critics of the democratic peace have been no less vocal. Some remain unconvinced that the

democratic peace even exists, dismissing it as a statistical artifact.4 Others question the causal nature

of the relationship.5 Still others worry about the congratulatory subtext of the finding, or fear the

policy implications that potentially flow from it.6

In this chapter, I sketch the contours of existing democratic peace research in some detail.

The purpose of this stock-taking exercise is not to an exhaustive discussion of the various

contributions to the debate. Given the vast numbers of publications on the subject, this would

scarcely be possible anyway. Moreover, very good surveys exist already.7 The purpose is rather to

draw out the social-theoretic premises that make the democratic peace work and to suggest why a

different set of premises should be considered. In other words, to the extent that I call for more

research on the democratic peace, I am not recommending that we continue to fiddle in the margins

1 Levy 1988, 662.

2 Chernoff 2004.

3 Russett 1993, 357.

4 Spiro 1996a.

5 Layne 1996 ; Rosato 2003.

6 Owen 2005.

7 E.g., Geis and Wagner 2008.

Democratic Peace/Cold War - Chapter 1

2

(more data, more rival hypotheses), but rather that we envisage a fundamental reconsideration. As a

result, I have to argue my case with some fervor. What follows, therefore, is a thorough excavation of

the old, coupled with a substantive argument in favor of the strength and relevance of the new.

The “fact of the democratic peace”8 is not wrong. The observation has been observed

repeatedly and there is no obvious reason to assume that a malin génie is deceiving the scientific

gaze on this massive a scale. Democracies have rarely if ever fought each other. However, facts do

not exist outside of theories; data do. A datum becomes a fact when it is constituted as significant by

the theory that brings it forth and embeds it. “Being significant” should be understood here in its

dual sense both of “having meaning” and “being important.” However, it is not only that facts are

theory-dependent.9 Equally, theories have a political dimension to them. In Robert Cox’ well-known

phrase: “Theory is always for someone and for some purpose.”10 I am concerned, in short, with the

(social) theory and the politics of the democratic peace.

The next section reveals social theory as a hidden presence in democratic peace research.

Both its conception of the object of inquiry and its construction of causal explanations betray a

fundamentally un-sociological approach. It is my argument in this chapter that it would be fruitful to

recast research into the democratic peace in a more sociological mould.11 While this runs the risk of

taking the politics out of it, I will argue that a turn to sociology actually adds to our understanding of

“the politics of the democratic peace.” The reason is that it reconnects democratic peace with the

quintessential, and in fact quintessentially political, problem of order.12 This is, however, not to deny

that important costs are incurred in the process.

2. The hidden presence of social theory

In this section, I critically review existing democratic peace research. The discussion has two parts:

one dealing with its explanandum (2.1.), the other with its explanans (2.2.). I use the Latin

terminology deliberately because it implies less methodological bias than the more common notion

of dependent and independent variables. The Latin terms allow for a more encompassing

understanding of causation and explanation. In the process, their use also signals the methodological

8 Russett 1993, chapter 1.

9 Compare Waltz 2008, 93. Waltz, quoting Goethe, affirms that: « The highest wisdom is to realize that every

fact is already a theory. » 10

Cox 1981, 128. 11

Compare Kratochwil 2008. Recasting International Relations in a « more sociological mould » was the exact purpose of the introduction of constructivism into the discipline (e.g., Onuf 1989 and Wendt 1999). Logically, the question ensues: “Which sociology?” On this point, see Godard and Nexon 2005. 12

Rengger 2000. Also Ringmar 2008.

Democratic Peace/Cold War - Chapter 1

3

bias in evidence when the more common terminology is deployed.13 For this reason, I entertain the

hope that changing vocabulary proves instrumental in excavating the implicit social-theoretic

premises of existing democratic peace research; premises which are by definition wagers:

“provisional commitments *…+ that can really never be settled definitively.”14

2.1. The object of inquiry

In ‘Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs, ’15 an article published in two parts in

Philosophy & Public Affairs and one of the loci classici of democratic peace research, Michael Doyle

states his topic of inquiry unambiguously: “What difference do liberal principles and institutions

make to the conduct of the foreign affairs of liberal states?”16 Compare the work of Dean Babst, a

former government-employed sociologist who is generally credited for having published the first

empirical piece on “Elective Government” being a “Force for Peace.” Almost two decades before

Doyle, Babst set out to study if “There *have+ been any wars *fought+ between independent freely

elected governments,” a hypothesis that had been arrived at “purely impressionistically.”17 The latter

claim is rather puzzling given the international context at the time of Babst’s writing,18 which

basically pitted the free world against the communist bloc – the Cold War was in full swing, with the

1962 Cuba crisis having just recently occurred. Bruce Russett, whose ongoing work takes democratic

peace research out of the context of the Cold War and explores its use for the Post-Cold-War world,

extends Babst’s concerns: “Why Democratic Peace?”19 Thomas Risse paraphrases Russett: “Why is

that the ‘security dilemma’ appears to be far less significant when democracies deal with each other,

while it seems to govern their interactions with authoritarian systems?”20 Critically engaging the

democratic peace within the context of a broader discussion on the causes of war, Hidemi Suganami

describes the program’s substantive concern as being about the relative frequency of war

occurrence. “Under what sort of circumstances have wars occurred more frequently?”21

Notice how these are in fact different questions. Some are obviously complementary. Thus,

Babst’s and Russett’s questions complement each other in a neat chronological way: settle the facts

13

Compare Kurki 2008. 14

Jackson 2010, xxx. 15

Doyle 1983a,b. 16

Doyle 1983a, 206. Elsewhere, Doyle recounts that, in publishing “Liberal Legacies,” he had wanted to demonstrate Kant’s infamous peace essay “could be constructed as a coherent explanation of two important regularities in world politics: the tendencies of liberal states simultaneously to be peace-prone in their relations with each other and unusually war-prone in their relations with nonliberal states. Cf. Doyle 1996, 358. 17

Babst 1964, 9. 18

Cf. Macmillan 2004, 489. 19

Russett 1993, chapter 2. 20

Risse 1995, xxx. Look up (p. 23 in the reprinted version in the Geeraerts and Stouthuysen collection.) 21

Suganami 1996, 6.

Democratic Peace/Cold War - Chapter 1

4

first, account for them second. Doyle’s and Suganami’s questions, however, suggest more holistic

concerns. Both are out to paint a picture of a “whole” of which Babst’s and Russett’s inquiries can be

seen to be a “part.” But they are different wholes: the study of liberalism, on the one hand, and the

study of war, on the other. From liberalism’s perspective (as Doyle depicts it), one should find it a

pity that the democratic peace is so easily subsumed within a study of war occurrence (as Suganami

not incorrectly frames it). With Doyle, the liberal peace concerned both the use of military force and

international redistributive justice. He gestured toward Galtung’s notion of a positive peace. After

Doyle, the focus narrowed down again to a concern for international security only. Recently,

however, its range has broadened again from a mere democratic peace to the exploration of a more

general democratic distinctiveness.22 Increasingly, democracy is believed to be positively correlated

to trade interdependence, to institution-building, and to peace “proper”; and these four elements

are seen to be involved in a virtuous circle of mutual reinforcement.23 Clearly, there is no full

consensus on what it is that we are explaining. However, to the extent that the object of inquiry is

peace “proper,” which it is largely, then scholars do conceive of it in negative terms. Democratic

peace concerns the absence of war.

Note, further, that while the democratic peace is perhaps true, its significance is contested in

multiple ways. Thus, David Spiro has argued that democracies do indeed not fight each other, but

that this cannot be statistically significant because of the low numbers of democracies in the

international system and because of the low numbers of wars that occur anyway. Spiro argues, in

other words, that “the distribution of wars among democracies is not statistically different from that

which is generated by random chance.”24 This is not to say that leaders of democratic countries

throw the dice to decide on war, but it does imply, says Spiro, that the search for a theory of

democratic peace is ill-founded. The reason is that there is nothing surprising to explain; there is no

puzzle.25 Spiro’s mode of argumentation is technical in nature. It fights fire with fire, statistics with

(presumably) ever better statistics. Unsurprisingly, a statistical back and forth26 has ensued, which

Chernoff applauds as (one of the elements) signaling the possibility of meaningful dialogue toward

consensus, and thus of progress in studying international relations.27 It is nonetheless noticeable that

Chernoff does not discuss those contributions to the democratic peace debate that voice a more

22

Geis and Wagner 2010 ; Owen 2004. 23

Russett and ONeal 2001. 24

Spiro 1996a, 215. 25

Spiro believes that scholars should be paying more attention to explaining the habit of democracies to ally with one another more than other regime types do. This finding, he maintains, would be significant. Cf., Spiro 1996a, 231. 26

Russett 1996; Spiro 1996b. 27

Chernoff 2004.

Democratic Peace/Cold War - Chapter 1

5

radical critique still, either because they think that the very observation does not hold,28 or because

they question its theoretical and political contextualization.29

Ido Oren, for example, states vigorously that “*it+ is the empirical claim of a democratic peace

that I challenge *…+” and he does so from the perspective of a “historical sociology of knowledge.”30 If

one does not define democracy trans-historically, as Oren thinks one should not, but rather defines it

as was habitual at the time of a given conflict, then the democratic peace falters. Moreover, when

war breaks out, countries are often redefined as democracies depending on whose side of the

conflict they are on. Weimar Germany, for instance, was only defined as a non-democracy when war

broke out in 1914, and only securely so when the United States intervened in the war in 1917. Tarak

Barkawi and Mark Laffey, for their part, argue that the democratic peace, as the likes of Doyle and

Russett describe it, does not take the relevant historical context into account. Most democratic

peace research approaches its object from the inside-out, so that “the relevant context” is the

national context of each state. However, according to Barkawi and Laffey, it is more appropriate to

reason from the outside-in, and to embed the “fact of the democratic peace” within a holistic story

of world social development. Capitalism is an unfolding process which has bred states, which orders

the relations between states, and which fosters, via what Kautsky described as the mechanism of

“ultraimperialism,”31 the observed peace among democracies as an epiphenomenon. In the same

process, war with, and the economic exploitation of, non-democracies comes about.32

In fact, more than directly engaging the debate over the causes of the democratic peace (on

which more below), these contributions add up to a re-description of its explanandum. An

explanandum is a description (!) of a state of affairs that begets a concern for explanation.33 Re-

describing that same state of affairs, i.e., re-describing the facts, likely leads one to different kinds of

explanations and probably the very description of the fact constitutes a large part of its explanation.

Consider Oren’s re-description of the democratic peace as a “peace of our kind” and Barkawi and

Laffey’s re-description of it as an “imperial peace.” Discovering a “peace of our kind” suggests that

this peace is the outcome of the dialectical logic of self-other relationships and, therefore, points to

social identity theory as a source of theoretical inspiration (which Oren himself gives an explicitly

materialist, “exogenous-interest-based” grounding). Moreover, it would lead one to expect that

28

Oren 1996. 29

Barkawi and Laffey 1999. 30

Oren 1996, 265, 296. 31

Kautsky 1914. 32

Barkawi and Laffey 1999. 33

As such it is different from « naming » the dependent variable.

Democratic Peace/Cold War - Chapter 1

6

different “kinds” could manipulate a state of peace as well. Developed socialist states, for example.34

Or how about a peace of the umma?35 Discovering an “imperial peace,” on the other hand, implies a

Marxist approach and would question the possibility of extending the democratic peace by making

more countries democratic since the political-economic process of global capitalism takes

precedence over the desire for, and thus actually impedes the possibility of, democratization.36

Clearly, the work of Oren and that of Barkawi and Laffey upsets Chernoff’s assessment of

progress. As in different Kuhnian paradigms37, the same concept does, it turns out, mean quite

different things to different researchers. “*The] notion that there is but one ‘Democratic Peace’ no

longer holds water.”38 As a result, it is unsurprising to find that these alternative accounts are not

referred to in Chernoff’s evaluation, nor are they engaged with in Russett’s and Oneal’s “Kantian”

reformulation of the democratic peace. They are simply not mentioned.39 In some ways, this is a pity

because, as I will argue below, it impairs a full appreciation of the politics of the democratic peace.

Still regarding its explanandum, it is important to stress that the democratic peace is

conceived of as a dyadic datum. This means, foremost, that democracies are not inherently peaceful.

The monadic thesis exists, but it has largely been disproven empirically. Democratic states have

fought wars, just not with other democracies. There is near consensus on this, but the occasional

dissident does exist. Thus, John Macmillan intelligently advances the argument that a democracy is

not necessarily a singularly “liberal state.” Rather, he speaks of liberally inclined people or politicians,

or of liberal “agencies” within the state. If one disaggregates “the democratic state” in one’s analysis

of conflict situations – also with non-democracies – one finds that liberals have consistently been

34

Oren and Hayes1997. 35

Moses 2006. 36

For this very reason, Heikki Patomäki argues for the necessity of scaling up the process of democratization to the world-political level in the form of a global security community. Cf. Patomäki 2002, chapter 8. While disagreeing with Patomäki on the nature of global democracy, Beate Jahn is nonetheless developing a similar argument concerning the political economy of democratization. Cf. Jahn 2010. 37

In a recent discussion, Patrick Jackson and Daniel Nexon argue that the vocabulary of paradigms is inappropriate for describing the state of theoretical disagreement in International Relations Theory. Unlike paradigmatic contenders, proponents of different theories can meaningfully communicate with each other, as becomes obvious, amongst others from the debate over absolute and relative gains. Katzenstein’s and Sil’s call for “analytical eclecticism” likewise contradicts the existence of mutually exclusive paradigms. However, toward the end of their article, Jackson and Nexon do entertain the possibility that on epistemological and methodological issues, there might in fact be paradigmatic faultlines in International Relations Theory. Cf. Jackson and Nexon 2009, 919; Katzenstein and Sil 2008. 38

Macmillan 2004, 490. 39

Even more striking, given their aspiration to initiate work on a critical theory of democratic peace, is that Geis and Wagner (2010) do not refer to them neither.

Democratic Peace/Cold War - Chapter 1

7

pushing for the more peaceful solution.40 Macmillan’s liberal peace is monadic, the democratic peace

is dyadic.

As a dyadic observation, the democratic peace is not only not monadic, but neither is it a

feature of the international system. Consider the difference. In line with Suganami’s description of

the democratic peace as a theory of the relative frequency of the occurrence of war, and reminiscent

of Durkheim’s sociological interest in the distribution of suicide, Zeev Maoz and Bruce Russett have

stated that they “want to explain patterns of conflict.”41 Taken into account that a system, or society,

is sometimes defined as a “patterned arrangement,”42 it would seem that a structural description –

not only explanation – of the democratic peace should be possible. Such an account would have to

theorize, in Hobbesian terms, a “state of peace”: its nature, its causes, its internal and external

constitution, its dynamics. Arguably, Doyle actually conceived of his project in these terms, remarking

that “the thesis *he+ drew from Kant focused on a state of peace distinguishing liberal relations from

the state of war characterizing liberal-nonliberal and nonliberal-nonliberal relations.”43 However, in

spite of these provocative suggestions, and a recent article-length attempt notwithstanding,44 no

existing analysis of the democratic peace is actually systemic in such a thick, might I say Waltzian,

sense. The democratic peace is thickly dyadic in that it conceives of every specific relationship as a

freestanding entity. Relationships are in a “state”, they are not seen to be embedded in a more

encompassing systemic “state.” What’s more, every year that a specific relationship endures counts

as a separate observation. Hence, not only are the relationship between France and the United

States and that between Great Britain and the United States theorized to be independent

relationships, but also the relationships between Great Britain and the United States in 1980 and

1981 are considered to be separate ones. “Society” and “history,” in short, are absent from the

explanandum. Sovereign states, which seemingly exist ex nihilo, interact one-on-one, and the sum of

all this interaction remains just that: a vast set of one-on-one interactions. This is a thoroughly un-

sociological conception.

In a review article, perhaps too uncompromising to be appealing, Sebastian Rosato has

pushed this argument a bit further still, observing that the logic of the democratic peace is really a

monadic one, even if the observation is not.45 Rosato situates his remark in the debate on the

explanation of the democratic peace, but it pertains to its explanandum no less. True enough, the

40

Macmillan 1996. 41

Maoz and Russett 1993, 628. 42

E.g., Merton xxx, 370. Here, Merton is defining his notion of social structure. 43

Doyle 1996, 360 (italics in original). He concludes: “War or peace are thus merely indicators of the ‘states’ that permit them.” 44

Harrison 2004. 45

Rosato 2005, 467.

Democratic Peace/Cold War - Chapter 1

8

dependent variable of democratic peace research is “war,” or, alternatively “militarized interstate

disputes” defined as “a set of interactions between or among states involving threats to use military

force, displays of force, or actual uses of force.”46 Empirical descriptions of a dispute must, by

definition, feature more than one party, and hence, they are dyadic. It takes two to tango. However,

the theoretical description of war – that description which presents itself as puzzling – is, in fact,

monadic. What ultimately interests democratic peace researchers is not “war” as something that

exists as a patterned distribution in the system (pace Suganami), or as the carrier/exponent of a

system of inter-subjective meaning,47 but rather war as a foreign policy choice. A dyad is at war when

each side decides either to initiate war or to resist prior aggression. War is theorized as interaction

and, allegedly, it can neatly be decomposed into, or rationally reconstructed as, a set of actions and

reactions. What demands explanation, then, is every instance and reiteration of this decision, all of

which are held (theoretically) to be independent from each other. In case of the democratic peace, it

specifically concerns the decision to avoid fighting war in spite of being caught in a situation of

(possibly intense) conflict.48

And puzzling this is, or so we are told. After all, is not international relations the realm of

repetition and recurrence, where morality has no place and where war is a constant possibility? On

first inspection, the cumulative findings of democratic peace research prove this traditional realist

thesis wrong.49 And herein lies, arguably, its particular attraction. However, on closer inspection, the

case is not that obvious, nor that compelling. First, realist scholars have advanced their own theory of

the democratic peace. Given the material, power-political, circumstances in which inter-democratic

interaction has unfolded, realist theory would allegedly predict peace between democracies.50

Second, in the way that war is theorized in democratic peace scholarship, i.e., as a constantly re-

iterated decision, war does in fact not generally disqualify as a reasonable foreign policy option. It is

only argued that there is a growing recognition in democracies that violence is not necessary; it is

safe not to wage war, so to speak, since fellow democracies are for various reasons not seen to

constitute a physical threat51. However, nowhere is it argued that war has become unreasonable in

their mutual relationships. What is theorized, in other words, is war avoidance in certain dyadic

relations, not the absence of war as an emergent property of these relations. As such, the

democratic peace surprisingly resembles a realist theory of war. Third, I would like to suggest that

46

Maoz and Russett 1993, 628. 47

Cf. Bull 1995, chapter 8. 48

Kinsella 2005, 455. 49

Doyle 1983a, 218-224. 50

Farber and Gowa 1996; Rosato 2003, 599-600. 51

Zinnes 2004, 436. “*…+ states that use bargaining to solve societal problems can only afford to use bargaining to settle international conflicts if they are not threatened [in their security+.”

Democratic Peace/Cold War - Chapter 1

9

proponents of the democratic peace are, in a certain way, getting realism wrong. That is to say, they

are getting Waltz wrong. After all, Waltz has stated time and again that his is no theory of foreign

policy, but one of international relations.52 Waltz was a Parsonian concerned with the problem of

order. He was a sociologist.53 Research into the democratic peace, on the contrary, re-interprets

realism as a theory of foreign policy, and finds it, unsurprisingly, inadequate; an assessment that

Waltz would probably agree with. If the democratic peace really wants to challenge realism, it

should, therefore, engage realism at the systems level. It should become “an observation in

sociology”: a fact still, but of a different kind – a social fact perhaps –, and calling for a different

explanation.

2.2. Causes and action

Often, it is claimed with respect to the democratic peace, that there are “many data, but little

explanation”54; i.e., empirically virtually uncontested, but theoretically weak. I doubt this because

good empirical research is not possible without sound theoretical backing. Therefore, if research on

the democratic peace is judged to be empirically strong, then it cannot, by fiat, be argued to rest on

theoretical quicksand. Remember, in this respect, that Michael Doyle, and increasingly Bruce Russett,

relate the democratic peace to Kantian political theory; not the worse basis to work from, even if,

arguably, they are getting Kant wrong.55 Moreover, its earlier theoretical weakness has spawned

innovative (e.g., game-theoretical) theorizing.56 Therefore, it is important to discuss the causal, or

explanatory, claims that are being made. What causes the democratic peace?

Note foremost that a rather weak claim is being advanced. The argument is emphatically not

that democracy alone causes peace. According to Doyle, for example, “republican representation, an

ideological commitment to human rights, and transnational interdependence are the causal

mechanisms of the explanation,” likening them to the “constitutional, international, and

cosmopolitan” articles of Kant’s peace treaty, and insisting that the “three causes explained liberal

peace and liberal war when, and only when, combined.”57 Similarly, Maoz and Russett have claimed

that – obviously – other factors (not in the least political realist or geopolitical ones: contiguity,

balance of power, etc.) play their part in pacifying an international relationship, but, if one controls

52

E.g., Waltz 1979, 48-49. 53

Goddard and Nexon 2005. 54

Müller and Wolff 2006. 55

Baum 2008; Behnke 2009; Cavallar 2001; Jahn 2005; Macmillan 1995. More on Kant and the Democratic Peace is to follow in the second chapter. 56

E.g., Bueno de Mesquita, Morrow, Siverson and Smith, 1999. 57

Doyle 2005, 463.

Democratic Peace/Cold War - Chapter 1

10

for these factors, one nonetheless discovers that democracy has some autonomous influence on

peace. Not much perhaps, but still some: “All the theories competing with that about democracy find

solid support. Nevertheless, a strong, independent, and fairly robust role for joint democracy remains

evident.”58 In like fashion, Slantchev, Alexandrova and Gartzke submit that even if a theory (in casu,

the theory that holds that democracies can signal their resolve better) only holds true in 10% of the

cases, it should not be discarded, because they are an important 10%.59 Universally valid in practice,

the democratic peace remains probabilistic in theory. Its causal claims are mild ones. Consequently, I

am not interested in suggesting yet another rival hypothesis, let alone suggesting a mono-causal

alternative.60 Rather, I’ll focus on how, in its causal accounts, democratic peace scholarship conceives

of the concept of causal explanation, and what it conceives causes to be. My argument will be that

underlying one’s understanding of causal explanation lies a theory of action. In case of the

democratic peace, this theory is (predominantly) that of rational choice.

Consider, first, Doyle’s original contribution. Remember that his argument concerns the role

of “liberalism in world politics”61: “What difference do liberal principles and institutions make to the

conduct of the foreign affairs of liberal states?”62 It is Y-centered, so to speak, and could in many

ways be recast as an ideal-typical analysis of the workings of “liberalism” in world politics. Given a

certain definition of “liberalism,” this is how (i.e., peacefully) one expects it to unfold. If it does not,

this is not because of a flaw in the analysis but because there are countervailing forces in the world,

which impede the unconstrained unfolding of liberalism. As a result, in relations with nonliberal

states, and because of them, the condition of anarchy prevails, the security dilemma perseveres, and,

war will, ultimately, ensue.63 The causal challenge, for Doyle, is to theorize liberalism’s agency. Can

states be liberal? Can even people? How does one know that when a state or a person is acting, that

it is acting on its liberal personality or inclination? Or, is liberalism the designation of a set of

institutional arrangements that enable and constrain otherwise “normal” states and people to act in

various ways? If so, what institutional arrangements count as liberal? Do they exist domestically and

internationally? And, again, if so, are they of necessity compatible at these different levels? In other

words, what is liberalism and what kind of a cause is it?

I restrict myself to a discussion of these issues in the two best-known causal models of

democratic peace: the normative and the structural; paralleling Doyle’s “principles” and

58

Maoz and Russett 1993, 632. 59

Slantchev, Alexandrova, and Gartzke 2005, 460. 60

This is Rosato’s flaw. Cf. Rosato 2003. 61

Doyle 1986. 62

Doyle 1983a, 206. 63

Doyle 1983b, part vi.

Democratic Peace/Cold War - Chapter 1

11

“institutions” respectively. The latter is also called the “institutional” explanation and it is garnering

increasing support.64 The normative model hypothesizes that “states, to the extent possible,

externalize the norms of behavior that are developed within and characterize their domestic political

processes and institutions.”65 Within their domestic realm democracies settle their disputes through

peaceful means, i.e., in the final analysis, by means of regular and free elections which entail, in case

of electoral loss, the possibility of a return on the scene with the next election. The model is

“normative” because, underlying the behavioral norm, there is a deeper norm, that of “live and let

live.”66 Preferably, it is argued, democracies will act peacefully in their external relations as well. But

with non-democracies, they cannot take this risk. Given the violence that (supposedly) is habitual

within non-democracies, where conflict is a zero sum game, the safe bet is to assume that non-

democracies will behave aggressively toward outsiders as well, and to harness yourself against them.

Naiveté in relations with non-democracies is ill-advised. In relations with democracies there can be

no naiveté because they are trustworthy after all.

Note that this is a very thin “normative” model. First, there is mention of a deeper norm, but

the real assurance of the behavioral norm being observed internally (which is the starting point of

the model) seems to come from the strategic consideration that an electoral failure does not mean

that all is lost. Notice also that, in the model, there are no norms at the international level. Norms, to

the extent they matter, originate at the domestic level and remain firmly lodged there. There are no

emergent norms, nor are there original international norms. This is most obvious in the way “live and

let live” is taken into account. This deeper norm plays no role in the external relations of states.

Whereas (perhaps) the deeper norm explained the behavioral norm (i.e., peacefulness) in the

domestic realm, in the international realm, the behavioral norm is adhered to only because it fits

(and determines) “rational cost-benefit calculations.”67 The internal observance of a norm fosters an

expectation regarding external behavior in the perception of outsiders, which expectation (of

peacefulness) “lowers the relative benefit to be achieved from violence.” The model is really “tit-for-

tat” with “tit” being cooperative, or at least non-violent, because it is assumed to be a safe bet.

The structural model of democratic peace starts from the observation that decision-making

in democratic states plays itself out in a very different institutional context than in non-democracies.

The most significant difference is that in a non-democracy, the executive has to seek and mobilize

support from a broad swath of actors before it can embark on action: bureaucracies, the legislature,

interest groups, and, not in the least, the public. As a result, decision-making would be slow even if

64

Russett 2009, 21. 65

Maoz and Russett 1993, 625. 66

Mazo and Russett 1993, 625. 67

Maoz and Russett 1993, 625.

Democratic Peace/Cold War - Chapter 1

12

not a single one of the different actors are in principle opposed to war. Due to the slow pace of

democratic decision-making, diplomats of democracies in an inter-democratic dispute tend to have

more time to settle the disputes their respective governments are engaged in before war breaks out.

In relations with non-democracies, on the other hand “the non-democracy imposes on the

democratic political system emergency conditions enabling the government to rally support rather

rapidly.”68

Bruce Russett, who (with Zeev Maoz) first proposed to tell the two models apart, has recently

remarked that the distinction between them is “somewhat arbitrary.”69 I would argue that the two

models are distinct indeed but only superficially so. The reason is that both assume the same model

of action and, as such, the same model of causation. But this remains implicit. What is lacking is an

explicit theory of (state) action, even if an implicit theory of action is doing all the work: it informs the

explanandum and it does the explaining. My argument is that in both models rational, conscious,

will-driven action of atomic agents is the cause of the democratic peace. Democracy causes to the

extent that it is an institutional setting which constrains (and enables) action as an outside force, i.e.,

by means of an external manipulation of the rational cost-benefit calculus. So do all the other

“independent variables”: wealth, growth, alliances, contiguity, and capability ratio. A democratic

agent is a rationally calculating agent operating in a democratic setting; a liberal agent, a rationally

calculating agent operating in a liberal setting. Admittedly, in the case of the institutional model,

Bueno de Mesquita (and associates) has made his model of action explicit, and labeled it (correctly)

rational choice.70 However, the normative model is premised no less on rational choice

considerations. Of it, a benevolent reading would disclose a different understanding of action and

causation to be operative in the domestic realm, but not in foreign policy. The democratic peace, in

other words, is complicit in the neo-neo-synthesis.71 There is no constructivist theory of the

democratic peace because there is no constructivist conceptualization of the phenomenon nor of its

causes; neither, then, of liberalism as its cause.

A cause is something that brings something else about, or that prevents something else from

coming about. The rational choice model of action as cause assumes action to be an efficient cause

only. Aristotle’s sculptor is an efficient cause. Aristotle mentioned material causes (the marble),

formal causes (the statue’s shape), and final causes (e.g., display of wealth or religious symbolism) as

well. A constructivist-causal analysis of the democratic peace would have to factor in these types of

68

Mazo and Russett 1993, 626. 69

Russett 2009, 20. 70

Bueno de Mesquita, Morrow, Siverson and Smith, 1999. 71

Compare Waever 1996.

Democratic Peace/Cold War - Chapter 1

13

causes too (if conceivable).72 In the social world, which is a world of humans, this means that one

adds to an interpretation of action as efficient cause an understanding (and theorization) of agency

as material, formal, and final cause. When Doyle explains that “liberals have indeed established a

separate peace – but only among themselves,”73 it would appear that, given sufficient imagination,

Aristotle’s four causes could be put to work and that liberalism could become a formal or telic cause.

The democratic peace would become a statue that we proudly behold, observe with curiosity, or spit

on in disgust. But in existing democratic peace research, there is no statue to behold. As argued in

the discussion of its explanandum, the democratic peace does not exist as an emergent or

autonomous entity. It exists only as an epiphenomenon of individual and uncoordinated (state)

action. Internationally, presumably, there is neither matter, nor form, nor a telos. Liberals did not

establish anything – rather something came about. The democratic peace, it appears, is an

consequence, but not one that was sought after, of rational action operating as an efficient cause.

Probably, Aristotle could not even have conceived of an efficient cause separate from the three other

forms of causes. He surely would not have considered it an explanation of anything. For Aristotle,

democratic peace research would have been meaningless.

I want to conclude this account of the debate on the democratic peace – of its explanandum

and its explanans – by arguing that the real debate concerning the democratic peace should be one

of social-theoretical conceptualization. The democratic peace is an observation in social science and,

therefore, its grounding lies in social theory. The most fundamental challenge in social theory is that

of theorizing agency. What is action? What does it mean to act? Consider the democratic peace.

Wars would not happen if no one acted. Without action, no war. Without action neither the absence

of war or diplomacy. Without action, no nothing. States cannot act. People can. But sometimes

people act as agents of states. And perhaps states, like people, can enact, or act out. Via the

(physical) agency of individual people, states can enact war, or peace for that matter. Different

theories of action, make for different theories, and different facts, of democratic peace. Social theory

should be the locus of the theoretical debate on democratic peace. Chapter 2 develops a sociological

theory of democratic peace on the basis of a theory of agency as the enactment (or performance) of

social practices. Section 3 of this chapter, its last section, answers the inevitable charge – i.e., “So

what?” – by inquiring into the politics of the democratic peace.

3. The politics of the democratic peace

72

Kratochwil 2008, 450-451 ; Onuf 2009, 188. 73

Doyle 1986, 1156.

Democratic Peace/Cold War - Chapter 1

14

On its own terms, the democratic peace has been a story of unremitting scientific success. According

to sound Enlightenment reason, scientific progress ought to contribute to moral and societal

progress. According to this rule, in political science, the Baconian adage applies: “scientia propter

potentiam.” Of course, Enlightenment reason need not be sound. Opinions differ. The promise of the

Enlightenment, epitomized and driven by the promise of science, could well prove false.74 Bruce

Russett, for one, has turned his gaze inwards. He recognizes that scientific findings, when fed into the

real world of politics, have consequences that were neither foreseen, nor desired, by the scientific

community, let alone the individual scientist. The truth of the democratic peace having been invoked

as a post factum justification of the invasion of Iraq, Russett reports that he feels much like the

atomic scientists must have felt after the bombing of Hiroshima and Nagasaki in 1945: powerless and

betrayed because their scientific knowledge had been perverted for political purposes.75 And yet, if

the democratic peace is true, it should be spoken. “E pur si muove,” murmured Galileo. “And yet it

moves,” declares Russett.76 What’s more, from before Iraq the policy implications of the democratic

peace have always been part of the agenda, and part of the attraction of its scholarship. Implications

for policy were a selling chip. Note that Russett himself subtitled his 1993 book Principles for a Post-

Cold War World. If the democratic peace is true indeed, shouldn’t we be embarking on a policy of

democratization? Of regime change? By force if need be? What does it mean to democratize? What

does it take? Can every state and people be democratized? Shouldn’t it be possible? Peace is at

stake. This is one dimension of the politics of the democratic peace.77

A second dimension concerns the so-called democratic or liberal wars: wars fought, or

violence committed, for reasons that only liberal actors would have. Just think of the plentiful

tradition of liberal imperialism in this respect.78 However, when traditional democratic peace

scholarship discusses the war-proneness of democracies in relation with non-democracies,

responsibility for the outbreak of war is rarely assigned to the democracies. Anarchy retains its

Hobbesian logic, and war accordingly ensues, because non-democracies cannot be trusted. The

autocracies are to blame, and if not they, then anarchy is. In no way are democracies. Historically,

critics maintain, this position is not tenable. The democratic peace is political, from this perspective,

because it carries out (wittingly) a biased research agenda. Violence that is specifically liberal or

democratic in origin is systematically ignored in the empirical analyses and left unaccounted for in

the theoretical explanations.

74

Horkheimer and Adorno 2002. 75

Russett 2005, 369. 76

Russett 1996. 77

For a concise but to-the-point discussion of this dimension, cf. de Wilde 2011. 78

Geis, Brock and Müller 2006; Howard 2008.

Democratic Peace/Cold War - Chapter 1

15

Similarly, research into the democratic peace fails to theorize democracy adequately.

Because it consistently reasons from the inside out, democracy remains firmly lodged at the

domestic level. As a result, however, democratic peace scholarship fails to perceive, let alone

theorize, the lack of global democracy, the resurgence of intrastate violence, and the connection

between these two.79 Its “ontological conservatism” is empirically inadequate and politically

nefarious in the age of (distinctively capitalist) globalization, say some.

Notice that democratic peace scholarship cannot deal with any of these dimensions from

within its original design. Concerning the specifics of its implications for international security policy,

the democratic peace is clueless if it does not take recourse to theories of comparative

democratization.80 What’s more, on its own, the theory is not without danger because it holds the

promise of a solution where it cannot give any direction as to how to get from here to there. We

might as well opt for a quick fix and impose democracy by force; which is of course exactly what

happened even if no single scholar ever imagined it or even if all of them consistently opposed the

option from the start.81 The second dimension, for its part, largely undermines the democratic

peace’s normative attraction. Not only is the promise difficult to attain, its attainment could be less

promising than we are led on to believe. As a result, it cannot answer these charges of political bias

adequately without initiating a fundamental, and self-transforming, overhaul. The third dimension,

finally, imagines a world that traditional democratic peace simply cannot imagine. Exactly because it

cannot deal satisfactorily with any of these dimensions, calls to develop of a “critical theory of the

democratic peace”82 have recently been voiced.

These three dimension of the politics of the democratic peace are valid and challenging

observations. Yet none of them, except perhaps the third, are informed by the social-theoretical

considerations that entertained the previous section. But there is a fourth dimension which does. It is

concerned not so much with the politics of the democratic peace, as it is with the conception of

politics in the democratic peace. At the outset of this chapter, I stated that the democratic peace is

an “observation in political science.” Of modern political science, Jürgen Habermas has written that it

was established on “the model of the modern experimental sciences, having little more than its

name in common with the old politics.”83 The difference he notes is in part methodological and in

part substantive. Modern political science believes in the possibility of, and searches for, secure

79

Macmillan 2004. 80

As does, e.g., Russett 2005. 81

Russett 1993, 396. « The modelof ‘fight them, beat them, and make them democratic’ is irrevocably flawed as a basis for contemporary action. » 82

Geis and Wagner 2010. 83

Habermas 1973, 41.

Democratic Peace/Cold War - Chapter 1

16

knowledge of “the laws and compacts” that govern social life. Classical politics defined its capacity

restrictedly as a “prudential understanding of the situation.”84 In this chapter, I have hardly touched

upon methodology. Notice, though, that an evaluation of democratic peace research along classical

lines, and specifically its perversion in political practice, would not lay blame with the politicians that

pervert, but with the hubris of the scientist. It is not the specifics, or the substance, of their

knowledge that lends itself to perversion but its nature and the status that scholars assign to it. The

second difference that Habermas identifies concerns the definition of (the domain of) politics as a

field of action. Modern political science focuses upon decision-making by a governmental apparatus

(states or functional equivalents). Conceptually, The political is divorced from the cultural, the legal,

and the societal. To be sure, political decision-makers are theorized, and advised, to factor into their

decisions and, as such, into their actions, sentiments from “the public” and constraints from “the

law”, but the “public” and the “law” are seen to exist as separate entities. Applied to democratic

peace research, this means that politics is conceptualized as a set of policies that are decided upon

by foreign policy elites (cf. the first dimension), and this foreign policy elite is taken to stand in a

strategic relationship with its public, with other bureaucracies, with the law, and with the leaders of

other countries. Ultimately, politics, in existing democratic peace research, is about politicians

wanting to retain their office.85 Compare the classical conception of politics, which saw politics as

being about “the concrete collective life of the city, the customs, the habits and the passions of the

city.”86 Politics, classically conceived, was about the maintenance of the order of the polis. This

comprehensive conception of politics was lost in the eighteenth century, Habermas informs us, ever

since when “the newly emerging social sciences and the discipline of jurisprudence have drawn off

the waters of classical politics.”87

Habermas’ assessment is somewhat too radical if it concerns modern social science as such.

To be sure, the classical conception of politics is lost from contemporary political science, both

methodologically and substantively. Witness the democratic peace. However, traces of the classical

conception are still around in the broader social sciences. I refer, first, to Foucault’s tracing of the rise

of governmentality, which has been a source of methodological and substantive influence for a range

of scholars in the social sciences, also in international relations.88 I refer also to classical, early-

twentieth century sociology, which was centrally concerned with the problem of order in industrial

societies. The beauty of interpreting politics in light of classical sociology is that it brings out most

84

Habermas 1973, 42. 85

Bueno de Mesquita, Morrow, Siverson and Smith 1999. 86

Viroli 1990, 156. 87

Habermas 1973, 41. 88

Foucault 1991 ; Leira 2009 ; Neumann and Sending 2010.

Democratic Peace/Cold War - Chapter 1

17

explicitly that the problem of order becomes (reconstituted as) an experience in modernity. One

expects that classical politics under modern conditions make for a different set of dynamics than do

classical politics in antiquity, both on the level of observation and on that of action.

Now, if the democratic peace presents itself as a transcendence of the security dilemma, as

Thomas Risse suggests89 and thus as a solution to the problem of order,90 then it becomes plausible

to analyze it with the classical conception of politics in mind, and, accordingly, with the tools of

(classical) sociology. A sociological analysis will eventually assist the analysis of its politics, because it

will broaden our understanding of the reach of what its politics are about. Moreover, the need to

broaden this reach is not without empirical referent. Increasingly, politicians and activist-scholars,

not in the least in international law, are blending findings from the democratic peace with practical

designs for future world orders in the shape of a proposed “concert of democracies,” which would be

the “institutional embodiment and ratification of the ‘democratic peace’.”91 Ignorant of the social-

theoretic premises of democratic peace scholarship, and rightfully so, these people elevate the

democratic peace to a systemic phenomenon. Therefore, more than ever, understanding it requires

that we – scholars – theorize democratic peace in systemic terms. Both the object of inquiry, the

underlying conception of action and causation, and the implied conception of politics will alter in the

process. And this should be foregrounded, not remain implicit.

4. Conclusion

I started this chapter by stating that “the democratic peace is an observation in political science.” The

goal in the chapter was to draw out what the significance of this statement is. Perhaps it should be

summarized to mean that “the democratic peace is no observation in sociology.” Throughout, I have

implied that this is regretful. To a certain extent, feelings of regret are subjective. I do not think,

however, that, as a rule, sociology is superior to political science. Yet, in the case of the democratic

peace, my feelings of regret have substantive reasons. The democratic peace holds a particular

attraction (a) theoretically, because it promises to undo the dominance of political realism, and (b)

practically, because it promises the possibility of progressive politics in international relations. For

reasons that I have stated above, none of the promises can convincingly be maintained if the

democratic peace does not recast itself in a more sociological mould. This is the task of the next

chapter.

89

Cf. Risse 1995, xxx. 90

Rengger 2000, 112-126. 91

Ikenberry and Slaughter 2006. For a good discussion,see Clark 2009; Geis and Wagner 2010.

Democratic Peace/Cold War - Chapter 1

18

List of references

Babst, Dean. 1964. Elective Governments: A Force for Peace. Wisconsin Sociologist 3 (1): 9–14. Barkawi, Tarak and Mark Laffey. 1999. The Imperial Peace: Democracy, Force, and Globalization. European Journal of International Relations 5 (4): 403-434. Baum, Tomas. 2008. A Quest for Inspiration in the Liberal Peace Paradigm: Back to Bentham? European Journal of International Relations 14 (3): 431-453. Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce, James D. Morrow, Randolph M. Siverson, and Alastair Smith. 1999. An Institutional Explanation of the Democratic Peace. The American Political Science Review 93 (4): 791-807. Bull, Hedley. 1995. The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics. New York: Columbia University Press. Cavallar, Georg. 2001. Kantian Perspectives on Democratic Peace: Alternatives to Doyle. Review of International Studies 27 (2): 229-248. Chernoff, Fred. 2004. The Study of Democratic Peace and Progress in International Relations. International Studies Review 6 (1): 49-77. Clark, Ian. 2009. Democracy in International Society: Promotion or Exclusion. Millennium: Journal of International Studies 37 (3): 563-581. Cox, Robert. 1981. Social Forces, States and World Orders: Beyond International Relations Theory. Millennium: Journal of International Studies 10 (2): 126-155. De Wilde, Jaap. 2011. Xxxx. European Review. Doyle, Michael. 1983a. Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs, Part 1. Philosophy and Public Affairs 12 (3): 202–235. Doyle, Michael. 1983b. Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs, Part 2. Philosophy and Public Affairs 12 (4): 323–353. Doyle, Michael. 1986. Liberalism and World Politics. American Political Science Review 80 (4): 1151-1169. Doyle, Michael. 1996. Reflections on the Liberal Peace and its Critics. In Debating the Democratic Peace: An International Security Reader, edited by Michael Brown, Sean Lynn-Jones, and Steven Miller, 358-363. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

Doyle, Michael. 2005. Three Pillars of the Liberal Peace. American Political Science Review 99 (3): 463-466.

Farber, Henry and Joanne Gowa. 1996. Polities and Peace. In Debating the Democratic Peace: An International Security Reader, edited by Michael Brown, Sean Lynn-Jones, and Steven Miller, 239-262. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

Democratic Peace/Cold War - Chapter 1

19

Foucault, Michel. 1991. Governmentality, trans. Rosi Braidotti and revised by Colin Gordon. In The

Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality, edited by Graham Burchell, Colin Gordon and Peter

Miller, 87–104. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Geis, Anna, Lothar Brock and Harald Müller (eds.). 2006. Democratic Wars: Looking at the Dark Side of the Democratic Peace. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan. Geis, Anna and Wolfgang Wagner. 2008. From Democratic Peace to Democratic Distinctiveness: A Critique of Democratic Exceptionalism in Peace and Conflict Studies. CLPE Research Paper 4 (8): 1-52. Geis, Anna and Wolfgang Wagner. 2010. How far is it from Köningsberg to Kandahar? Democratic Peace and Democratic Violence in International Relations. Review of International Studies (forthcoming). Godard, Stacie and Daniel Nexon. 2005. Paradigm Lost? Reassessing Theory of International Politics. European Journal of International Relations 11 (1): 9-61. Habermas, Jürgen. 1973. Theory and Practice. Boston: Beacon. Harrison, Ewan. 2004. State Socialization, International Norm Dynamics and the Liberal Peace. International Politics 41 (4): 521-542. Horkheimer, Max and Theodor Adorno. 2002. Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical Fragments. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Howard, Michael. 2008. War and the Liberal Conscience. London: Hurst and Company. Ikenberry, G. John and Anne-Marie Slaughter. 2006. Forging a World of Liberty under Law: U.S. National Security in the 21st Century. Princeton Project Papers. http://www.princeton.edu/~ppns/report/FinalReport.pdf. Accessed 19 April 2010. Jackson, Patrick. 2010. The Conduct of Inquiry in International Relations. London: Routledge. Jackson, Patrick and Daniel Nexon. 2009. Paradigmatic Faults in International Relations Theory. International Studies Quarterly 53 (4): 907-930. Jahn, Beate. 2005. Kant, Mill and Illiberal Legacies in Foreign Affairs. International Organization 59 (1): 177-207. Jahn, Beate. 2010. The Political Economy of Democracy Promotion. Paper presented at the 2010 … something ECPR in Münster. Katzenstein, Peter and Rudra Sil. 2008. Eclectic Theorizing in the Study and Practice of International Relations. In Oxford Handbook of International Relations, edited by Christian Reus-Smit and Duncan Snidal, 109-130. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kautsky, Karl. 1914. Ultra-imperialism. Available from http://www.marxists.org/archive/kautsky/1914/09/ultra-imp.htm. Accessed 09 April 2010. Kinsella, David. 2005. No Rest for the Democratic Peace. American Political Science Review 99 (3): 453-457.

Democratic Peace/Cold War - Chapter 1

20

Kratochwil, Friedrick. 2008. Sociological Approaches. In Oxford Handbook of International Relations, edited by Christian Reus-Smit and Duncan Snidal, 444-461. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kurki, Milja. 2008. Causation in International Relations: Reclaiming Causal Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Layne, Christopher. 1996. Kant or Cant: the Myth of the Democratic Peace. In Debating the Democratic Peace: An International Security Reader, edited by Michael Brown, Sean Lynn-Jones, and Steven Miller, 157-201. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

Leira, Halvard. 2009. Taking Foucault Beyond Foucault: Inter-State Governmentality in Early-Modern Europe. Global Society 23 (4): 475-495.

Levy, Jack. 1988. Domestic Politics and War. Journal of Interdisciplinary History 18 (4): 653-673. Macmillan, John. 1995. A Kantian Protest against the Peculiar Discourse of Inter-Liberal State Peace. Millennium: Journal of International Studies 24 (3): 549-562. Macmillan, John. 1996. On Liberal Peace: Democracy, War, and International Order. London: I.B. Tauris. Macmillan, John. 2004. Whose Democracy? Which Peace? Contextualizing the Democratic Peace. International Politics 41 (4): 472-493. Maoz, Zeev and Bruce Russett. 1993. Normative and Structural Causes of Democratic Peace, 1946-1986. The American Political Science Review 87 (3): 624-638. Merton, Robert K. Social Theory and Social Structure. Moses, Jonathan. 2006. The Umma of Democracy. Security Dialogue 37 (4): 489-508. Müller, Harald and Jonas Wolff. 2006. Democratic Peace: Many Data, Little Explanation. In Democratic Wars: Looking at the Dark Side of the Democratic Peace, edited by Anna Geis, Lothar Brock and Harald Müller, 41-73. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan. Neumann, Iver and Ole Jacob Sending. 2010. Governing the Global Polity: Practice, Mentality, Rationality. Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press. Onuf, Nicholas. 1989. World of Our Making: Rules and Rule in Social Theory and International Relations. Columbia, SC: University of South Carolina Press. Onuf, Nicholas. 2009. Structure? What Structure? International Relations 23 (2): 183-199. Oren, Ido. 1996. The Subjectivity of the ‘Democratic’ Peace: Changing U.S. Perceptions of Imperial China. In Debating the Democratic Peace: An International Security Reader, edited by Michael Brown, Sean Lynn-Jones, and Steven Miller, 263-300. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

Oren, Ido and Jude Hays. 1997. Democracies May Rarely Fight One Another, But Developed Socialist States Rarely Fight At All. Alternatives 22 (4): 493–521.

Owen, John. 2004. Democratic Peace Research: Whence and Whither? International Politics 41 (4): 605-617.

Democratic Peace/Cold War - Chapter 1

21

Owen, John. 2005. Iraq and the Democratic Peace. Foreign Affairs 84 (6): 122-127. Patomäki, Heikki. 2002. After International Relations: Critical realism and the (re)construction of world politics. London: Routledge. Rengger, Nicholas. 2000. International Relations, Political Theory and the Problem of Order: Beyond International Relations Theory? London: Routledge. Ringmar, Erik. 2008. Empowerment Among Nations: A Sociological Perspective. In Power in World Politics, edited by Felix Berenskoetter and Mike Williams, 189-203. London: Routledge.

Risse, Thomas. 1995. Democratic Peace – Warlike Democracies: A Social Constructivist Explanation of the Liberal Argument. European Journal of International Relations 1 (4): 491-517.

Rosato, Sebastian. 2003. The Flawed Logic of Democratic Peace Theory. American Political Science Review 97 (4): 585-602.

Rosato, Sebastian. 2005. Explaining the Democratic Peace. American Political Science Review 99 (3): 467-472.

Russett, Bruce. 1996. The Democratic Peace – And Yet It Moves. In Debating the Democratic Peace: An International Security Reader, edited by Michael Brown, Sean Lynn-Jones, and Steven Miller, 337-350. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

Russett, Bruce. 2003. Grasping the Democratic Peace: Principles for the Post-Cold War World. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Russett, Bruce. 2005. Bushwacking the Democratic Peace. International Studies Perspectives 6 (4): 395-408.

Russett, Bruce. 2009. Democracy, War and Expansion through Historical Lenses. European Journal of International Relations 15 (1): 9-36.

Russett, Bruce and John Oneal. 2001. Triangulating Peace: Democracy, Interdependence, and International Organizations. New York: W.W. Norton and Company.

Slantchev, Branislav, Anna Alexandrova, and Erik Gartzke. 2005. Probabilistic Causality, Selection Bias, and the Logic of the Democratic Peace. American Political Science Review 99 (3): 459-462.

Spiro, David. 1996a. The Insignificance of the Liberal Peace. In Debating the Democratic Peace: An International Security Reader, edited by Michael Brown, Sean Lynn-Jones, and Steven Miller, 202-238. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

Spiro, David. 1996b. The Liberal Peace – And Yet It Squirms. In Debating the Democratic Peace: An International Security Reader, edited by Michael Brown, Sean Lynn-Jones, and Steven Miller, 351-354. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

Suganami, Hidemi. 1996. On the Causes of War. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Viroli, Maurizio. 1990. Machiavelli and the republican idea of politics. In Machiavelli and Republicanism, edited by Gisela Bock, Quentin Skinner, and Maurizio Viroli, 143-172. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Waltz, Kenneth. 1979. Theory of International Politics. New York: McGraw-Hill.

Democratic Peace/Cold War - Chapter 1

22

Waltz, Kenneth. 2008. Realism and International Politics. London: Routledge.

Wendt, Alexander. 1999. Social Theory of International Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Waever, Ole. 1996. The Rise and Fall of the Inter-Paradigm Debate. In International Theory: Positivism and Beyond, edited by Steve Smith, Ken Booth and Marysia Zalewski, 149-185. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Zinnes, Dina. 2004. Constructing Political Logic: The Democratic Peace Puzzle. The Journal of Conflict Resolution 48 (3): 430-454.