David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’...

179
BỘ KẾ HOẠCH VÀ ĐẦU TƯ BỘ GIÁO DỤC VÀ ĐÀO TẠO VIỆN NGHIÊN CỨU QUẢN LÝ KINH TẾ TRUNG ƯƠNG LÊ HỒNG GIANG ÐỔI MỚI MÔ HÌNH PHÁT TRIỂN KHU KINH TẾ TRÊN ÐỊA BÀN TỈNH QUẢNG NINH TRONG HỘI NHẬP KINH TẾ QUỐC TẾ LUẬN ÁN TIẾN SĨ KINH TẾ Hà Nội- Năm 2019

Transcript of David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’...

Page 1: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

volume19,no.45 october2019

Normative Perfectionism

and the Kantian Tradition

David O. BrinkUniversity of California San Diego

© 2019 DavidO.BrinkThis work is licensed under a Creative Commons

Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 3.0 License. <www.philosophersimprint.org/019045/>

P erfectionistethicaltheoriesgroundmoraldemandsintheper-fectionorfullrealizationofone’sessentialnature.1Perfection-ismhasarichhistory.PerfectionistideascanbefoundinAristo-

tle,theStoics,Maimonides,Aquinas,Malebranche,Spinoza,Leibniz,vonHumboldt,J.S.Mill,F.H.Bradley,T.H.Green,Nietzsche,andMarx,amongothers.Thoughindividualperfectionistfigureshavereceivedsignificantattention, theirperfectionismhasnotalwaysenjoyedthesame focus.Perfectionismhasnotbeenstudied thoroughlyasadis-tinctivetradition,anditremainsaneglectedoptionincontemporarymoralandpoliticalphilosophy.2Thisneglectmayreflectdoubtsaboutthejustification,content,andimplicationsofperfectionistideals. Differentconceptionsofperfectionismresult fromdifferentcon-ceptions of human nature. Some perfectionists and their critics un-derstandhumannatureasabiologicalkind.However,thatconceptionof perfectionism gives rise to legitimate foundational doubts aboutwhether there isanythingsubstantive that isessential tohumanna-tureandwhether, if there is, itwouldbenormativelycompelling.Adifferentstrandintheperfectionisttraditiongroundsperfectionistide-als inanormative conceptionofhumannatureas involvingpersonal-ityoragency.Normative perfectionismisadistinctiveconceptionwithin

1. Anearlierversionof thismaterialwaspresentedatSheffieldUniversityaspartofa2014conferenceonPost-KantianPerfectionism;a2015UniversityofPennsylvaniaconferenceonAncientandModernConceptionsofHappiness;Ohio and St. Louis Universities; a 2016 UCSD conference, Perfectionism:AncientandModern; theChineseUniversityofHongKong;and the2019PacificDivisionMeetingsoftheAPA.IwouldliketothankmembersofthoseaudiencesandespeciallyKarlAmeriks,AnneMargaretBaxley,ChrisBennett,Alyssa Bernstein, Gwen Bradford, Rosalind Chaplin, Andrew Chitty, Gor-donFinlayson,DanHaybron,TomHurka,Terence Irwin,David James, JanKandiyali,JonathanKnutzen,CharlieKurth,HonLamLi,KathrynLindeman,HendrikLorenz,J.P.Messina,SusanSauvéMeyer,DougMoggach,StephenPalmquist,AndrewPayne,RobertStern,JohnSkorupski,AlanThomas,andEricWatkinsforhelpfulcommentsandinput.Revisionsbenefitedfromtheinputofthreeanonymousreaders.SpecialthanksgotoDonRutherford,withwhomIco-taughtagraduateseminaronancientandmodernperfectionismin2016andfromwhomIhavelearnedmuchabouttheperfectionisttradition.

2. AnimportantexceptiontothisgeneralneglectisThomasHurka,Perfectionism (Oxford:ClarendonPress,1993).ThoughHurka’sprimaryfocusissystematic,hemakesanumberof interestinghistorical claimsabout theperfectionisttradition.

Page 2: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –2– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

andKantianethical traditions.Second, the importanceofautonomyin normative perfection explains why there are special constraintsonhowwecanpromotetheperfectionofanother.ThisperfectionistrecognitionofKantianconcernsisnicelyillustratedinGreen’sbrandofliberalismandinMill’sdefenseofautonomyandskepticismaboutpaternalism.

Seeing how normative perfectionism can answer these Kantianworriesbyappealtomoralpersonalitypavesthewayforseeingper-fectionist strands in Kant’s own ethical theory. Despite his doubtsaboutotherformsofperfectionism,Kantappealstomoralpersonalityasbothgroundandcontentofmoralrequirements,whichisreflectedintheUniversalityandHumanityformulationsoftheCategoricalIm-perative.ThisallowsustoidentifyapossibleperfectionistreadingofKant’sownethicaltheory.

However,becausethenormativeperfectionist,likeKant,groundsmoral requirements in rationalnature, she toomust face theworrythatKantians faceabout the incompleteness of theappeal to rationalnature.HegeliansandothershavecomplainedthatKant’sappeal torational nature to groundmoral requirements is formal and empty.Likewise, ifwe conceiveofmoralpersonality, as thenormativeper-fectionistsdo,intermsofreasons-responsiveness,wemayworrythatthe perfectionist appeal to rational naturemust be incomplete andrequires supplementation with a list of objective goods or reasonsthat can guide rational choice. A radical version of the incomplete-nessworrytreatstheappealtorationalnatureasemptyandwithoutcontent.Bycontrast,amoderateversionoftheincompletenessworrygrantsthattheappealtorationalnaturehascontentbutinsiststhatitprovides incompleteethicalguidanceunlesssupplementedbya listofnon-perfectionistgoodsor reasons.However, theappeal to ratio-nalnaturehascontent,whichmeansthat it is themoderateversionoftheincompletenessworrythatweneedtotakeseriously.Iexploremoreandlessconcessiveperfectionistrepliesthatassignperfectionistelementssmallerandlargerroleswithinthepersonalgood.ThoughIamsympatheticwiththelessconcessivepositionstakedoutbypure

theperfectionisttradition,anditisarguablymorerobustnormativelythanconceptionsappealingtoabiologicalconceptionofhumanna-ture.Aristotle,J.S.Mill,andT.H.Greenarenormativeperfectionistsandmakedistinctivecontributionstothattradition.3 Wecanbegintoredresstheneglectoftheperfectionisttraditionbyreconstructingandassessingtheessentialsof thisnormativeper-fectionisttradition.PartofthattaskinvolvesengagingKantiandoubtsaboutperfectionism.Kantwasacriticofperfectionism,anditisworthconsideringtheprospectsofnormativeperfectionismtoaddresshisconcerns.4Kantmakestwokindsofcriticismofperfectionismthatde-serveourattention.First,thereishisworry,especiallyintheGround-work and the Critique of Practical Reason, that the perfectionist andeudaimonist traditions must be heteronomous and cannot expressrequirements of practical reason.Groundingmoral requirements inperfectionistideals,Kantclaims,generateshypothetical, rather than cat-egorical, imperatives.Second,thereisKant’sclaimintheMetaphysics of Moralsthatwemustacceptamoral asymmetryinwhichweaimatourownperfectionbutatthehappiness,ratherthantheperfection,ofoth-ers. Indefenseof thisasymmetry,heargues thatperfectinganothersubvertstheother’sstatusasarationalagent.Iwanttoexplorethehistoricalandsystematicresourcesofnormativeperfectionismtoaddresstheseworries.First,insofarasthenormativeperfectionistgroundsperfectionistidealsinthenormativecategoryofpersonalityoragency,ratherthanabiologicalcategoryofhumanity,itcanrepresentperfectionistdemandsascategoricalimperatives.Thisis clearest inGreen,who self-consciously tries to synthesizeGreek

3. IfocusonAristotle,Mill,andGreenasexemplarsofnormativeperfectionismbothbecausetheirnormativeperfectionismisreasonablyclearandbecauseI know thembest,notbecause I assume that they are theonlynormativeperfectionists.

4. PartofmyagendaoverlapswiththediscussioninRobertStern,“BritishIdeal-ism”inThe Cambridge History of Moral Philosophy,ed.SachaGolobandJensTimmermann(Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress,2017).Sterndiscuss-esthecontributionsofGreenandBradleyundertheguiseofpost-Kantianperfectionism.

Page 3: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –3– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

claims about the human function, and onemight think that he un-derstandsthehumanfunctioninbiologicalterms.ThomasHurkaisacontemporaryperfectionistwhounderstandstheperfectionistappealtohumannatureasanappealtoabiologicalessenceforhumanbeings,groundingperfectionistgoodssuchasknowledge,creativity,achieve-ment, and athleticism in our biological essence.5 However, ground-ingperfectionistidealsinabiologicalconceptionofhumannatureisproblematicinatleasttwoways.

First,on familiarconceptionsofspeciesmembership, there isnosubstantivehumanessence.6For instance,acommonconceptionofspeciesmembership is reproductive closureor the capacity to inter-breed.Buttheorganismslinkedbyreproductiveclosuredonotpickout aparticular set of phenotypic traits or capacities as essential tohuman beings. Alternatively, speciesmembership is sometimes un-derstoodintermsofcommonlineagewithmembersofthesamespe-ciesallbeingorganismswithacommonancestorwhoaresufficientlysimilargenetically.Butcommonlineagedoesnotpickoutaparticularsetofphenotypictraitsorcapacitiesasessentialtohumanbeings.

Second, neither conception ofHomo sapiens is likely to pick outallandonly thecapacities thatwe thinkofasdistinctlyvaluableornormative.Admirabletraitssuchasrationality,creativity,andsocialityneednotbepossessedtoahighdegreebyallhumanbeingsonrepro-ductiveclosureorcommonlineageconceptionsofourspecies.

Biological conceptionsofhumannaturemight eschewappeal toasubstantiveconceptionofspeciesmembershipandinsteadappealtocharacteristicactivitiesof the species.7However, thechallenge istoidentifyvaluabletraitsthathaveabiologicalbasis.Therearemany

5. Hurka,Perfectionism,esp.chs.2−4.

6. SeePhilipKitcher,“EssenceandPerfection”Ethics110(1999):59−83.Where-asKitcher takes skepticismabout a substantivebiological essence to raisedoubts about perfectionism, I take it tomotivate a form of perfectionismgrounded in a normative, rather than a biological, conception of humannature.

7. Foroneexampleof thisapproach,seePhilippaFoot,Natural Goodness (Ox-ford:ClarendonPress,2001).

perfectionisttheories,eventhemoreconcessiverepliesbymixedthe-ories assignperfectionist ideals an important role.Defending theseclaims takes thenormative perfectionist beyond explicitKantian re-sources,butprovidesadefenseoftheimportanceofrationalnaturethatboththenormativeperfectionistandtheKantianneed.

Finally,it’sworthnotingtheresourcesofnormativeperfectionismtoexplaintherationalauthorityofitsdemands.LikeKant,thenorma-tiveperfectionistgroundsnormativedemandsinournatureasratio-nalagents,whichpromisestodefendtherationalistclaimthatagentshavecategoricalreasonstosatisfyperfectionistdemands.

This discussion of normative perfectionism addresses the inter-sectionof anormativeperfectionist tradition that includesAristotle,Mill,andGreenandtheKantiantradition.Assuch,itinvolvesmanymovingparts,eachofwhichispotentiallyquitecomplex.EveniftheperfectionistreadingofAristotleisreasonablyfamiliar,aperfectionistreadingofMillmay seemheterodox, andGreen’sethicsof self-real-izationisnotfamiliartomanyreaders.GiventhecomplexityofKant’sownethical theory, sucha comparative studymay seemmisguided.However,itispossibletoisolatetheessentialsofthesetwotraditionswithoutsignificantdistortionforcomparativepurposes.Thevalueofcomparingthetwotraditionsandassessingtheirdifferencescompen-satesfortheneedtobeselectiveinthecoverageofeachtradition,orsoIshallargue.Thiscomparativestudyispartofassessingthepros-pectsofnormativeperfectionism.

1. The Essentials of Normative Perfectionism

Thoughtheperfectionisttraditionisheterogeneous,mostperfection-ist theories understand the fundamental ethical demand to be therealizationandperfectionofone’snature.Inthisway,perfectionismrestsonclaimsabouthumannature.Differentperfectionisttheoriesunderstandhumannatureanditsperfectiondifferently.

Itiscommontounderstandclaimsabouthumannatureasinvolv-ingabiological kind—humanbeing.Aristotledefendsaconceptionofeudaimoniaorhappinessthatisaformofperfectionismbyappealto

Page 4: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –4– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

onunderstandinghumannatureasabiologicalkind,thefoundationsofperfectionismappearproblematic.

Amorepromisingwaytogroundperfectionistidealsisbyappealtohumannatureunderstoodasanormative kind,ratherthanasabio-logicalkind.Onthiskindofview,perfectionistidealsarerelative,nottoournatureashumanbeings,buttoournatureaspersonsoragents.Aristotle,Mill,andGreen,Ibelieve,areallnormativeperfectionists.10 Spaceconstraintsprecludereconstructionsofthedetailsoftheirethi-caltheories,butwecanhighlightsomerelevantaspectsoftheirver-sionsofnormativeperfectionismthatbearonthearticulationandde-fenseofnormativeperfectionistessentials.

Aristotle.LikeotherGreekethicists,Aristotleisaeudaimonist,treat-ingtheagent’sowneudaimoniaorhappinessasthecentralorfoun-dationalelementinethics.11 InthefirstbookoftheNicomachean Eth-ics,Aristotle identifiesthefinalgoodwitheudaimoniaorhappinessand recognizes threemain formal constraintsoneudaimonia—thatitmustbe completeor lackingonnothing, that itmustbe suitableforthesortofbeingsweare,andthatitmustbecomparativelystableandwithinourcontrol.12Eudaimonismimpliesperfectionisminsofaras the content of eudaimonia is constrained by assumptions abouthuman nature. Aristotle’s eudaimonism makes him a perfectionistinsofar as he explicitly develops the suitability constraint on eudai-moniabyappeal to thehumanfunction(NE I.7).The functionargu-mentdrawsonthetaxonomyofcharacteristicactivitiesandsoulsinDe Anima.Thoughsometimesinterpretedinbiologicalterms,thattax-

10.AlsoseeDavidO.Brink,“TheSignificanceofDesire”Oxford Studies in Meta-ethics3(2008):5−45.

11. On the eudaimonist assumption, see Gregory Vlastos, Socrates: Ironist and Moral Philosopher (Ithaca:CornellUniversityPress,1991),203.AlsoseeTer-enceIrwin,Plato’s Moral Theory(Oxford:ClarendonPress,1977),esp.51−54,249−80 and Terence Irwin, Plato’s Ethics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995),§§36−37,142.

12. Aristotle,Nicomachean Ethics,trs.TerenceIrwin,2ded.(Indianapolis:Hackett,1999)[NE].IalsodrawselectivelyontheEudemian Ethics,theMagna Moralia, andthePoliticsinThe Revised Oxford Translation of the Complete Works of Aristo-tle,2vols.,ed.JonathanBarnes(Princeton:PrincetonUniversityPress,1984).

traits characteristic of humanity, such as deviousness, cruelty, andschadenfreude,whichdonotseemnormativelysignificant.Toavoidthis problem,wemight appeal instead to valuable or attractive hu-mantraits,suchascooperation,creativity,andfriendship.Butwithoutsomebiologicalgroundforselectingthesetraits,theresultingtheorydoesnotinvolveabiologicalconceptionofhumannature,andtheap-pealtohumannatureseemstodonoexplanatorywork.8

Onepossibility is toappeal tocharacteristiccapacitiesandactivi-tiesof the species thatare theproductofnatural selection.Compli-ance with familiar other-regarding norms of cooperation, honesty,fidelity, fair play, and non-aggression ismutually beneficial, and sothereisacaseforthinkingthatthesecooperativevirtuesmighthavebeen selected forgeneticallyor culturally.But therearemany traitsthatwehavebecause theyconferredselectiveadvantageonouran-cestors inhunter-gatherer tribes that itwouldbeproblematic to re-gardasgoodforusnoworasprovidinguswithreasonsforaction.Forinstance, there issomeevidence thatautomaticaffectivediscrimina-toryattitudestowardoutsidershaveahereditablebasisintheamyg-dalaorprefrontalcortexandlikelyprovedtobeadaptivetraitsforourancestorswholivedinsmallhomogeneoustribalcommunities.9Butthebiologicalbasisofracismandxenophobiadoesnotprovideanor-mativegroundforthosetraits.Ahistoryofselectiveadvantageseemsneithernecessarynorsufficientfornormativesignificance.Ifweinsist

8. AlsoseeDaleDorsey,“ThreeArgumentsforPerfectionism”Noûs44(2010):64−68.

9. See,e.g.,LisaM.Brown,MargaretM.Bradley,andPeter J.Lang,“AffectiveReactionstoPicturesofIngroupandOutgroupMembers”Biological Psychol-ogy71(2006):303−11;MatteoForgiarini,MarcelloGalluci,andAngeloMara-vita,“RacismandtheEmpathyforPainonourSkin”Frontiers in Psychology2(2011):1−7;andMelissaM.McDonald,CarlosDavidNavarrette,andMarkVanVugt, “Evolutionand thePsychologyof IntergroupConflict:TheMaleWarriorHypothesis”Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B367(2012):670−79.Forevidenceofthemalleabilityofstereotypingandprejudicialaffect,seeIreneV.Blair,“TheMalleabilityofAutomaticStereotypesandPrejudice”Personality and Social Psychology Review6(2002):242−61.

Page 5: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –5– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

InOn Liberty, he defends individual rights to basic liberties, but hetellsusthattheseindividualrightshaveautilitarianfoundationbasedon“utilityinthelargestsense,groundedonthepermanentinterestsofmanasaprogressivebeing”(OLI11;CWXVIII224).Thisprogres-siveconceptionofhappiness is reflected in thedistinctionbetweenhigherandlowerpleasuresinUtilitarianism,inwhichhearguesthata lifeexercisingone’s rationalanddeliberativecapacities—Socratesdissatisfied—isdiscontinuously betterthanalifecontainingonlylowerpleasures—thepigor foolsatisfied(U II3–6;CW210−12).Aperfec-tionist readingof thehigherpleasuresdoctrinereceives furthersup-portfromthedignitypassage,inwhichMillexplainsthepreferenceofcompetentjudgesforhigherpleasuresbyappealtotheirsenseofthedignityofalifeofcomplexandhigheractivities(UII6;CWX212).Here,Millclaimsthatitistheperceptionofthevalueoftheseactivitiesthatexplainsthecategoricalpreferencesofcompetentjudges.Aper-fectionistcommitmenttoself-realizationinformsOn Liberty’sdefenseofindividualautonomyandexperimentationinlifestyleasnecessaryand importantaspectsofself-development.This isanormativecon-ceptionofhumannatureandhappiness,because itdependsonourcapacitiesforself-governmentthatMillsaysarerequisiteforourbe-ingresponsibleand,hence,moralagents(A System of LogicVI.ii.3;CW 839−42).Itisthesecapacitiesthatmarkusasprogressivebeings.Mill’sappealstotheseclaimsabouthumannatureandhappinessmakehimanormativeperfectionist, andhisperfectionist conceptionofhappi-nessshapesagreatdealofwhatisdistinctiveinhiscontributionstotheutilitarianandliberaltraditions.15

Green. In theProlegomena to Ethics, Green aims to synthesize thebestelementsinancientandmodernethicaltraditions,inparticularAristotelianandKantianclaims.16Hecriticizeshedonistconceptions

15. See David O. Brink, Mill’s Progressive Principles (Oxford: Clarendon Press,2013).

16. T.H. Green, Prolegomena to Ethics, ed. David O. Brink (Oxford: ClarendonPress,2003) [PE].AlsoseeThe Collected Works of T. H. Green, 5vols.,ed.Pe-terNicholson(Bristol:ThoemmesPress,1997)[Works].Ofspecialinterestin

onomyisreally functional incharacter, inasmuchas itdistinguishesthesoulsofplants,animals,humans,andgodsintermsoftheircapaci-tiesandactivities.Inparticular,animals,rationalanimals,andgodsaredistinguishedbytheirdifferentialcapacitiesforintentionalactionandrationalthoughtandcontrol.Aristotleconceivesofusasrationalani-malswithnormativecapacitiestoregulateourpassionsandactionsinaccordancewithpracticalreason.Thismakeshistaxonomygroundedinphilosophicalandmoralpsychology,notbiology,whichmeansthathisuseofthefunctionargumenttoconstrainhiseudaimonismmakeshimanormativeperfectionist.Aristotle’sconstraintsoneudaimoniasupportacomprehensiveconceptionofeudaimoniainwhichvirtue,conceivedofasalifeinwhichthepassionsanddesiresareregulatedbytherationalpartofthesoul,isthedominantcomponent.Thevir-tuesareregulatedbythecommongood,whichwecanseeclearlyinthecaseofgeneraljustice,whichinvolvescompletevirtueinrelationtoanother (NE 1129b15−30).Wecanbegin toseehowthecommongood contributes to the agent’s own eudaimonia by reconstructingtherelationshipbetweenjusticeandfriendshipandthewayinwhichfriendshipcompletesandperfectsarationalbeingwithfinitecapaci-ties(NE booksVIII–IX).Thoughvirtueisthecontrollingelementinanagent’shappiness,suchthatitisalwaysbesttochoosevirtuewhateveritsopportunitycosts,acompletegoodnonethelessincludesfortuitousgoods(externals)andpleasure,whichexplainswhyvirtueisnotsuf-ficientforhappiness.13

Mill.14Asautilitarian,Millembracesateleologicalethicaltheoryinwhichthefundamentaldemandistopromotehappinessimpartially.

13. IassumeacomprehensiveconceptionofeudaimoniabestcapturesthefirstninebooksoftheNicomachean Ethics,evenifbookXintroducesanalternativestrictintellectualistconception.

14. ThedefinitiveeditionofMill’swritingsisCollected Works of John Stuart Mill,33volumes,ed.JohnM.Robson(Toronto:UniversityofTorontoPress,1963−91)[CW].TofacilitatecommonreferenceamongreadersusingdifferenteditionsofMill’smostpopularworks—forinstance,Utilitarianism (U)andOn Liberty (OL)—Iwillrefertothoseworksusingnaturaldivisionsinhistexts,suchaschapter,section,and/orparagraph.ButIwillalsorefertoMill’sworksusingvolumeandpagenumberinhisCollected Works.

Page 6: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –6– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

requiresmoralresponsibility,whichrequiresoneformofreasons-re-sponsiveness.Butrationalagencyalsorequiresepistemicresponsibil-ity,whichrequiresaparallelformofreasons-responsiveness(PE§§84,120,125).19Tobeepistemicallyresponsible,onemustbeself-consciousandabletodistinguishappearanceandfact,reasonaboutthecreden-tials of one’s appearances, and regulate one’s beliefs and epistemicbehavior inaccordancewith thisreasoning.Epistemicandmoral re-sponsibilityarebothpartsofagencyorpersonality,andsoaunifiedconceptionofagencyrequiresbothformsofreasons-responsiveness.

Thesearetheessentialsofnormativeperfectionism,andtherearemanydifferentwaysofdeveloping theseessentials, reflected, for in-stance,insomeofthedifferencesonefindsamongAristotle,Mill,andGreen.Ineffect,therearedifferentchoicepointsinthearchitectureofnormativeperfectionism.Someofthosechoicepointsarenotdirectlyrelevanttothecomparativeagendainthisessay.However,threesuchchoicepointsdeservebriefdiscussionnowandwillbesignificantlater.

First,perfectionismhasoftenbeenunderstoodasaclaimaboutthegood,typicallyaboutthepersonalgood—thatis,whatinitselfmakessomeone’slifebetterforhisorherownsake.Butitcouldalsobeun-derstoodasaclaimaboutpracticalreason—that is,whatconstrainsand regulates an agent’s reasons for action. Perfectionismmight beunderstoodasconcerningboththegoodandpracticalreasonifweac-ceptabroadlyteleologicalconceptionofpracticalreason.ThisseemstobeapointofnormativearchitectureonwhichAristotle,Mill,andGreenallagree.Theyofferperfectionistconceptionsofthepersonalgoodthatinformstheirconceptionsofpracticalreason.

Second, perfectionismmight be understood in agent-relative orin agent-neutral terms. Aristotle and Green are perfectionist eudai-monists,whounderstandthefundamentalperfectionistdemandtobefortheagenttopromoteherowngood.Theirperfectionismtakesa

19. ThisreversesGreen’sactualorderofexposition,sinceheintroducestheroleofself-consciousnessinepistemicresponsibilityattheendofBookI(PE§84;cf.§§120,125),whichsetsthestageforhisintroductionofself-consciousnessinmoralresponsibilityinBookII(PE§§85−86,92,96,103,107,220).

ofdesire,thewill,andthegood.FollowingButlerandKant,hearguesthatagentshavecapacitiesforpracticalreasonthatallowthemtodis-tinguishbetweenthe intensityandauthorityofdesire, todeliberateabouttheirends,andtoregulatetheiractionsaccordingtothesedelib-erations.Indoingso,heexplicitlycriticizesKant’sappealtotranscen-dentalfreedomanddefendsacompatibilistunderstandingofthewill.Greenunderstandsactingonsuperiorprinciplesintermsofactingonaconceptionofone’sownoverallgoodandinterpretstheagent’sowngoodintermsofself-realization.Becausethedemandforself-realiza-tionisgroundedinfeaturesofmoralpersonalityoragency,Greenre-gardsitsdictatesascategorical,ratherthanhypothetical,imperatives.Properself-realizationrequiresaconstitutiveconcernforothersthatshouldbegenuinelycosmopolitanincharacter,involvingrespectforallotherrationalagents.Hence,GreenacceptsKant’sHumanityFor-mulaof theCategorical Imperative,butheunderstandsthesemoraldemandsasgroundedinself-realization.17

Inallthreecases,butmostclearlyinGreen,perfectionistidealsaregroundedinaconceptionofmoral personality,understoodinButleriantermsasthecapacitytodistinguishbetweenthepowerandauthorityofpassionanddesire(SermonsII14).18Thisinvolvescapacitiestodistin-guishoneselffromone’sdesires,framethequestionofwhatoneoughttodo,deliberateabout themeritsofalternatives,andregulateone’sactionsinaccordancewithone’sdeliberations.Moralpersonality,onthisview,involvesaformofreasons-responsiveness.

Interestingly, Green thinks that moral personality or agency in-volvesjustoneformofreasons-responsiveness.Hethinksthatwearerationalagentsengagedinboththoughtandaction.Rationalagency

thepresentcontextareGreen’slecturesonKant’smetaphysicsandethicsinWorksII.

17. IreconstructandassesssomemainelementsofGreen’sperfectionisminDa-vidO.Brink,Perfectionism and the Common Good: Themes in the Philosophy of T. H. Green(Oxford:ClarendonPress,2003).

18. Bishop JosephButler,Fifteen Sermons Preached at Rolls Chapel and A Disserta-tion on the Nature of Virtue,ed.W.R.Matthews(London:G.Bell&Sons,1953),referencesbychapter/sermonandparagraphnumber.

Page 7: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –7– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

andpromotion.Forinstance,considertwodifferentanti-paternalismprinciplesandtheirattitudetowardsellingoneselfintoslavery.Thisinvolvestheuseofone’snormativepowerstoabdicatepermanentlyone’sfutureuseofthosenormativepowers.Honoringanagent’snor-mativepowerswouldrequirepermittingself-slavery,butpromotingan agent’s normative powerswould permit a policy forbidding self-slavery.Aswewillsee in§3,Milldiscusses this issue(OLV11;CW XVIII299)andendorsestheprohibitiononself-slavery,claimingthatthisisaprincipledexceptiontotheusualprohibitiononpaternalism,becausetheverysamevaluesthatnormallyspeakagainstpaternalismherespeakinfavorofit.Here,Milladvocatespromotingrationalna-tureaspartofitsfullrealization,atleastintrapersonally.

Giventhisbriefsummaryoftheessentialsofnormativeperfection-ism,weare inaposition toexplorehow thatdoctrinecan respondtoworriesaboutthejustification,content,andimplicationsofperfec-tionism,especiallyasweencounterthosedoubtswithintheKantianethicaltradition.21

2. Are Perfectionist Ideals Requirements of Reason?

WemightbeginwithKant’sdoubtsaboutthegroundorjustificationof perfectionist ideals. Famously, he thinks that all previous moralphilosophiesareheteronomous insofaras theybasemoralityonhu-mannature,sentiment,inclination,interest,orperfection(G4:432−33,

21. MydiscussionoftheKantianethicaltraditiondrawsprimarilyonKant’sthreemainethicalworks:Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals [G], Critique of Practical Reason[KpV],andMetaphysics of Morals[MM].IrefertotheseworksusingPrussianAcademypagination in the translationsbyMaryGregor inImmanuelKant,Practical Philosophy(NewYork:CambridgeUniversityPress,1996).However,IalsodrawmoreselectivelyonKant’sessay,“OntheCom-monSaying:ThatMayBeCorrectinTheory,ButitisofNoUseinPractice”inPractical Philosophytrs.MaryGregor(PrussianAcademypagination);Kant’slecturesonethics (CollinsandMrongovius) in ImmanuelKant,Lectures on Ethics,trs.PeterHeath(NewYork:CambridgeUniversityPress,1997)(Prus-sian Academy pagination) [Lectures]; Immanuel Kant, Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason,trs.AllenWoodandGeorgediGiovanni(NewYork:CambridgeUniversityPress,1998)(PrussianAcademypagination)[Religion];and ImmanuelKant, Idea for a Universal History from a Cosmopolitan Point of View,trs.LewisWhiteBeck(Indianapolis:Bobbs-Merrill,1963)[History].

fundamentallyegocentricoragent-relativeform.Bycontrast,Millisaperfectionistutilitarian,whounderstandsthefundamentalperfection-istdemandtobefortheagenttopromotethegeneralhappiness,un-derstoodintermsofthenatureofprogressivebeings.Thisisanagent-neutralconceptionofperfectionism.This isan importantdifferenceinnormativearchitecture.Butitmayturnouttobesubstantivelylessimportantthanitfirstappearsiftheeudaimonistrecognizesthecom-mongood as a constitutive commitmentof self-realization, as bothAristotleandGreendo,andtheutilitarianrecognizestheimportanceofvariousformsofpartialityinthepromotionofhumanperfection,asMilldoes.

Third,cuttingacrossthedistinctionbetweenegocentricandimpar-tialconcernisadistinctioninhowoneshouldbeorientedtowardthevalueofrationalnature,whetherone’sownoranother’s.Oneoptionis topromote rationalnatureoverall,whetherwithina lifeor acrosslives;anotheroption is tohonor itoneachoccasion. 20Honoring ra-tionalnaturemayrequirethatoneforegopromotingitiftheonlyorbestway topromote rationalnaturewould require failing tohonoritonaparticularoccasion.Onecould treat thevalueof rationalna-turesymmetricallyinintrapersonalandinterpersonalcontexts,eitherpromotingorhonoringitbothwithinlivesandacrosslives.Alterna-tively,onecouldtreatrationalnatureasymmetricallyinintrapersonalandinterpersonalcontexts,forinstance,promotingitwithinlivesbuthonoringitacrosslives.Presumably,anysuchasymmetricaltreatmentofrationalnaturerequiressomekindofspecialrationaleorjustifica-tion.Normativeperfectionism,assuch,mightremainagnosticaboutwhetherrationalnatureshouldbepromotedorhonored,treatingthisissueasachoicepointwithinnormativeperfectionism.

However, normative perfectionists have tended to favor promot-ing rationalnature,at least intrapersonally.Afterall, the full realiza-tion of one’s essential nature seems to involve itsmaximal pursuit

20.Forthedistinctionbetweenhonoringandpromotingvalues,seePhilipPettit,“Consequentialism” reprinted inConsequentialism, ed. StephenDarwall (Ox-ford:Blackwell,2003).

Page 8: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –8– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

empiricalmotivation,whichheregardsasprudentialandultimatelyhedonistic, insofar as inclination aims at pleasure (KpV 5: 21−23).22 This helps explain his concerns about both Epicureanism and Sto-icism.KantthinksthatboththeEpicureansandStoicsidentifyvirtueand happiness, but that they recognize different explanatory asym-metries between these concepts. He regards the Epicureans as ex-plainingvirtueintermsofhappiness,hedonisticallyconceived.Soheunderstandsthemasdefendingvirtueasinstrumentallyvaluableforproducingpleasureandtreatingmoralrequirementsashypotheticalimperatives.Bycontrast,heunderstandstheStoicsasexplaininghap-pinessintermsofvirtue,whichheregardsasanimprovementontheEpicureanview(KpV5:111−12).However,heunderstandstheStoicsasidentifyinghappinesswiththepleasurableconsciousnessofvirtuousaction,andsohethinkstheStoicsstillmistakenlyidentifyrationalandempiricalconcepts.

ThoughKant’sunderstandingofEpicureanethicsislargelycorrect,hisunderstandingofStoicethicsismistaken.TheStoicsidentifyhap-pinesswithvirtue,understoodastheexpressionofourrationalnature(DLvii84−89;Finiii11,20−21,26−28).23Inidentifyingvirtueandhap-piness,theyinsistthatvirtueissufficientforhappinessanddenythatfortunate outcomes and circumstances are genuine goods, treatingthemaspreferredindifferents(DLvii102−108;Finiii53−54,iv20,69).

22. For a non-hedonistic interpretationofKant’s conceptionof happiness, seeAndrewsReath,“Hedonism,Heteronomy,andKant’sPrincipleofHappiness”Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 70 (1989): 42−72. Reath reads Kant as under-standinghappiness in termsof the satisfactionof desire, but I don’t thinkthatthisdoesjusticetoKant’sinsistencethatdesireaimsatpleasure.Inanycase,theresolutionofthisdebatewouldnotmuchaffectthemeritsofKant’sownconceptionofhappinessorhisunderstandingofGreekconceptions,asbothhedonisticanddesire-satisfactionconceptionsofhappinessrepresentdemandsofprudenceashypotheticalimperatives.

23.DiogenesLaertius,The Lives of Eminent Philosophers, 2vols., trs.R.D.Hicks(Cambridge:Loeb,1925)[DL]andCicero,De Finibus Bonorum et Malorum,trs.H.Rackham(Cambridge:Loeb,1914)[Fin].ForusefulcomparisonsofAris-totelian andStoic conceptionsof happiness, seeTerence Irwin, “Stoic andAristotelianConceptionsofHappiness”inThe Norms of Nature,ed.MalcolmSchofieldandGiselaStriker(Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress,1986)andJuliaAnnas,The Morality of Happiness(Oxford:ClarendonPress,1993).

442−44;KpV5:20−28,35−36,39−41,111−12).Assuch,suchconceptionsgenerateonlyhypothetical,notcategorical,imperatives:

Wherever anobject of thewill has tobe laiddownonthebasisforprescribingtherulethatdeterminesthewill,theretheruleisnoneotherthanheteronomy;theimper-ativeisconditional,namely:iforbecauseonewillstheob-ject,oneoughttoactinsuchorsuchaway;henceitcannever commandmorally, that is, categorically.Whetherthe object determines thewill bymeans of inclination,asintheprincipleofone’sownhappiness,orbymeansof reasondirected toobjectsofourpossiblevolition ingeneral,as in theprincipleofperfection, thewillneverdeterminesitselfimmediately ….[G 4:444]

ThoughKantdistinguisheshappinessandperfectionasendshereandelsewhere (G 4:442−43;KpV 5: 39−41), it is significant thathis criti-cismtreatsthemtogether.Moreover,someofhisactualandpotentialeudaimonist targets provide perfectionist conceptions of happiness.ThisisclearlytrueofbothAristotle,whomKantdoesnotdiscus,andtheStoics,whomhedoes.Indeed,aslongastheeudaimonistgroundshisconceptionofeudaimoniainhumannature,heisaperfectionist,andaslongashegroundshisconceptionofeudaimoniainanagent’srationalnatureasanagent,heisanormativeperfectionist.

Kant’sdiscussionofeudaimonismfocusesontheEpicureansandStoics,curiouslyomittingSocrates,Plato,andAristotle.Heiscriticalofeudaimonisttheoriesforidentifyingvirtueandhappinessandconse-quentlytreatingmoralityasasystemofhypotheticalimperatives(G4:425,441−45;KpV5:20−28,35−36,111−12).Insofarasnormativeperfec-tionistsbasemoralityonaconceptionofaperson’sgoodorhappiness,asAristotle,Mill,andGreendoindifferentways,theseperfectionisttheories shouldalsobeguiltyof conceivingmoralityasa systemofhypotheticalimperatives.

Kant conceives of happiness as consisting in the pleasure atten-danttothesatisfactionofdesire,andthis influenceshisviewabout

Page 9: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –9– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

willandsocannotgeneratecategoricalimperatives(G4:444;KpV 5:41).

HisexactunderstandingoftheperfectionismsofLeibnizandWolffisunclear.Leibniz’sethicalwritingsarescatteredandtheymixperfec-tionismandeudaimonism:

Wisdom isnothingother than the scienceof thehappi-nessorperfectionofhumanbeings;andthemostgeneralandarchitectonicof thisknowledge is toshowhowhu-manbeingscanstrive for thatperfectionofwhich theyarecapablebynature.Thisshouldnotbeinterpretedasifahighestdegreeofhumanperfectioncanneverbeat-tained,sincethenatureofhappiness,rather,isnevertobeimpededinfurtherprogresstomoreorgreatergoods.26

Perfectioninvolvesunityamiddiversity,andGodrepresentsabsoluteperfection.ForLeibniz,anagent’sperfectionisexplainedintermsofheractinginaccordancewiththesameprinciplethatgovernsGod’swill—therealizationinunderstandingandactionofthegreatestpos-sibleobjectiveharmonyorperfection.27Wolffalsomixesperfection-ismandeudaimonism:

Thelawofnatureisthemeansbywhichmanattainsthehappinessofwhichheiscapablethroughhisnaturalpow-ers inthis life.Now,becausethe lawofnaturerequirestheperfectionofusandourconditionandbecausethisperfectionisthefinalgoalofallfreeaction,man,wantingthehappinesshecanachievethroughhisnaturalpowers

26.G.W.Leibniz,Sämtliche Schriften und Briefe,Reihe6,Band4,975,ed.DeutscheAkadamie der Wissenschaften (Berlin: Akademie-Verlag, 1999) [Complete Writings and Letters,series6,vol.4,Akademiepage975].ThankstoDonRuth-erford,whobroughtthispassagetomyattentionandprovidedatranslation.

27. SeeG.W.Leibniz,Discourse on Metaphysics§36andLeibniz’sletterstoWolffof4May1715and18May1715inG.W.Leibniz,Philosophical Essays,ed.RogerAriewandDanielGarber(Indianapolis:Hackett,1989).

WhiletheStoicsmaybelievethatthevirtuouspersonwillexperiencepleasureinthecourseofpracticingvirtue,thisisaby-productofvirtueandnottobeconfusedwithit(DLvii86;Finiii17).TheStoicsiden-tifyhappinesswithvirtue,conceivedasaliferealizingone’srationalnature,notwithpleasurableconsciousnessofone’svirtue.ItisKant’sownhedonisticconceptionofhappinessthatleadshimtomisunder-standStoichappiness.

Kant’s criticisms of a morality of happiness reflect mistaken as-sumptionsabout thehedonisticcharacterofhappiness.Though theEpicureanswerehedonistsabouthappiness,theStoicswerenot.PlatoandAristotle,whomhedoesnotdiscuss,alsorejecthedonism.24Un-liketheStoics,theydonotidentifyhappinessandvirtue,denyingthatvirtueissufficientforhappiness,becausetheyrecognizethevalueofexternals.However,liketheStoics,theyregardvirtueasthecontrol-lingelementofhappiness,suchthatoneisalwaysbetteroffchoosingvirtue,whateveritsopportunitycosts(RepublicII,esp.357b−367e;NE I.7−I.13).Also,liketheStoics,theythinkthatvirtuenormallyaffordspleasure, so that pleasure is a typical by-product of virtue (Philebus 63e3−6, Laws 662b1−663d5, 734b8−e1; NE 1153b15−18, 1174b20−33,1176a16−19).Thismeans thatKant’s criticismsofperfectionisteudai-monismrestonamistakenunderstandingoftheirconceptionsofhap-piness,reflectingKant’sownhedonisticconceptionofhappiness.25

Thougheudaimonistscanbeperfectionists,Kantdistinguishesper-fectionismandeudaimonism,associatingperfectionismwithLeibnizandWolff(G 4:442−43;KpV5:40−41).Whenhedistinguishesthem,hesuggests thatperfectionism involvesa lessermistake thaneudai-monism, but amistake nonetheless (G 4: 443;KpV 5: 40−41). Kantclaimsthataperfectionisa“materialprinciple”externaltotheagent’s

24.ReferencestoPlatonictextsaretodialoguesinPlato Complete Works,ed.JohnM.CooperandD.S.Hutchinson(Indianapolis:Hackett,1997).

25. AlsoseeTerenceIrwin,“Kant’sCriticismsofEudaemonism”inAristotle, Kant, and the Stoics: Rethinking Happiness and Duty,ed.StephenEngstromandJen-niferWhiting(NewYork:CambridgeUniversityPress,1996).

Page 10: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –10– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

otherthanthefeelingofanincreaseinperfection.”31Onthisreading,pleasureisconsequentialonvirtue,understoodastheexpressionofone’srationalnature,notthegroundofit.

Wolffisevenclearerthathappiness,whichheunderstandsintermsof pleasure, is consequential on the highest good,which he under-standstoconsistinperfection:

[T]hehighestgoodofmanorhisblessedness is rightlyexplained as an unhindered progress to greater perfec-tions.…Hewhoprogressesunhamperedfromoneper-fectiontoanotherandavoidsimperfection,andisawareofthis,hasanintuitiveawarenessofperfection.Intuitiveknowledgeofperfectionaffordspleasureorenjoyment;so he has continuous pleasure. So the highest good orblessednessofmanisconnectedwithhappiness.32

BecauseLeibnizandWolfftreatpleasureasconsequentialontheper-ceptionofperfectionandhenceasaby-productratherthangroundofduty,theimportancetheyattachtopleasureshouldnotrendertheirviewsheteronomous.

However,Kantmaythinkit istheir formofperfectionism,ratherthananyapparentcommitmenttohedonism,thatrenderstheirviewsheteronomous. For he sees them as perfectionistswho conceive ofperfectionasametaphysicalprincipleconcernedwithunityandhar-monyinnaturethatdeterminesthecontentoftherationalwill(Lec-tures Mrongovius29:622).Heregardsthisasmakingtherationalwilldependentonsomethingotherthanitself,whichresultsinheterono-my.Onlymoral perfection—understoodasthefullrealizationofone’scapacities in rationalwilling—can serveas thegroundofduty (Lec-tures Collins27:265−66,470).

Here,Kantassumesboth thatLeibnizandWolffconceiveofper-fectionasametaphysicalprincipleofunity,order,orfittingnessand

31. “AphorismsConcerningHappiness,Wisdom,Charity,andJustice”inLeibniz on God and Religion,ed.LloydStrickland(London:Bloomsbury,2016),138.

32.Wolff,Reasonable Thoughts,338.

inthislife,mustsetasthefinalgoalofallhisfreeactionstheperfectionofhisinnerandouterconditions.28

AlsolikeLeibniz,Wolffregardsperfectionasakindofunity—“agree-ment of themanifold”—and treats human perfection as awill thatmaximizes internalandexternalharmony.29BothLeibnizandWolffseemtoconceiveofperfectionintermsofmetaphysicalrelationsoforder, harmony, and agreement. Kant objects to these perfectionistclaims, claiming that they make morality dependent on a materialprinciple,whichrendersmoralityheteronomous.Theworryseemstobeaboutmakingmoralityconditionalonanidealthatisexternaltorationalagencyitself.

KantmayseetheperfectionismsofLeibnizandWolffasmakingmorality dependon anobjectionablematerial principle, because oftheroletheygivetopleasure.Forinstance,Leibnizrecognizestheendashappiness,whichhetreatsasenduringjoyorpleasure:“InmoralsI setupourhappiness [felicitas]asanend; this Idefineasa stateofenduringjoy[laetitia].JoyIdefineasanextraordinarypredominanceofpleasure[voluptas]….”30However,thecontextofthispassagesug-geststhemoreStoicconceptionofhappinessinwhichpleasureisun-derstoodasconsequentialonandaby-productoftheperfectionofone’srationalnature.After identifyingperfectionwithakindofharmony,Leibnizclaimsthatfromthis“senseofharmony,thatis,observationofagreement[consensus]mightbringforthpleasure.”Andaftertheap-parentcommitmenttohedonism(quotedabove),heinsiststhat“plea-sureisthesensationofperfection.”Elsewhere,Leibnizmakesasimilarperfectionistclaimaboutpleasure,claimingthat“pleasureisnothing

28.ChristianWolff,Reasonable Thoughts about the Actions of Men, for the Promotion of their HappinessinMoral Philosophy from Montaigne to Kant,ed.J.B.Schnee-wind(CambridgeUniversityPress,1990),vol.I,pp.340−41.

29.Wolff,Reasonable Thoughts,341.AlsoseeChristianWolff,German Metaphysics, Reasonable Thoughts about God, the World, and the Human Soul,§157,quotedinSchneewind,349.

30.Leibniz’slettertoWolffof18May1715inPhilosophical Essays.

Page 11: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –11– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

himself …. [Self-realization] will express itself in [the]imposition…ofrulesrequiringsomethingtobedoneir-respectivelyofany inclination todo it, irrespectivelyofanydesiredendtowhichitisameans,other than this end, which is desired because conceived as absolutely desirable.[PE §193]

Because thedemandsof self-realizationdependonlyon those verycapacitiesthatmakeoneanagentanddonotdependonconditionsextraneoustorationalagency,theyarecategorical,ratherthanhypo-thetical,imperatives.

Wemight considerhowGreen’s conceptionof normativeperfec-tionismcanrespondtoadilemmathatKantposesfortheperfectionistinthePrefacetothefirsteditionofReligion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason.34Afterrejectingattemptstogrounddutyinahedonisticver-sionofself-love,Kantconsiderstwoalternativegrounds:

Butthenthereareonlytwodetermininggroundsleft:onethatisrational,namelyone’sownperfection;andanotherthat isempirical, thehappinessofothers.Now, ifby thefirst they do not already understand moral perfection,whichcanonlybeonething(namelyawilluncondition-allyobedienttothelaw),inwhichcasetheywouldhow-everbedefininginacircle,thentheymustmeanthehu-manbeing’snaturalperfectioninasmuchasitiscapableofenhancement;andofthisperfectiontherecanbemanyaspects(suchasskillintheartsandsciences,taste,physi-calagility,etc.).But thesearealwaysonlyconditionallygood,thatis,goodonlyonconditionthattheirusedoesnotconflictwiththemorallaw(whichalonecommandsunconditionally); hence natural perfection cannot be,whenmadeintoanend,theprincipleoftheconceptsofduty.[Religion6:4n]

34. ThankstoRosalindChaplinfordrawingthispassagetomyattention.

thata rationalwill cannotbedeterminedbyanyprinciples—goodsorreasons—outside itself,nomatterhowobjectivetheseprinciplesare.Later,in§5,wewillexaminehowmuchethicalcontentrationalagencyitselfcanprovidewithoutappealtoobjectivegoodsorexter-nalreasons.Ifthenormativeperfectionistmusteschewanyappealtoprinciplesexternaltomoralpersonalityitself,LeibnizandWolffmightnotbenormativeperfectionists.33

ButGreenisanormativeperfectionistwhobasesmoralityontheverycapacitiesforreasons-responsivenessthatmakeusagents,whichallowshimtomeetKant’sstricturesoncategoricalrequirements.Be-causeGreenseeshimselfaspreservingwhatisdefensibleinKantianethics and reconciling itwithGreek eudaimonism, it is no surprisethatheisclearestabouthowtheperfectionistcanrecognizecategori-calimperatives:

Atthesametime,becauseit[self-realization]isthefulfil-mentofhimself[asanagent],ofthatwhichhehasinhimtobe,itwillexciteaninterestinhimlikenootherinter-est,differentinkindfromanyofhisdesiresandaversionsexceptsuchasarederivedfromit.Itwillbeaninterestasinanobjectconceivedtobeofunconditionalvalue;oneofwhich thevaluedoesnotdependonanydesire thattheindividualmayatanytimefeelforitorforanythingelse, or on any pleasure that… hemay experience…. [T]hedesirefortheobjectwillbefoundedonaconcep-tionofitsdesirablenessasthefulfilmentofthecapabili-ties ofwhich aman is conscious inbeing consciousof

33.Ononereading,LeibnizandWolffaremetaphysical,ratherthannormative,perfectionists, because they conceive of perfection as ametaphysical prin-cipleofunity,order,orfittingness, rather thanasanormativeprincipleofmoralpersonalityorrationalagency.Thiswouldmaketheirperfectionismsin somewaysmore akin to the rational intuitionist tradition that includesSamuelClarke,JohnBalguy,andRichardPrice.Fordiscussion,seeTerenceIrwin,The Development of Ethics,3vols.(Oxford:ClarendonPress,2007−09),vol.II,ch.43andStefanoBacin,“RationalismandPerfectionism”inThe Cam-bridge History of Moral Philosophy.

Page 12: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –12– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

Mill,orifitrecognizesthecommongoodasanimportantpartofself-realization,asitdoesforAristotleandGreen,thenanagentalsohasreasontopromotethenormativeperfectionofothers.

This limitedclaimaboutthecontentof theperfectionistdemandtoperfectone’sownrationalnatureandthatofothersissufficienttoposeaconflictwithKant’sinsistenceintheMetaphysics of Moralsonafundamentalself/other moral asymmetryinwhichweaimatourownperfectionbutatthehappiness,ratherthantheperfection,ofothers.IntheDoctrineofVirtue,Kantdescribesthebasicendsthatareourmost fundamentalduties as “one’s own perfection and the happiness of others”(MM6:385).Incommentingonthisasymmetry,Kantinsistsondistinguishingtheendsofperfectionandhappinessanddefendstwoclaims.First,heclaimsthatonecan’tbeunderadutytopromoteone’sownhappiness,becauseeachagentnecessarilydesireshisownhap-piness,andonecanonlybeunderadutyifonecanhavecontra-moralmotivation(MM6:386;cf.KpV5:20,37).Second,Kantclaimsthatthedutyofperfectionistomakeone’sfreechoicesconformtoduty,butwhileone canmakeone’s own choices freely conform toduty, onecannotmakeanother’schoicesfreelyconformtoduty(MM 6:386–87).

Thisself/otherasymmetryispuzzlinginseveralrespects.First,it’spuzzlinginsofarasitgrantsthatone’smostfundamentaldutytoone-selfistoperfectoneself.It’shardtoseehowthathalfoftheasymme-try is compatiblewithhis critiqueofperfectionismasyieldingonlyhypothetical imperatives,unlessheunderstandsperfection in termsofpersonalityorrationalnature,asthenormativeperfectionistdoes.Second,wemightquestionKant’sgroundsforrecognizingthisasym-metrybetweendutiestoselfandtoothers.Here,wemightquestionthefirstprongofKant’sasymmetry,viz.thatwecan’taimatourownhappiness.35 However, it is the second prong that threatens perfec-

35. Even if all agentsdesire their ownhappiness, that doesn’t show that theydesireonlytheirownhappiness.Butthenagentsmaywellbemotivatedcon-trarytoadutytopromotetheirownhappiness.Moreover,wemightwonderifit’struethatyoucan’tbeobligatedtodosomethingyouaredisposedtodo.IamobligatedtonurtureandcareformychildreneventhoughIamdisposedtodoso.IwouldstillbeobligatedtodosoevenifIcouldn’thelpbutdoso.

Ifperfectionisunderstoodasmoralperfection,thengroundingdutyinperfectioniscircular.Ifperfectionisunderstoodasnaturalperfection,thengroundingdutyinperfectionisheteronomous,becausenaturalperfectionisempiricalandonlyconditionallygood.Butthisisafalsedilemma,becauseKant’salternativeconceptualizationsofperfectionarenotexhaustive.Ifperfectionisunderstoodaspersonalityorratio-nalnature,asthenormativeperfectionistconceivesit,thenperfectioncangroundthegoodorduty inadistinctnormativeconcept that isnotempiricalinKant’ssense.Indeed,aswewillseeshortly(§4below),Kant’sownethical theorygives rationalnaturean important role ingroundingtheCategoricalImperative.Ifso,Kant’sownethicaltheoryshowsthepossibilityofaformofnormativeperfectionismthatisnei-thercircularnorempirical.

Kant’scriticaltargetistheattempttofoundmoralityonanempiricist conceptionofhumannaturethat ispriortoandindependentofrea-son.Buthehasnoreasontorejectattemptstofoundmoralityonanor-mativeconceptionofhumannaturethatunderstandshumannatureintermsofrationalagencyorreason-responsiveness.ButthenitseemsthatKant’scriticismsofperfectionismaremisplacedwhenappliedtonormativeperfectionism.

3. Can We Aim at the Perfection of Another?

Turningtoissuesaboutthecontentofperfectionistideals,wemightaskwhatconceptionofmoraldemandsnormativeperfectionismsup-ports.Thatisalargetopic,thedetailsofwhicharebeyondthescopeof thisessay.But itseemsfair tosaythatanagenthasreasontode-velopherownnormativecompetence,inwhichheragencyconsists,andtopursuealifethatexercisesherrationalagencywellinactivitiesthatembodydeliberativecontrolandreasons-responsiveness.Forin-stance,wemightagreewithAristotleandMillthatwehavereasontopursueactivelivesthatexerciseourdistinctivecapacitiesforpracticalreason,ratherthanlivesofmerecontentmentoranimalsatisfaction.Amongotherthings,suchalifewillassignprioritytohigherpleasures.Ifnormativeperfectionismtakesanagent-neutralform,asitdoesfor

Page 13: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –13– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

FormulaoftheCategoricalImperative:“Actsothatyoutreathumanity[personality],whetherinyourownpersonorthatofanother,alwaysasanendandnevermerelyasameans”(G4:428–29).IncommentingontheHumanityFormula,inbothitsapplicationtodutiestooneselfandtoothers,Kantinsiststhatouractionsmustnotonlynotconflictwithhumanitybutalsoharmonizewithit(G 4:430).Inthecaseofdu-tiestoothers,thisrequiresmakingtheirendsourown:

Now,humanitymightindeedsubsistifnoonecontribut-edtothehappinessofothersbutyetdidnotintentionallywithdrawanythingfromit;butthereisstillonlynegativeandnotapositiveagreementwithhumanity as an end in itselfunlesseveryonetries,asfarashecan,tofurthertheendsofothers.For,theendsofasubjectwhoisanendinitselfmustasfaraspossiblebealsomyends,ifthatrepre-sentationistohaveitsfulleffectinme.[G 4:430]

But ifanotheragent’send ishisownperfection, thentheHumanityFormula implies that I shouldmakehisperfectionmyend.Yet, thisconflictswiththeself/othermoralasymmetryKantrecognizesintheMetaphysics of Morals.

Interestingly,GreenagreeswithKant,bothinacceptingthemoralsymmetryoftheHumanityFormulaoftheCategoricalImperative,anditsinjunctiontoaimattheperfectionofothers,andinhavingdoubtsaboutwhetheronepersoncanpromotetheperfectionistgoodofan-otherdirectly.Heexpressesthissecondpointinhisessay“LiberalLeg-islationandFreedomofContract:”

[I]tisthebusinessofthestate,notindeeddirectlytopro-motemoral goodness, for that, from theverynatureofmoralgoodness,itcannotdo,buttomaintainthecondi-tionswithoutwhichafreeexerciseofthehumanfacultiesisimpossible.[WorksIII374]

InGreen’sview,aliberalstatenotonlyhasnegativedutiesnottointer-ferewiththebasiclibertiesandopportunitiesofitscitizens,butalso

tionism,inasmuchasitclaimsthatIcannothaveadutytoaimattheperfectionofothers.Kantclaimsthatyourperfectionconsistsinyourmakingyourfreechoicesconformtoduty,andIcannotdothisforyou:

Sotoo,itisacontradictionformetomakeanother’sper-fectionmyendandconsidermyselfunderanobligationtopromotethis.Fortheperfectionofanotherhumanbeing,as aperson, consists just in this: thathehimself is abletosethisendinaccordancewithhisownconceptionofduty;anditisself-contradictorytorequirethatIdo(makeitmydutytodo)somethingthatonlytheotherhimselfcando.[MM 6:386]

Here, Kant associates perfection with moral personality, which hethinksexplainswhyonecannotmakeanother’sperfectionone’send.Heseemstoreasonasfollows.

1. Moral personality implies that an agent’s perfectionconsists inher freelychoosing toconformto themorallaw.

2.Icanfreelychoosetoconformtothemorallawinmyownactions.

3.Hence,Icanaimatmyownperfection.

4.Icannotmakeanotherfreelychoosetoconformtothemorallaw;thatwouldbypassthatperson’sagency.

5.Hence,Icannotaimattheperfectionofanother.

Thisargumentbeginsfromapremiseabouttheconnectionbetweenmoralpersonalityandfreedomorautonomyandreachesananti-per-fectionistconclusion.

However,thismoralasymmetrybetweenselfandothersshouldbesurprisinginlightofthemoralsymmetrycontainedintheHumanity

Perhaps inthatcase, Iwouldn’tperceive itasaburdenorconstraint,but Iwouldstillhaveadutytodoso.

Page 14: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –14– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

assumptions about happiness provide him with a more robust de-fenseofautonomyandcritiqueofpaternalism.Ifaperson’shappinessconsists in the exercise of her normative powers and capacities forpracticalreason,thenaprincipalingredientofherowngoodmustin-cludeopportunitiesforresponsiblechoiceanddecision-making.MilldevelopsthisperfectionistargumentagainstpaternalisminChapterIIIofOn Liberty:

Hewholetstheworld,orhisownportionofit,choosehisplanoflifeforhimhasnoneedofanyotherfacultythantheape-likeoneofimitation.Hewhochooseshisplanforhimself employs all his faculties. Hemust use observa-tion to see, reasoningand judgment to foresee, activitytogathermaterialsfordecision,discriminationtodecide,andwhen he has decided, firmness and self-control tohold his deliberate decision. And these qualities he re-quiresandexercisesexactlyinproportionasthepartofhis conductwhichhedeterminesaccording tohisownjudgmentand feelings isa largeone. It ispossible thathemightbeguidedinsomegoodpath,andkeptoutofharm’sway,withoutanyofthesethings.Butwhatwillbehiscomparativeworthasahumanbeing?[OLIII4;CW XVIII262−63]

Here,Mill’snormativeconceptionofhumannatureexplainswhyself-determinationisanimportantpartofaperson’sgoodthatpaternalismnecessarilyundercuts.

However,Mill’sperfectionismdoesnotendorseablanketprohibi-tiononpaternalism.Aswenotedearlier,oneexceptiontotheusualprohibition on paternalism thatMill recognizes concerns a prohibi-tiononsellingoneselfintoslavery:

Thegroundforthuslimitinghispowerofvoluntarilydis-posingofhisownlotisapparent,andisveryclearlyseenin this extreme case.… [B]y sellinghimself for a slave,

positivedutiestoitscitizenstoeducatethem,developtheircapacities,andprovideopportunitiesinsocialandpoliticallifethatenablethemtorealizetheircapacitiesasagents.

Here,GreenmakessenseofKant’sadmonitionsagainstaimingattheperfectionofanotherbyinterpretingthemasconstraintsonhow wecanpromotetheperfectionofothers.Giventheroleofone’sownagencyinone’sperfection,Ican’tperfectothersanymorethanIcanwincompetitiveracesforthem.ButjustasIcanhelpanothertowinaracebytrainingwithher,discussingstrategy,andsharingnutritionaltips,sotoocanIhelpothersperfectthemselvesbyhelpingthemde-veloptheirnormativecompetenceanddeliberatingwiththem,identi-fyingoptions,discussingthecomparativemeritsoftheseoptions,andprovidingthemwithopportunitiestoexercisetheirnormativepowers.Icanhelpothersperfectthemselves,justnotinwaysthatbypasstheiragency.Ifso,(5)doesnotfollowfrom(4).

Ineffect, this is to insiston the importanceofautonomy inanor-mativeperfectionist conceptionof thegoodand theways inwhichautonomyconstrainspaternalistic interventioninthelivesofothers.Inthisconnection,Mill’sperfectionistcritiqueofconventionalformsofpaternalisminOn Libertyandhisdefenseofsociety’sroleindevel-opingthenormativecompetenceofindividualsareinstructiveabouthowanormativeperfectionistmighttrytoaccommodatewhatisde-fensibleinKant’smoralasymmetry.

Mill offers some consequentialist arguments that paternalistic li-cense is liable tobeunsuccessful, failingtoadvancethe interestsofthosewhoselibertyisrestricted.Somepaternalismisinbadfaith,de-signedtobenefitthosewhorestrictliberty,ratherthanthosewhoselibertyisrestricted(OLV20−23;CWXVIII306−10).Evenwhenpater-nalismisingoodfaith,itislikelytomissitsmark,becauseagentsaregenerallymorereliablejudgesoftheirownintereststhanothers(OL IV12;CWXVIII283).Importantastheseargumentsare,theyprovidenoprincipledobjectiontopaternalism—noobjectiontosuccessful pa-ternalism thatgenuinelyadvances the interestsof thepersonwhoseliberty is restricted by paternalism. However, Mill’s perfectionist

Page 15: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –15– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

reasontoaimattheirperfectioninawaythatrequiresustoconsultandengage,ratherthanbypass,theiragency.

4. Kantian Perfectionism

The normative perfectionist who appeals to moral personality, un-derstoodintermsofrationalnatureandreasons-responsiveness,cananswerKant’sexplicitconcernsaboutperfectionisminawaythatre-spectsKant’sowncommitmentstotheconnectionsamongagency,ra-tionalnature, andmoral requirements.Thisgivesus reason to takeseriouslyanormativeperfectionistreadingofKantianessentials.Aswenoted,Kant’scriticaltargetistheattempttofoundmoralityonanempiricistconceptionofhumannature that isprior toand indepen-dentofreason.Butthenhehasnoreasontorejectattemptstofoundmoralityonanormativeconceptionofhumannaturethatunderstandshumannatureintermsofrationalagency.Indeed,Kanthimselfclearlywantstofoundmoralityonanappealtorationalnature.38ThoughhefrequentlyassociatesmoralitywithhumanityandevenformulatestheCategoricalImperativeatonepointintermsofrespectforhumanity,itisclearthathemustunderstandhumanity,inthiscontext,intermsofmoralpersonalityandtheabilitytosetandactforthesakeofends(G 4:428,430−31;KpV5:87).39Kanttreatsrationalnatureasbothground andcontentofduty.

38.ThisisacentralthemeinIrwin’sconceptionofKant’splaceinthehistoryofethics.SeeIrwin,The Development of Ethics,vol.III,chs.66−72.

39. In the Religion, Kant recognizes three “predispositions”—to animality, hu-manity,andpersonality (6:26−28).Animality involves instinctual self-love,humanityinvolvesreflectiveself-love,andpersonalityinvolvesthecapacitytobemotivatedbythemorallaw.Heconcludes:“Ifweconsiderthethreedis-positions…accordingtotheconditionsoftheirpossibility,wefindthatthefirstdoesnothavereasonatitsrootatall;thatthesecondisrootedinareasonwhich is indeedpractical,butonlyas subservient toother incentives; andthatthethirdaloneisrootedinreasonpracticalofitself,i.e.inreasonlegislat-ingunconditionally”(6:28).TheReligiondistinguisheshumanityandperson-ality,astheGroundworkdoesnot.ButtheReligionislaterthantheGroundwork, anditseemsthatwemustreadtheGroundworkasidentifyinghumanitywithpersonality,at least forpurposesof theHumanityFormulaof theCategori-calImperative,ifonlybecausetheUniversalityandHumanityFormulasareonly equivalent, asKantbelieves (G 4: 436), if humanity is understood as

heabdicateshisliberty;heforegoesanyfutureuseofitbeyondthatsingleact.He,therefore,defeatsinhisowncase,theverypurposewhichisthejustificationofallow-inghimtodisposeofhimself.[OLV11;CWXVIII299]

Millrepresentsthisasaprincipledexceptiontotheusualprohibitionon paternalism, because the very same values that normally speakagainstpaternalismherespeak in favorof it. If theusual reasonweopposepaternalismisoutofrespectforthenormativepowersoftheagent,thenrespectforthosenormativepowersgivesusspecialreasontoprohibittheuseofthosenormativepowerstopermanentlyunder-mineallfutureuseofthosesamepowers.ThisrequiresMilltotreatautonomyasavaluetobepromoted,ratherthanhonored,andtorec-ognizethepermissibilityofautonomy-enhancing forms of paternalism.36

It’sinterestingtocompareMill’sextendedcritiqueofpaternalismwithKant’sbrief remarks in“OntheCommonSaying:ThatMayBeCorrectinTheory,ButitisofNoUseinPractice,”wherehedescribesagovernmentthatpaternalisticallycoercescitizenstobehappyas“thegreatestdespotismthinkable”(8:290−91).GivenKant’sownsubjectiveconceptionof happiness, his critiqueof paternalism targetswhat iswrongwithaimingatanother’shappinessinwaysthatbypassherownagency.Whatexplainsthesereservationsisrespectforherautonomyandagency.37Butthentheproblematiccharacterofpaternalismwouldseemtogiveusreasontotreateachotherasmoralpersons.That’sa

36.Millnotesthatthereasonsforallowingpaternalismin“thisextremecase”are“evidentlyoffarwiderapplication”(OLV11;CWXVIII300).Thatmakesthisprincipledexceptiontotheusualprohibitiononpaternalismthetipofanor-mativeiceberg.Thecontoursoftheicebergarenotimmediatelyclear,thoughthereisreasontoseeMillasanticipatinghislaterargumentsinThe Subjection of Women, inwhichheargues thatVictorianmarriage lawwith its require-mentsthatwomenunilaterallysurrendertheirnormativepowers,includingtheirrightsofself-ownership,isaformofslaverythatcannotbedefendedbyappealtoawoman’sconsenttobemarried(CW XXI270−71,323).

37. FordiscussionofdifferentstrandsinKant’sconceptionofautonomy,seeKarlAmeriks,“OntheManySensesof‘Self-Determination’”inKant on Freedom and Spontaneity,ed.KateA.Moran(NewYork:CambridgeUniversityPress,2018).

Page 16: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –16– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

1.Becausemoral requirementsare inescapable, theyex-presscategoricalimperatives.

2. Hence, moral requirements must apply to ratio-nal agents as such, independently of their empiricalmotivations.

3.Hence,moralrequirementsmustbeuniversal.

4.Hence, themaximsorprinciplesunderlyingmoralre-quirementsmustbecapableofservingasuniversallaws.

ThisyieldsthefirstofKant’sthreemainformulationsoftheCategori-calImperative—theFormulaofUniversality.40

F1:Actonlymaximsthatyoucanwill tobeauniversallawofnature(G 4:421).

WeshouldinterpretF1asaskingwhatrationalbeingscanconsistentlywill.But this claim is ambiguous. F1mightbe interpretedasaskingwhatrationalbeingscanconsistentlywill,thatis,whatsomeonewhois rationalcanconsistentlywill.This test candependon thecontin-gentinterestsanddesirespossessedbyrationalbeings.ButthismakesitdifficulttodistinguishF1fromtheGoldenRule,whichKantclearlywishestodo(G 4:431n).Alternatively,wecanunderstandwhatara-tionalbeingcanconsistentlywillaswhatsomeonecanwillinsofarasshe is rational.Onthis interpretation,F1askswhatwecanwill,notinsofaraswehaveparticularcontingentwantsandinterests,butwhatwecanwillinsofaraswearerationalbeings.

40. IalludetotheUniversality,Humanity,andKingdomofEndsformulae.Thistripartition simplifies amore fine-grained taxonomy. Some commentatorsidentify six formulae: (1) universal law (G 4: 421), (2) universal law of na-ture (G 4: 421), (3) theend in itself (G 4: 429), (4)universal legislationbyeveryrationalbeing(G 4:431),(5)thekingdomofends(G 4:438),and(6)autonomy(G 4:440).SeeH.J.Paton,The Categorical Imperative,5thed.(Lon-don:Hutchinson,1947),129andIrwin,The Development of Ethics,vol.III§917.However,thetripartitetaxonomydoesnotoversimplifyinasmuchas(1)and(2)areequivalentversionsofUniversality,(3)correspondstoHumanity,and(4)−(6)representdifferentaspectsoftheKingdomofEnds.Here,IfocusonUniversalityandHumanity.

Kanttreatsrationalnatureasthegroundofdutywhenheinsiststhatdutymustbeknowableapriori.Thismayseemstrange. Surely,my duties—for instance, my contractual duty to sell you my wid-gets—depend upon empirical facts aboutwhat I have done, for in-stancethatIsignedacontracttosellyoumywidgets. Kantdoesnotdenythis.Buthewantstomaketwoclaims.First,hethinksthatmydutiesapplyindependentlyofmywillingnesstocomply.Ican’tdefeatanascriptionofanobligationsimplybypleadingdisinclination.Sec-ond,healsothinksthatthederivationofourdutieshasanimportantapriorielement.Itmighthelptothinkofderivingsuchdutiesviaasyllogism.

1. It is a (pro tanto) duty to keep one’s voluntaryagreements.

2.Ivoluntarilyagreedtosellyoumywidgets.

3.Hence,itismy(protanto)dutytosellyoumywidgets.

Thedutyin(3)isderivedfromthemajorpremisein(1)aboutfidelityplustheminorpremisein(2)whichiscontingentandknownempiri-cally.Presumably,Kant’sclaimisnotthatallduties,includingdutieslike(3),areknowableapriori.Hisclaimisthatthegroundsofourdu-ties,includingmoralprinciples,suchas(1),areknowableapriori.

Moral requirements, Kant thinks, must depend upon essential,ratherthancontingentandvariable,featuresofagents,whichexplainswhymoralrequirementsmustexpresscategorical, rather thanhypo-thetical,imperatives(G4:416,425).Ifmoralrequirementsarenottobebasedonvariableempiricalconditions,thentheymustbeuniver-sal.Toachievethissortofuniversality,Kantrequiresanagenttobeable towillhermaximsorprinciples tobeuniversal.His reasoningseemstobesomethinglikethefollowing.

personality.Here, I disagreewithAllenWood,Kant’s Ethical Thought (NewYork:CambridgeUniversityPress,1999),118−21.

Page 17: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –17– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

against normative perfectionism. If normative perfectionism is anethicaltheorythatgroundsethicalrequirementsinmoralpersonalityorthereasons-responsivecapacitytosetandactforthesakeofends,thentheessentialsofKant’sownethicaltheoryadmitofanormativeperfectionist reading. For he regards both the grounds and contentofmoralrequirementsasconsisting inmoralpersonalityorrationalnature.42

ThisnormativeperfectionistreadingofKant’sethicssuggestssometentative and partial verdicts on the choice pointswithin the archi-tecture of normative perfectionism. It is common to readKant as adeontologistforwhomtherightispriortothegoodinvariousways,butifwethinkofperfectionismasateleologicaldoctrine,wemaybeskepticalofperfectionistreadingsofKant.Butwehavereasontoques-tiontheseorthodoxies.

First,thenormativeperfectionistreadingofKantstressesthewayinwhich the requirements of themoral law depend on the uncon-ditionedvalueof rationalnature. It’s true that themoral law issuesdemandsandrequirementsthatconstrainourpursuitofcertaingoods.Thisisclear,forinstance,inKant’sdiscussionthehighestgood.KantdiscussesthehighestgoodmostfullyintheCritique of Practical Reason (KpV 5: 108−10), just prior tohis criticismsof eudaimonism.Hede-scribesthehighestgoodasacomplexwholeconsistingofvirtueandhappiness inwhich thevalueofhappiness is conditionedbyvirtue(KpV5:109−11).Onthisconception,thehighestgoodincludeshappi-ness,buthappinessonlyhasvaluewhenconditionedbyandinpro-portiontovirtue.Sohappinessisagoodwhosevalueisconditionedbyduty.43Butaswesaw,Kant’sconceptionofhappinessissubjective,

interpretationofKantandhisrelationtoAristoteliannaturalism,thoughIr-windoesnotconceptualizehis readingofKantasaperfectionistone.SeeIrwin,The Development of Ethics,vol.III,chs.66−72.

42. Moreover,Kanttreatsmoralperfectionasthegoalofhumanhistoryinhisprogressiveviewofhistoryasthequesttoperfecthumanity’srationalnature(History;Lectures Collins27:470).

43. Forausefuldiscussion,seeStephenEngstrom,“HappinessandtheHighestGoodinAristotleandinKant”inAristotle, Kant and the Stoics.

What,ifanything,wouldwewilljustinsofaraswearerationalbe-ings?Kant thinks that insofarasone is rationalonewillmakeratio-nalnatureone’send(G 4:428). Happiness,heclaims,canhaveonlyconditionedorinstrumentalvalue;rationalnaturealonehasintrinsicvaluethatdoesnotdependoncontingentandvariablecircumstances.Soonlyrationalnaturecouldbevaluedregardlessofone’scontingentcircumstancesandsentiments.Rationalnature is thecapacity tosetendsandact for thesakeofends(G4:428,430−31;KpV5:87).Butthenarationalagentwillvalueactivitiesandlivesthatexpressratio-nalnature.AndKantmightarguethatarationalagenthasnootherbasisforfindinganythingintrinsicallyvaluable.Moreover,ifIchooserationalagencysolelyinsofarasIamarationalbeing—solelyinvirtueofthepropertiesofrationalagentsassuch—thenitseemsIchoosetodeveloprationalagencyassuch,andnottherationalagencyof thisorthatparticularrationalbeing(G4:427).Ifso,thenF1directsmetobeconcernedaboutotherrationalagents,asrationalagents,fortheirownsakes.ThisisKant’ssecondmainformulaoftheCategoricalIm-perative—theFormulaofHumanity.

F2:Treathumanity,whetherinyourownpersonorthatofanyrationalagent,alwaysasanendinitselfandnevermerelyasameans(G 4:429).

ThisishowhegetsfromgroundtocontentandfromUniversalitytoHumanity.

Perfectionist readings of Kant’s ethics are uncommon, partly be-causeofhiscritiqueofperfectionismandrelateddoctrines, suchaseudaimonism. 41Butwesaidthatthosecriticismsdonotgettraction

41. PaulGuyer explores aperfectionist readingofKant in “KantianPerfection-ism”inPerfecting Virtue: New Essays on Kantian Ethics and Virtue Ethics,ed.Law-renceJostandJulianWuerth(NewYork:CambridgeUniversityPress,2011).HecontrastsWolff’sconceptionofperfectionismasperfectingone’srationalpowers,whichKantcriticizes,andaKantianconceptionofperfectionismthatappealstotheunconditionalvalueofautonomy.IamsympatheticwiththeroleofautonomyinGuyer’sinterpretationofKant,thoughIthinkthevalueofautonomyisitselfgroundedinmoralpersonality.Therearealsobroadaffini-tiesbetweenmynormativeperfectionistreadingofKant’sethicsandIrwin’s

Page 18: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –18– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

Consider theappropriateattitude towardrationalnature in inter-personal contexts.Onemight treat theHumanityFormulaas recog-nizing rational nature as a side-constraint on action—never act soastotreatrationalagentsasmeremeans.Suchaside-constraintmayseemtoimposeadutytohonor,ratherthanpromote,rationalnatureinothers.ButnoticethattheHumanityFormuladoesn’tprohibittreat-ingpeopleasmeans—thatwouldbeaveryrestrictiveinjunction.Weregularlytreatpeopleasmeansincivilsociety,makingcontractsandavailingourselvesof theservicesofothers.Rather, itprohibits treat-ingpeopleasmeremeans.SotheHumanityFormulaprohibitstreatingothersasiftheyweremeretools,withnowell-beingoragencyoftheirown.Wemust treat theminwaysthatreflectconcernfor theirwell-beingoragency.Butthatdoesnotmeanthatwemaynevertreatthemasmeanstopromotetheagencyofothers.ThatpossibilitydoesnotseemtoberuledoutbytheHumanityFormula.

Finally,onemightinvokeKant’sclaimsaboutthedignityofrationalnaturetoshowthathethinksitisavaluethatmustbehonored,ratherthanpromoted,inbothintrapersonalandinterpersonalcontexts. 44IntheGroundwork,Kantcontraststhingshavingapriceandthingshav-ingdignity:

Inthekingdomofends,everythinghaseitherapriceordignity.Whateverhasaprice canbe replacedby some-thingelseasitsequivalent;ontheotherhand,whateverisaboveallprice,andthereforeadmitsofnoequivalent,hasadignity.[G 4:434]

Kantgoesontosaythathappinessandthingsthatproducehappinesshaveaprice,butthathumanity,understoodaspersonalityorrationalnature,hasdignity(G 4:435−36).Thingsthathaveapricearefungible,whereasthingsthatdisplaydignityare“infinitelybeyondallprice”(G 4:435).Wemightthinkofdignityas asuitthattrumpsallothersuits.Withnon-trump suits, it is always thehighest value card that takes

44. Forusefuldiscussion,seeThomasE.Hill,“HumanityasanEndinItself”Eth-ics91(1980):84−99.

consistinginthesatisfactionofdesireswhoseultimateobjectisplea-sure.Thegoodsof(Kantian)happinessandnormativeperfectionarevery different. Crucially, moral personality is unconditionally good,whereas(Kantian)happinessisgoodonlyconditionally.Insofarasthegroundofdutyrestsontheunconditionalvalueofrationalnature,aperfectionistgoodisarguablypriortotheright.

Second,insofarasKantcanbereadasanormativeperfectionist,itwouldappearthathisperfectionismisimpartial,ratherthanegocen-tric.AstheHumanityFormulamakesclear,thefundamentalmoralde-mandistorespectthevalueofrationalagencyineveryperson.Con-cernfortherationalagencyofothersisnotderivativeinthewayitisforegocentricformsofnormativeperfectionismthatweencounterinAristotleandGreen.Inthisrespect,Kant’sperfectionismhasmoreincommonwithMill’sperfectionistutilitarianism,howevermuch theymaydifferinotherrespects.

Third,we can askwhetherKantianperfectionism instructs us tohonororpromoterationalnatureinourselvesandothers.Manyread-erswillassumethatKantiandeontologyimpliesthatthecorrectori-entationtowardthevalueofrationalnature is tohonor,ratherthanpromote,it.Evenifthisistrue,itdoesn’tblockaperfectionistreadingofKant,becausewesaidthatwhethertohonororpromoterationalnaturewasachoicepointwithinnormativeperfectionism.

However, thisdeontological readingofKant’s attitude toward ra-tionalnaturedeservesscrutiny.Promotingrationalnatureseemsplau-sibleintheintrapersonalcase.AswesawinMill’sdiscussionofself-slavery,theprohibitiononsellingoneselfintoslaveryrequiresthatwepromote,ratherthanhonor,rationalagency.InhisdiscussionofdutiestooneselfintheGroundwork,Kantsaysthatrationalnatureisnotjustaconstraintonhowoneleadsone’sownlife,butthatouractions“mustharmonize [zusammenstimmen] with it,”seeking“thefurtherance”(Beför-derung)ofthisend(G 4:430).Furtheringanendinvolvespromotingit,whichmightrequireforegoingsomeopportunitiestohonorit,forthesakeofitsbetterrealization.

Page 19: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –19– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

conclusions of interest to the perfectionist reading of Kant’s ethics.First,because thequestionwhether topromoteorhonormoralper-sonalityisachoicepointwithinnormativeperfectionism,thepossibil-ityofanormativeperfectionistreadingofKantdoesnotturnonhowhethinksweshouldbeorientedtowardrationalnature.Second,uponcloserinspection,severalclaimsthatKantiscommittedtohonoring,ratherthanpromoting,rationalnatureappearproblematic.Moreover,there is someevidence thatKant thinks that the correct attitude to-wardrationalnatureinbothintrapersonalandinterpersonalcontextsrequiresthatitbepromoted.Third,evenifKantisnotcommittedtopromotingrationalnature,wecanconstructaformofnormativeper-fectionismthatisotherwiselikeKant’sethicaltheorybutiscommittedtopromoting,ratherthanhonoring,rationalnature.

5. Is the Appeal to Rational Nature Incomplete?

So far, normative perfectionism seems well positioned to addresssomeofKant’sexplicitworriesaboutperfectionismandrelateddoc-trines,suchaseudaimonism,andtoaccommodatewhatisreasonableinKant’s concerns. Indeed,wehaveseen reason to takeseriouslyanormativeperfectionistreadingofsomecentralaspectsofKant’sownethicaltheory.

ThismakesitappropriatetoaddressaworrythathasbeenraisedabouttheadequacyofKant’sownappealstorationalnature,becausenormative perfectionism appeals to rational nature in many of thewaysthatKantdoes.Thegeneralworryisthattheidealsofrationalityandperfectiondonotthemselvesprovidecompleteethicalguidance.Rationalityisamatterofrecognizingandrespondingtoreasons,butthen rationality does not provide adequate guidancewithout somespecificationofthesubstantivereasonsforactionthatarationalagentwouldrecognizeandweigh.Similarly,perfection,understoodintermsof thedevelopment and exercise ofmoral personality andpracticalreason,doesnotseemtoprovideadequateguidance.Wedeliberateby recognizing and weighing goods and reasons. But then practi-calreasonordeliberationseemstobean incompleteguidewithout

thetrick.Butthelowestvaluecardinatrumpsuitbeatsthehighestvaluecardinanynon-trumpsuit.WemightinterpretKantassaying,ineffect,thatrationalnatureisatrumpsuitandthatitisneverpermis-sibletoviolateorcompromiserationalnatureasameansofpromotingothergoods,suchashappiness,thathavemereprice.

Wecanthinkofthisclaimthatrationalnaturehasdignityasclaimaboutvalue that recognizesdiscontinuitiesbetween thevalueof ra-tional agencyandothergoods. In thisway,Kant’s claimsabout thesupremevalueofdignityinrelationtoothergoodscouldbelikenedtoMill’sclaimsinChapterIIofUtilitarianism aboutthevalueofhigherpleasuresinrelationtolowerpleasureswhenhesaysthatacompetentjudgewouldpreferthesmallestamountofhigherpleasuretothelarg-estamountoflowerpleasure(UII5;CWX211).Justaspromotinghap-pinessforMillwillnotallowtrade-offsofhigherandlowerpleasures,sotoocouldKantclaimthatpromotingrationalnaturewillnotallowtrade-offsbetweenrationalnatureandhappinessbecausetheformerisdiscontinuouslybetterthanthelatter.

But even if rationalnature trumpsother goods, there canbeun-avoidableconflictsinthedemandsofrationalnature.Evenifthelow-estvaluecard ina trumpsuitbeats thehighestvaluecard inanon-trumpsuit,within the trumpsuit, thehighest cardinalitywins.Thiswouldimplythatinsituationswheretheclaimsofrationalnaturecon-flict,Kantmayhavereasontopromoteormaximizerationalnature.Aswe saw in§3, he thinks theHumanity Formula requires thatweharmonizepositively,andnotjustnegatively,withrationalnature,fur-theringtheagencyofothers(G 4:430).Thissuggeststhatweshouldtakerationalnature,whereverwefindit,asavaluetobepromoted.Atleast,itdoesn’trulethisout.45

This discussion of whether Kant thinks that rational nature is avaluetobepromotedorhonoredinintrapersonalandinterpersonalcontextshasbeeninconclusive.Butitissufficienttoestablishseveral

45. Kant’sviewcouldbenotthatwepromoterationalnatureevenifthismeansharmingindividualrationalagents,butratherthatwehaveadutytopromoterationalagencybutonlyinwaysthatneverviolaterationalagency.

Page 20: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –20– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

recognizing a diversity of good lives exercising practical reason incomparablygoodbutdifferentways,butitisnotcontent-neutral.

By contrast, the moderate critique needs to be takenmore seri-ously.Accordingtothemoderatecritique,evenifperfectionistvaluesarenotempty,theyprovideanincompleteethicalguideandneedtobe supplemented by additional non-perfectionist kinds of value orreasons.Differentmoderate critiquesmight appeal todifferentnon-perfectionistvalues.Presumably,anyconceptionofethicalguidancethat recognizesasetofperfectionistgoodsas incompletewouldbepluralistincharacter.Somefamiliarpluralistconceptionsofthegoodinclude knowledge, achievement, pleasure, beauty, friendship, andmoralgoods.48Themoderatecritiqueisthatadequateethicalcontentpresupposessomesuchpluralistconceptionthatisnotexhaustedbyperfectionistgoods.

Adequatelyaddressingthemoderatecritiqueisbeyondthescopeofthisessay.Butwecanframehowthatdiscussionmightproceedbydistinguishingdifferentkindsofresponsetothatcritique.Inparticular,wecandistinguishmoreandlessconcessiveresponses,dependingonhowmanynon-perfectionistvalueswerecognizeandhowimportanttheyare.

Perhapsthemostconcessiveresponsewouldbetodefendaformofpartial perfectionismthatisbasedonamixedconceptionofthegoodthat includes perfectionist elements. Even if perfectionismprovidesincompleteguidanceandmustbesupplementedbyalistofindepen-dentobjectivegoods,evenaverylonglist,itwouldstillbetruethatourconceptionofthegoodwouldbeincompleteifitdidnotrecognizeperfectionistgoods.

Alessconcessiveresponsewouldbetoembraceaformofdominant perfectionismthatrecognizesamixedconceptionofthegoodinwhichperfectionist goods aremost important.There aredifferentways inwhich perfectionist goodsmight dominate others. First, even if we

48. See,e.g.,W.D.Ross,The Right and the Good(Oxford:ClarendonPress,1930),27,102,140andDerekParfit,Reasons and Persons(Oxford:ClarendonPress,1984),499−502.

somespecificationoftheobjectivegoodsandsubstantivereasonsthatshouldguidedeliberation.

We can distinguish radical andmoderate versions of this worryabouttheadequacyofperfectionism’sguidance.Theradical critique,fa-miliarfromHegeliancriticismsofKant,isthatrationalityisaformalorproceduralconceptand,hence,isemptyorwithoutcontent.46Bycon-trast,themoderate critiqueisthatrationalnaturehascontentandpro-videssomeguidancebutdoesnotprovidecompleteguidancewithoutaspecificationofsubstantivereasonsorobjectivegoods.47

Wecanrejecttheradicalcritiqueinsofarasmoralpersonalitypro-videsboththegroundandcontentofmorality.Aswesaw,Kantarguesthatmoralrequirementsapply invirtueofournatureasagentsandthatwhatwecanvalue insofarasweare rationalagents is rationalnature,whichcommitsustotherequirementtotreatrationalnaturealwaysasanendandnotmerelyasameans.ThisishowhegetsfromgroundtocontentandUniversalitytoHumanity.Similarly,thenorma-tiveperfectionistidentifiesnormativeidealswithactivitiesandlivesthat realize our capacities as agents. Content is a function ofwhatis ruledout, and thepre-eminent valueof rationalnature rules outsomekindsoflives.Thereareavarietyofkindsoflivesandactivitiesinwhichonecanexerciseone’srationalcapacitieswell.Butrationalnature speaks against selling oneself into slavery anddiscriminatesbetweenhigherandlowerpleasures,betweentheexaminedlifeandthelifeofsensorycontentment,betweenaself-directedlifeinwhichonemeetsandcopeswithvariouschallengesandashallowandun-demanding life, andbetween the lifeof anartisanwhohas controloverthenatureofherworkandthedistributionofherproductsandthelifeofacouchpotato.Normativeperfectionismcanbepluralistic,

46. SeeG.W.F.Hegel,The Philosophy of Right, trs.T.Knox (Oxford:ClarendonPress,1952)§135R.BradleydevelopstheHegeliancritiqueinFrancisHerbertBradley,Ethical Studies,2d.ed.(Oxford:ClarendonPress,1927),145−63.

47. See, e.g.,DonaldRegan, “TheValueofRationalNature”Ethics 112 (2002):267−91.

Page 21: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –21– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

terms.Where accommodation is not possible, reform recommendsdenyingthattheallegedgoodsaregenuinegoods.Themeritsofac-commodationandreformdependonhowmuchtheperfectionistcanaccommodate,howmuchrequiresreform,andwhethertheresultingreformsseemreflectivelyacceptable.Thisstrategywouldhavetobeassessedon a case-by-casebasis by considering allegednon-perfec-tionistgoodsandevaluatingstrategiesforaccommodationandreform.Here,Icanonlysketchwhatsuchadiscussionmightlooklike.

Knowledge and Achievement.Itisnothardtounderstandhowknowl-edge or achievement might be understood as perfectionist values.Knowledgeisarguablythestateatwhichourcapacitiesfortheoreti-cal reasonaim,andcertainkindsofachievementsarewhatweaimat inourpracticaldeliberations.Wecanunderstandhowanappealtopracticalagencymightexplaintheperfectionistvalueofpracticalachievements, andwe can understand how an appeal to epistemicagencymight explain the perfectionist value of knowledge, butwemightdoubt that either conceptionof agency canexplainboth.Thisworryraisesinterestingquestionsabouttheabilitytoexplaintheoreti-calachievementsintermsofpracticaldeliberationaboutourmentalactsandtheabilitytoexplainpracticalaccomplishmentsintermsoftheoreticalreasoningaboutpracticalmatters.Butthereisnoneedforreductive explanations of either kind, provided that normative per-fectionismisgrounded,asGreenbelieves,inaunifiedconceptionofagency—onethatseesrationalagentsasreasons-responsiveinwaysthatmakethembothpracticallyandepistemicallyresponsible.

Pleasure.Itiscommontoregardhedonicvaluesasnon-perfectionistvalues.Pleasureistobesoughtandpaintobeavoidedinthemselves,independentlyoftheirrelationtoperfection.Painisoftenextrinsicallybadinsofarasitisaninsistentformofconsciousnessthatdistractsonefromthepursuitofone’sactivitiesand,hence,impedesthepursuitofperfectionistgoods.Indeed,ifthenatureofpainistobeinsistentanddisruptiveinthisway,thentheperfectionistcanevenrecognizepainas beingnon-instrumentally bad. The interesting anddifficult ques-tioniswhetherpleasureisinherentlygoodandpainisinherentlybad

mustacceptamixedconceptionofthegood,itmightstillbetruethatperfectionistgoodsareindividually the most important goodsinsofarastheyexercisethemostgeneralandimportantconstraintonthecon-tentofanethicallife.Second,perfectionistgoodsmightconditionthevalueofothergoods,sothattheotherelementsonlycountasgenuinegoodswhentheydonotoffendagainstorcompromiseperfectionistelements.49Onsuchaview,perfectionistdemandstodevelopandex-erciseone’sownnormativepowersandthoseofotherrationalagentsconstrainwhatotherthingsmightbegood.Third,whetherornotper-fectionistgoodsarethemostimportantindividualgoodsortheonlyunconditionalgoods,theymightbesuperordinate goods.Onemightdis-tinguishbetweenprimaryandsecondarygoods.Thoughperfectionistgoodsareamongtheprimarygoods,theymayalsobeimportantsec-ondarygoodsinsofaraspracticalreasonisexercisedinthecompari-sonofprimarygoods,thecorrectorderingofprimarygoods,andtheresolutionofconflictsamongprimarygoods.Ifso,practicalreasonisanimportantsecondaryorsuperordinategood.Ifperfectionistgoodsarebothprimaryandsuperordinategoods,thenourconceptionofthegoodisarguablyaformofdominantperfectionism.Thecasefordomi-nantperfectionismwillbeevenstrongerifperfectionistgoodsaretheindividuallymostimportantprimarygoodsortheonlyunconditionalgoods.

Bothoftheseresponsestothemoderatecritiqueconcedethatthecorrectconceptionof thegoodmustbemixed,containingbothper-fectionist and non-perfectionist elements. A still less concessive re-sponsewouldbetodefendpure perfectionism.Here,theideawouldbetocombine twopureperfectioniststrategies—accommodationandre-form.Accommodationbringsapparentlynon-perfectionistgoodsun-dertheperfectionistumbrella,explainingtheirvalueinperfectionist

49. ThissortofviewmightbestructurallysimilartoKorsgaard’sideathatrationalnatureconditionsorconstrainsthereasonsthatreflectiveendorsementandpracticalidentityprovide.SeeChristineKorsgaard,The Sources of Normativity (NewYork:CambridgeUniversityPress,1996)andChristineKorsgaard,Self-Constitution: Agency, Identity, and Integrity (Oxford:OxfordUniversity Press,2009).

Page 22: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –22– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

atedbyintelligentbeingswouldstillbebeautifulandcontributetothevalueoftheworldsinwhichtheyoccurevenwhentheywereneitherthe product of creative activity nor the object of aesthetic apprecia-tion.Butthisisnotclear.Infact,therearetwoclaimsthatMooremustestablish—first,thatthereisbeautyinaworldwithnosentientcrea-tures,andsecond,thatbeautyinsuchaworldisanintrinsicgood.Butbothclaimsareopen todoubt.WemayregardDaVinci’sVenusdeMiloasbeautiful.ButthemethodofisolationrequiresustoimagineaworldcontainingapieceofstonewiththesamequalitativepropertiesastheVenusbutthatwasneithertheproductofcreativedesignnortheobjectofaestheticappreciation—perhapsoccurring ina lifelessworldastheresultoferosion.Itissimplynotclearthatthestoneinthatworldisbeautiful.PerhapsthebestcaseforMoore’sclaimaboutbeauty is natural beauty.Would a landscape containing the GrandCanyonbemorebeautifulthanasparelunarlandscapeevenifnosen-tientcreatureeverappreciatedit?Onecandoubtthatthereisbeautyin worlds without sentient creatures, and even if we do recognizebeautyinworldsinwhichsentientcreaturesareneitherproducersnorconsumersofbeauty,wemaywonderifthoseworldsarebetterasaresult.Ifso,wemightthinkthatbeautyisarelationalgoodandthatitsvalueliesinitsrelationtoperfectionistvalues.

Friendship.Friendshipmightseemtobeanon-perfectionistgoodthatnonethelessoughttoguidechoice.However,allthreeofourpara-digmaticnormativeperfectionistsbelievethatcertain formsof inter-personalassociationextendandcompletetheagent’srationalnature.

Aristotlebelieves that in the right sortof friendship,one’s friendprovides a kindofmirror ononeself and soprovides aperspectivethatmakes self-understanding and self-criticismpossible, providingakindofcompletionorperfectionforcognitivelylimitedbeings(NE 1162a20−24,1169b4−6,1170a5−7;EE1244b1−12;MM1212b24−1213b2;Politics1261b10−15).Moreover,hethinksthatinthebestsortoffriend-ships,friendsshareexperiencesanddiscussioninawaythatprovidesinterpersonal psychic unity that is relevantly like intrapersonal uni-ty.Thisunity,hethinks,isthebasisforeachregardingtheotherasa

independentlyof their effectsonone’s valuable activities.Comparethelivesoftwoartistswhoareeachengagedincreativework,produc-ingbeautifulart,andexercisingcontrolovertheirprofessionallives.Oneofthemappreciatesthevalueshecreatesandtakesdelightinherart,whiletheotherisdepressedandtakesnojoyinherart.Clearly,itmightseem,thefirstlifeisbetterthanthesecond,eventhoughtheyseemtorealize thesameamountofperfectionistvalue.Thenaturalexplanationforthisdifferenceinvalueisthatpleasureisanindepen-dent,non-perfectionist value.But in this case, thepleasure that theoneartisthasthattheotherlacksappearstobeadelight in her creative activity.FollowingtheleadofAristotle,theStoics,Leibniz,andWolff,wemight treat suchdelight as anappreciation of perfectionist value,andthisappreciationmightseemtobeafurtherperfectionistvalue.50 Whetherallgenuinehedonicgoodscanbefitundertheperfectionistumbrellainthiswayisanopenquestion.

Beauty.Itissometimessaidthatbeautyisanobjectivegood,whichcanandshouldguidechoice.Onsomeviews,beautymightwellbeanindependentnon-perfectionistgood.G.E.Moorethoughtthatifoneappliedhismethodofisolation,inwhichoneimaginessomethinginisolationfromsentientbeingstoseeifithasvalueinthosesituations,onewouldseethatbeautywasanobjectivegood.51Ifwecompareabarelunarlandscapewithasimilarlandscapecontainingourfavoriteworkofart,wewillseethatthesecondworldisbetterthanthefirst.Thisfactatteststotheobjectivevalueofbeauty,orsoMoorethought.Butworksofartareartifacts,createdbyartistsandtypicallyconsumedandappreciatedbyaudiences.Forthemethodofisolationtoevidencethatbeautyisanobjectivevalue,wewouldhavetoimaginethatob-jectsthatarebeautifulandchoiceworthywhenproducedandappreci-

50.Cf.RobertAdams,Finite and Infinite Goods: A Framework for Ethics(NewYork:OxfordUniversityPress,1999),93−101.Adamsproposestounderstandthepersonalgoodastheenjoymentoftheexcellent.Iwouldadd,first,thattheexcellentisgoodevenwhenitisnotenjoyed(evenifitisbetterstillwhenitisenjoyed),andsecond,thattheenjoymentoftheexcellentisitselfexcellent.

51. G.E.Moore,Principia Ethica(Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress,1903),83−84,90−91.

Page 23: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –23– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

become tohimashimself and inproviding forhimselfheprovides for them.Projectinghimself intothefutureas a permanent subject of possiblewell-being or ill-be-ing—andhemustsoprojecthimselfinseekingforaper-manentgood—heassociateshiskindredwithhimself.Itisthisassociationthatneutralisestheeffectwhichthean-ticipationofdeathmustotherwisehaveonthedemandforapermanentgood.[§231]

Greenclaimsthatinterpersonalpermanenceisanextensionofintrap-ersonalpermanence,implyingthattherightsortofinterpersonalasso-ciationmakesthegoodofone’sassociatepartofone’sown.Interper-sonalassociationunderminesthepopularcontrastbetweenself-loveandloveofothers(§232)andgiveseachassociateareasontopursueacommongood(§202).

Ofcourse,thedetailsoftheseperfectionistrationalesforfriendshipneedtobefilledinanddefended,butsuchclaimspromisetobringthegoodoffriendshipundertheperfectionistumbrella.

Moral Goods.Wemightconcedethepromiseofpureperfectionismasanaccountofprudentialvaluebutharbordoubtsaboutitsadequa-cytoexplaintheimportanceofother-regardingmoralvirtues,suchasjustice.Differentformsofnormativeperfectionismhavedifferentcom-mitmentshere.Anyagent-neutralorotherwiseimpartialconcernforrationalagentswillbuildconcernforothersinatafoundationallevel.SoaperfectionistlikeMillorKantseemstohavenospecialproblemaccommodatinganagent’sconcernforthegoodofothers.Bycontrast,eudaimonistperfectionistshaveagent-relativeoregocentricconcernfortheagent’sownrationalagency.SoperfectionistssuchasAristotleorGreenneed toexplainhowaconcern forothersemergeswithinaeudaimonist frameworkbyexplaininghow the rationalagencyofotherscontributestotheagent’sownrationalagency.However,bothAristotleandGreendobelievethatanagent’sownperfectionrequirespursuitofacommongood.Myremarksaboveabouthowtheyprovideaperfectionistexplanationoffriendshipandotherassociationalgoods

second self,whoseinterestsarepartofhisandforwhomhecaresfortheother’sownsake(NE 1166a1−2,10,1166a30−32,1168b1−1169a12).52

Mill believes that friends enhance each other’s higher facultiesbyhelpingeachotherenlargethemenuofdeliberativeoptionsandbetter assess themerits of the options on themenu. This is an im-portantpartofhisperfectionistdefenseoffreedomofexpressionandassociation(OLII20−33,III1;CWXVIII242−52,260−61).ButitalsoexplainstheuniquevalueheassignstofriendshipsamongequalsinhiscritiqueofVictoriansexualinequality(SWinCWXXI293−95,326,334−36).Equalstandingmakespossibleformsofpersonalassociationthatfosterdiscussionandcooperation,makeeachaccountabletotheother,andenableeachtorealizeherhighernature.53

Greeninsiststhatproperself-realizationshouldaimatacommongood,whichincludesthegoodofotherrationalagents.Aself-realizingagentdoesnotactonpassingwhimsorpassionsbutactsforthesakeofendsperceivedasvaluableandperseveresontheirbehalf,makingshort-terminvestmentsandsacrificesforthesakeoftheseends.ThisistovaluegoalsandprojectsinwhichIaminvolvedthathavesomedegreeofpermanence.Greenthinksthattherightsortofassociationwithothersextends thispermanence inanaturalway (PE §199). In-deed,Greenregardsinterpersonalpermanenceasakindofcounter-balancetomortalityorsurrogateforimmortality:

Thatdeterminationofananimalorganismbyaself-con-sciousprinciple,whichmakesamanandispresupposedby the interest inpermanentgood,carrieswith itacer-tain appropriationby theman tohimself of thebeingswithwhomheisconnectedbynaturalties,sothatthey

52. FordiscussionsofGreekeudaimonistconceptionsoffriendshipthatempha-sizethesethemes,seeIrwin,Plato’s Ethics,ch.18;TerenceIrwin,Aristotle’s First Principles(Oxford:ClarendonPress,1988),ch.18;DavidO.Brink,“Self-loveandAltruism”Social Philosophy & Policy14(1997):122−57;andDavidO.Brink,“Eudaimonism,LoveandFriendship,andPoliticalCommunity”Social Philoso-phy & Policy16(1999):252−89.

53. IdiscusstheroleofperfectionistvaluesinMill’sdiscussionofliberalassocia-tionsandfriendshipsamongequalsinMill’s Progressive Principles,chs.6−11.

Page 24: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –24– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

supportcosmopolitanconcernforothersmayseemclosertotheStoicthantheAristotelianview.54

Thoughthediscussionofpureperfectionismanditsresourceshasnecessarily been abstract and suggestive, it shows promise for theprojectofextendingthedomainofthenormativeperfectionistempire.Whetherallgenuinegoodsadmitofperfectionistanalysisremainsanopenquestion,worthfurtherinvestigation.Evenifwecannotextendtheperfectionistdomainas faras thepureperfectionistmust, thereremainmoreconcessiverepliesthatrecognizetheimportanceofper-fectionist goods within mixed or pluralist conceptions. DefendingtheseclaimstakesthenormativeperfectionistbeyondexplicitKantianresourcesbutprovidesadefenseoftheimportanceofrationalnaturethatboththenormativeperfectionistandtheKantianneed.

Moreover, we can now appreciate a connection between theseworriesaboutthecompletenessoftheappealtorationalnatureandKant’sfirstcriticismthatperfectionismyieldshypothetical,ratherthancategorical,imperatives.Recallfrom§2thatKantthinksLeibnizandWolffaremetaphysicalperfectionistswhomakearationalwilldepen-dentonmetaphysical principlesof unity, order, andfittingness thatareexternal to thewill itself.Greenpromises to avoidKant’sobjec-tion insofar as he thinks the imperatives of self-realization dependonlyonaspectsofmoralpersonality. In thisrespect,Green’snorma-tiveperfectionismappearsmorefullyKantianthantheperfectionismsofLeibnizandWolff.Butinthissection,wehaveseenthatthereisaquestionforbothKantiansandnormativeperfectionistswhethertheappealtomoralpersonalityorrationalnatureprovidescompleteguid-ancewithoutsupplementationbymaterialprinciplesaboutobjectivegoods and external reasons. If thenormativeperfectionist canbe a54. I discussGreen’s perfectionist justification of friendship and the common

good inPerfectionism and the Common Good, §§XV−XX andDavidO. Brink,“ThreeDualisms:Sidgwick,Green,andBradley”Collingwood and British Ideal-ism Studies25(2019):161−87.IdiscussAristotelianandStoiccommitmentsaboutthescopeofthecommongoodinDavidO.Brink,“EudaimonismandCosmopolitanConcern” inVirtue, Happiness, and Knowledge: Themes from the Work of Gail Fine and Terence Irwin,ed.DavidO.Brink,SusanSauvéMeyer,andChristopherShields(Oxford:ClarendonPress,2018).

indicatehowtheycouldbegintoexplaintheemergentvalueofmoralconcernfortheperfectionofotherswithinaeudaimonistframework.

Inthecontextofdiscussinganegocentricperfectionistjustificationofmoralconcern,it isworthmentioningGreen’sdisagreementwithAristotle about the scope of the common good. Both Aristotle andGreen think that interpersonal association provides a kind of inter-personalunityakintointrapersonalunityandforgesacommongoodamongassociatesthatgiveseachegocentricreasontocareabouttheassociate forhisownsake.Greenbelieves thatAristotlerecognizedtheway inwhich justice isconnectedwithacommongood,buthethinkstheGreekshadtoonarrowaconceptionofthecommongood.Green thinks agents have egocentric reasons to seek interpersonalpermanencewithwide scope:

The idea of a society of free and law-abiding persons,eachhisownmasteryeteachhisbrother’skeeper,wasfirstdefinitely formedamongtheGreeks,andits forma-tionwastheconditionofallsubsequentprogressinthedirectiondescribed;butwiththem…itwaslimitedinitsapplicationtoselectgroupsofmensurroundedbypopu-lationsofaliensandslaves.Initsuniversality,ascapableofapplicationtothewholehumanrace,anattempthasfirst beenmade to act upon it inmodernChristendom[PE §271].

Greenseesmoralprogressasconsisting inthegradualextensionofthe scopeof thecommongood,which isonlycompletewheneachrespectstheclaimsmadebyothermembersofamaximallyinclusivecommunityof ends (§§214, 216, 244, 332). Indeed,Green thinks theHumanityFormulaoftheCategoricalImperativeprovidesthecorrectinterpretationofthecommongood(§§202−17).Inthisrespect,Green’sbeliefthatanegocentricconcernwithself-realizationcanandshould

Page 25: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –25– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

onour rationalnature, theypromise tobedemandsof reason.TherationalisminKant’sethicsisasourceofitspersistentattractions,andinvirtueofitsappealtomoralpersonalityandrationalagency,norma-tiveperfectionismenjoysasimilarpromisetoexplainthenormativeauthorityofitsdemands.

Some writers doubt that ethical claims derived from the condi-tionsthatareconstitutiveofagencyenjoyrationalauthority,becauseitisalwaysopentorationalagentsnottocareaboutthedemandsofagency.Onthisview,rationalagentsarealwaysfreetorejectdemandsofagency.55Ofcourse,rationalagentsaremetaphysicallyfreetoresistwhat theyhave reason todo.But if therearedemands thatdependonlyonourrationalnatureasagents, thenagentsdisplay irrational-itywhentheyexercisethisfreedom.Itisrationaltocareaboutwhatrationalityconsistsin,andthereissomethingself-defeatingabouttheagentwhoasksforareasonwhysheshouldconformtothedemandsof rational agency. If there are lives that exercise those rational ca-pacitiesthatmakeusresponsibleagents,subjecttoreasonsforaction,thenwehavereasontocareaboutandpursuethosekindsoflives.

If so, there is something illegitimateabout thequestionwhetherrational agentshave reason todoas rationality requires.There is alegitimate question aboutwhether rational agency imposes any de-mands.Butthisisthedifferentquestionwhethertheappealtoratio-nalnaturehascontent.Weaddressed thatquestionearlier (§5)andarguedthatKantiansandnormativeperfectionistshavepromisingac-countsofhowrationalnatureprovidesnormativecontent.Whetherthenormativeguidance that rationalnatureprovides is complete isanothermatter.

There isa furtherquestionabout thenormativeauthorityofper-fectionist ideals that isworthaddressing.This is a challengenot tonormativeperfectionismperse,buttoitseudaimonistoregocentricversions. As we noted earlier (§1), nearly all of Greek ethics is eu-daimonist, treatingtheagent’sowneudaimoniaorhappinessasthe

55. See,e.g.,DavidEnoch,“Agency,Shmagency:WhyNormativityWon’tComefromWhatisConstitutiveofAgency”Philosophical Review115(2006):169−98.

pureperfectionist,explainingallethicalcontentintermsofmoralper-sonalityand itsexpression, then thenormativeperfectionistcanan-swerKant’sfirstcriticismofperfectionismonitsownterms.However,ifwemustacceptapluralistethicaltheory,inwhichrationalnatureissupplementedwithobjectivegoodsandexternalreasonsthatshouldguiderationalagency, thenwehavereasontorejectKant’sdemandthatmoralrequirementsdependonlyonrationalnature.

6. The Normative Authority of Perfection

A plausible ethical conception should be extensionally adequate. It shouldaccommodatemostofourconsideredjudgmentsaboutwhatsortsofactionsandlivesaregoodorbadandrightorwrongor,failingthat,provideuswithprincipled reasons for revisingourconsideredjudgments.Onthisscore,normativeperfectionismlookspromising.Itprovidessubstantialaccommodationandprincipledreform.Ifneces-sary,wecanachievegreateraccommodationbytreatingperfectionistgoodsasthedominantcomponentsinamixedconception.

Inadditiontoextensionaladequacy,aplausibleethicalconceptionalsoowesusanaccountofitsnormative authority.Whyshouldwecareabout conforming to its requirements?Once formulated, that ques-tionisnoteasytoanswer,andmanyfamiliarconceptionsdonotad-dressthatquestionorhaveunsatisfyinganswers.Forinstance,itisnotclearwhyweshouldcareaboutpleasureassuch,independentlyofitssources,objects,orconsequences.Equally,givenvariouspathologiesofdesire, it isnotclearwhyweshouldcareaboutsatisfyingdesiresindependentlyoftheirsources,objects,orconsequences.

Bycontrast,normativeperfectionismhasamorepromisinganswertoquestionsabout itsnormativeauthority.Bygroundingperfection-ist ideals inanormativeconceptionofhumannatureaspersonsoragents,normativeperfectionismexplainswhyweshouldcareabouttherealizationofperfectionistidealsbyappealingtotheverycapaci-tiesthatmakeusreasons-responsiverationalagentsinthefirstplace.In this respect, normative perfectionism enjoys the same appeal asKantianethics.Preciselybecausecategoricalimperativesdependonly

Page 26: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –26– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

forprovidingthewrongsortofreasontobejust.56Prichard’sessayiscomplexandnodoubtamenabletodifferentinterpretations.Butonecentralstranddeservesourattention.Inthe Republic, Platoasks“Whybejust?”whichwemightgeneralizetothequestion“Whybemoral?”Platoanswersthatjusticeisprofitablefortheagentbecauseitcontrib-utestohishavingawell-orderedsoul.Prichardinterpretsthisasade-mandforaninstrumentaljustificationofjustice.But,hethinks,moraldemandsoughttobedonefortheirownsakes.Ifso,Plato’squestionismisconceivedandhisanswerprovidesthewrongsortofreasontobejust.Plato’smistake,itmightbeclaimed,generalizestoanyegocentricversionofnormativeperfectionism.

One response to thisworry about egocentric versions of norma-tive perfectionism would be to adopt a non-egocentric version in-stead.A fundamentally impartial concernwith rationalnaturedoesnotfilter concern forothers through the lensof concernwithone’sownrationalnature.KantorMillmightbethemodelforthissortofnon-egocentricnormativeperfectionism.Alternatively,onemightre-jectPrichard’sclaimaboutPlato’smistake.InRepublicII, Platocananddoesdistinguishbetweensomething’sextrinsicconsequences,whichdependonmorethanthemerepresenceofthatthing,anditsintrin-sic consequences,whichdependonlyon thenatureof the thing inquestion.Withthisdistinctioninhand,GlauconandAdeimantuscanbe interpretedasconcedingthat justice isbeneficial for itsextrinsicconsequencesandaskingSocratestoshowthatjusticeisgoodforitsintrinsicconsequencestoo.Thatis,theydemandthatSocratesshowthat justice isalwayschoiceworthy invirtueof thebeneficial conse-quencesof justice itself.That is a coherent challenge,whichPlato’sSocratesaddresses,arguingthatjusticeisapsychicconditionwhoseintrinsicconsequencesarebeneficial.Ifso,justiceisgoodforitsownsakeoritsownreward,therebybenefittingthejustagent.

56.SeeH.A.Prichard,“DoesMoralPhilosophyRestonaMistake?reprintedinH.A.Prichard,Moral Obligation: Essays and Lectures(Oxford:ClarendonPress,1949).Acontemporaryworryaboutegocentricrationalesforother-regardingconcernwithsomeaffinitiestoPrichard’sworryabouteudaimonismisJen-niferWhiting,“ImpersonalFriends”The Monist74(1991):3−29.

centralor foundationalelement inethics.Eudaimonism takesaper-fectionistformprovidedthecontentoftheagent’shappinessdependsonhernature,andittakesaspecificallynormativeperfectionistformprovideditdependsonhermoralpersonalityorrationalnature.Plato,Aristotle,theStoics,andGreenareeudaimonistswhoarenormativeperfectionists. Eudaimonism implies that the virtues, including themoralvirtues,mustcontributetotheagent’sownhappinessinsomeway.Forthisreason,eudaimonistjustificationsofother-regardingcon-cernareegocentricandmusthaveaninside-outstructure,groundingother-regardingconcernintheagent’sowneudaimoniaorperfection.Thisegocentricconstraintgivesrisetotwoworries.

The first worry concerns the scope of ethical concern. If ethicalconcernmustbejustifiedfromtheinsideout,wemayworrythatthescopeofethicalconcernwillbelimitedandparochial.Theinside-outstrategylooksmostpromisingamongfriendsorothermembersofanassociationthathavesharedhistory.Butthenitmayseemasifanego-centricversionofnormativeperfectionismcouldnotjustifygenuinelycosmopolitanconcern.Thisisaworryabouttheextensionaladequacyof egocentricnormativeperfectionism. It couldbemetbyadoptinganon-egocentric versionofnormativeperfectionismof the sortwefindinKantorMillthatmakesconcernfortherationalnatureofoth-ersjustasfundamentalasconcernwithone’sownrationalnature.Al-ternatively,wemighttrytovindicatetheextensionaladequacyofanegocentricversionofnormativeperfectionismbyshowingthatitcaninfactdefendethicalconcernwithwidescope.Aswesawin§6,Greenthinkswecanreconcileeudaimonismandcosmopolitanconcern.

Asecondworryaboutegocentricversionsofnormativeperfection-ismconcernsthenormativeauthorityoftheiraccountofconcernforothers. An inside-out rationale for other-regarding concern claimsthat concern for others is awayof contributing to one’s owngood.Thismayseemlikethewrong sort of reasonforethicalconcernforoth-ers. In his essay “DoesMoral Philosophy Rest on aMistake?”H.A.PrichardfamouslyobjectedtoPlato’seudaimonistdefenseofjustice

Page 27: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –27– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

whyeachofusshouldbeconcernedwithherownrationalnature.Butwhyshouldweeachbeconcernedabouttherationalnatureofothers?PerhapsIshouldbeconcernedaboutrationalnatureassuch,whetherinmyownpersonorthatofanother.ThisiswhatKantandMillbe-lieve.Butitmightseemthatthegroundofmoralrequirementsmustlieintherationalagencyofeach.Ifso,wemightpreferanexplanationofconcernforotherrationalagentsthatisgroundedinanegocentricconcernforone’sownrationalagency.GreenthinksIshouldidentifywithmyrationalselfbecausethis istheself thatgroundsmoralper-sonality.Buthealsothinksthatsomeonecommittedtohisownratio-nalselfshouldbeinvestedinotherrationalselves;whiletheformerachievesintrapersonalpermanence,thelatterachievesinterpersonalpermanence. If so, egocentric normative perfectionism promises toprovideanexplanationoftheauthorityofcosmopolitanconcernthatimpartialformsofperfectionismdonot.

Thoughegocentricandimpartialformsofnormativeperfectionismhavedifferentresources,bothofferpromisingconceptionsofthenor-mativeauthorityofperfectionistdemands.57

7. The Prospects for Normative Perfectionism

Bycontrastwithformsofperfectionismthatappealtoabiologicalcon-ception of human nature, normative perfectionism grounds perfec-tionistidealsinanormativeconceptionofhumannature,understoodintermsofmoralpersonalityoragency.Thereisanimportanttradi-tionofnormativeperfectionism that includes theviewsofAristotle,Mill,andGreen.Inassessingtheprospectsfornormativeperfection-ism,wedowelltoconsideritsrelationtotheKantiantradition.Onemotivationfor thiscomparison is thatKant isan influentialcriticof

57.Wemightdistinguishbetweentheweakrationalistthesisthatmoralrequire-mentsenjoycategoricalauthorityandthestrongrationalistthesisthatmoralrequirements enjoy supreme or overriding authority. See David O. Brink,“KantianRationalism:Inescapability,Authority,andSupremacy”inEthics and Practical Reason,ed.GarrettCullityandBerysGaut(Oxford:ClarendonPress,1997).WhatIamdefendinghereistheweakerrationalistthesis,makingnocommitmentsaboutsupremacy.

Similarly, Aristotle offers an egocentric justification of other-re-gardingvirtues,suchas friendshipandjustice, that isderivativebutnon-instrumental(NE 1097a26−b7).Incompletegoodsarenotchosenfortheirownsakes;theyarechosenonlyforthesakeofsomethingelseandaremereinstrumentalgoods. Bycontrast,completegoodsarechosenfortheirownsakes;theyarenon-instrumentalgoods. Uncondi-tionally completegoodsarechosenfortheirownsakesandnotchosenforthesakeofanythingelse. Eudaimoniaistheonlyunconditionallycompletegood. Thismeansthatmerelycompletegoodsaregoodsinthemselvesbutarealsochosenforthesakeofeudaimonia,aspartsarechosenforthesakesofthewholesofwhichtheyareparts. Here,xisvaluableasconstituentofy;ithascontributoryvalueandisnon-instrumentally good. Aristotle claims that the virtues are complete,but not unconditionally complete, goods (1097a35−b7, 1100b8−11,1176b1−8). Theyarechoiceworthyinthemselvesaspartsofhappiness.Inmakingthisclaim,hemakesexplicitthesortofassumptionsPlatomakesabouttherelationshipbetweenjusticeandeudaimoniainRe-public II,wherehe(Plato)values justice for itsownsakeand for itsconstitutivecontributiontotheagent’sowneudaimonia.

Greenaccepts theseeudaimonist claims.He thinks thata self-re-alizingagentseeks interpersonal,andnot just intrapersonal,perma-nenceandthatthisrequirespursuitofacosmopolitanconceptionofthecommongood.Withinacommongood,Greenclaims,eachcaresaboutothersfortheirownsakesinthesamewayhecaresabouthim-self(PE §§232,236).ThoughGreentreatsthedemandforself-realiza-tionasanegocentricdemand,hethinksitnecessarilyrequirespursuitofacommongoodthatinvolvesnon-instrumentalconcernforothers.

Forthesereasons,weshouldbeskepticalthategocentricversionsofnormativeperfectionismprovidethewrongsortofreasonforother-regardingconcern.Theirjustificationofconcernforothersisderiva-tive, but non-instrumental. If so, then egocentrismneednot supplythewrongsortofreasontobemoral.Indeed,egocentrismmightbeanassetinaddressingthenormativeauthorityofperfectionistdemands.Aswehave seen, thenormativeperfectionisthasanexplanationof

Page 28: David O. Brink...% "vi brino. Normative Perectionism and the Kantian Tradition philosophers’ imprint – 3 – vol. 19, no. 45 (october 2019) claims about the human function, and

davido.brink Normative Perfectionism and the Kantian Tradition

philosophers’imprint –28– vol.19,no.45(october2019)

goodsorreasonsthatcanguiderationalagency.Inresponse,thenor-mative perfectionist has availablemore and less concessive replies.Eventhemostconcessiveresponseimpliestheimportanceofperfec-tionistgoods,withoutwhichaconceptionofthegoodwouldbeseri-ously incomplete.Thenormativeperfectionistmightbe lessconces-sive,arguingthatperfectionistgoodsdominateapluralistconceptionofthegood.Finally,theleastconcessivereplywouldbetobringalleg-edlynon-perfectionistvaluesundertheperfectionistumbrella.Whichisthebestresponsetothechargeofincompletenessdependsoncom-plexmattersofprincipledaccommodationandreformofourethicalassumptions.

Moreover,thenormativeperfectionist,liketheKantian,hasaprom-isingaccountofthenormativeauthorityofitsdemands,preciselybe-cause thesedemandsaregrounded inournatureas rationalagents.Thisgivesuscategoricalreasontoactonperfectionistdemands.More-over,wecandefend thenormativeauthorityof egocentricversionsofnormativeperfectionismagainstPrichard’sworrythattheyprovidethewrong sort of reason to care about others and their perfection.Egocentricnormativeperfectionismprovidesanagentwithderivativebutnon-instrumentalreasonforconcernfortheperfectionofothers.

GiventhebreadthandcomplexityoftheissuesassociatedwiththiscomparisonofthenormativeperfectionistandKantiantraditions,thisdiscussion has necessarily been selective and programmatic. None-theless,Ithinkitdemonstratestheinterestandresourcesofthenor-mativeperfectionisttraditionanditsdeepaffinitieswiththeKantiantradition,despiteKant’scriticismsofperfectionism.Moreover, thesetwotraditionshavetheresourcestorespondtoworriesthattheguid-anceprovidedbytheappealtorationalnatureisseriouslyincomplete.Theseconclusionsgiveusreasontoregardtheprospectsofnormativeperfectionismaspromisingandworthfurtherexploration.

perfectionism, claiming that it cannot generate categoricalmoral re-quirementsandthatwemustacceptaself/otherasymmetryinwhichweaimatourownperfectionbutatthehappiness,ratherthantheper-fection,ofothers.However,oncloserinspection,neitherobjectioniscompellingasappliedtonormativeperfectionism.Becauseitgroundsmoral requirements in rationalnature,normativeperfectionismcanrepresent moral requirements as categorical imperatives.Moreover,the role of autonomy inmoral personality shows that we can aimattheperfectionofanother,providedwedosoinwaysthatengage,ratherthanbypass,heragency.Sothenormativeperfectionistcanan-swerKantiandoubtsaboutperfectionismwhilerespectingKant’sowncommitmentstotheconnectionsamongagency,rationalnature,andmoralrequirements.Kant’scriticaltargetistheattempttofoundmo-ralityonanempiricistconceptionofhumannature.Butthenhehasnoreasontorejectattemptstofoundmoralityonanormativeconceptionofhumannaturethatunderstandshumannatureintermsofrationalagency.Indeed,Kanthimselfclearlywantstofoundmoralityonanap-pealtorationalnature,whichopensupthepossibilityofanormativeperfectionistreadingofKant’sownethicaltheory.ThatreadingmakesgoodsenseofKantianessentials,includingKant’sclaimthatrationalnatureprovidesboththegroundandcontentofmoralduty.

BecausebothKantandthenormativeperfectionistappealtoratio-nalnature,thenormativeperfectionisthasreasontotakeseriouslythecriticismofKantianethicsthatitsappealtorationalnatureisemptyorincomplete.Wehavegoodreasontorejecttheradicalversionofthiscriticism that theappeal to rationalnature is empty insofaras ratio-nalnaturesuppliesboththegroundandcontentofmoralduty.KantcanarguefromUniversalitytoHumanity,andtheHumanityformulahascontent,excludingsomeconductasimmoral.Aristotle,Mill,andGreenallrecognizewaysinwhichrationalnatureconstrainstheper-sonalgoodandethicaldemands.Even ifwereject theradicalclaimthattheappealtorationalnatureisempty,weshouldtakeseriouslythemoremoderate criticism that theappeal to rationalnature is in-completeandrequiressupplementationwithasetofnon-perfectionist