Crime and Punishment in Liberal Democratic Doctrine

download Crime and Punishment in Liberal Democratic Doctrine

of 14

Transcript of Crime and Punishment in Liberal Democratic Doctrine

  • 7/28/2019 Crime and Punishment in Liberal Democratic Doctrine

    1/14

    Crime and Punishment in Liberal Democratic Doctrine

    Sukumar Muralidharan

    Colloquiumon Capital Punishment: State and Society

    Indian Institute of Advanced Study, ShimlaMay 27 2013

    I thank the IIAS for this invitation to a colloquium which addresses

    an issue of profound moral significance. It is an issue that has been

    off the radar of public scrutiny and debate for a long while, thanks

    it seems to two presidents of the republic who chose evasion rather

    than a frontal engagement with the ethical issues it posed. It has

    been restored front and centre in the moral universe by a president

    who has suffered no such qualms and has it seems, quite gladly

    gratified a partisan political urge to seek electoral advantage from

    being seen to be tough on terrorism. The issue of the death penaltyhas in the process re-entered the public discourse. And maybe it is

    because I have a predisposition towards recognising only the points

    of view that are in accord with mine, I have a distinct feeling that

    the majority of expert commentary we have had since the two recent

    executions, has tended to see the death penalty as indefensible, both

    morally and legally.

    Where there have been efforts to justify the death penalty, these

    have not arisen from any manner of a rigorous assessment of its

    deterrent effect, but from a misplaced sense of deference to the law

    as it exists and the institutions that embody its processes andprinciples.

    The conventional moral calculus we are taught, holds that it is a far

    greater iniquity for one innocent man to be punished than for several

    wrong-doers to go free. It is a serious stigma for any kind of a

    political order, leave alone one that lays claims to being a

    democracy, to be accused of executing a person without adequate

    cause. Elaborate arguments are then advanced that the criteria of

    adequacy have been fulfilled, both in standards of proof needed to

    impose this ultimate sanction, and the requirements of fair procedure

    in evaluating all relevant evidence.

    Words of caution are offered to defuse the outrage, but little done

    to deprecate the unseemly revelry on display in certain quarters over

    executions carried out by the State. The conscience-stricken

    opponents of capital punishment are advised that too strong a

    denunciation of the processes through which the death penalty is

    awarded and enforced, will undermine popular faith in the

    institutions of governance. When all procedures prescribed under the

    law have been followed -- and the final recourse, which is the appeal

    for clemency, has been exhausted the public must simply learn to

    put up with the death penalty as a necessary evil, enforced for its

    own protection. That is part of the argument often heard in recent

  • 7/28/2019 Crime and Punishment in Liberal Democratic Doctrine

    2/14

    months: the death sentences recently implemented have been upheld by

    the Supreme Court which is final not because it is infallible, but

    invested with the cloak of infallibility because it is final.

    This is an argument for political conformity, for accepting the need

    for discrete silence where the credibility of the institutions ofgovernance is at stake. It also disregards several recent admissions

    from the highest court in the land that it has so far been absolutely

    unable to evolve sound and consistent norms for imposing the death

    penalty.1

    Before going any further into questions of ethics and political

    morality, let me turn towards something that I find a curiosity about

    the mood of agitation over the death penalty. Considered in purely

    numerical terms, the current level of public engagement with capital

    punishment might seem a bit of an indulgence. In the last eighteen

    years, we have had four executions under the law. There are, bycurrent estimations, fewer than five hundred convicts under the

    shadow of death, either at various stages in the appeals process or

    awaiting the outcome of mercy petitions. These are not insubstantial

    figures, but there is a strong probability that several among the

    five hundred on death row, in fact, the majority, would be reprieved

    at some point in the appeals process. The number whose final clemency

    pleas have been turned down would number fewer than twenty.

    The specific details of each prisoner trapped within the process that

    is designed to lead, ultimately, to his extinction as a person and an

    identity, needs to be explored. A modern liberal-democratic orderinstitutes a judicial process governed by certain universally

    accepted rules of fairness, beyond which, there is an opportunity

    afforded to the condemned man to invoke the power of mercy held in

    reserve by the sovereign he is obliged to serve. Once that recourse

    fails, he is left with no claims to staying alive. His life is as

    good as extinct.

    Purely as a detour into irony: the notion of the sovereign as the

    ultimate protector, which also reserves to itself the right to

    1

    In 2006, despite over a quarter century of evolving jurisprudence overthe death penalty emanating from the formulation in the Bachan Singh case

    that it should only be enforced in the rarest of rare cases, a two-judge

    bench of the Supreme Court effectively threw up its arms at the absence of

    clear norms. The bench of Justices S.B. Sinha and Dalveer Bhandari

    expressed its frustration rather directly, while commuting a death

    sentence: No sentencing policy in clear terms has been evolved by the

    Supreme Court. What should we do? (Cited in Lethal Lottery, A Study of the

    Death Penalty in India, Amnesty International India and the Peoples Union

    for Civil Liberties, Tamil Nadu and Pondicherry, May 2008, p 90). This

    volume also presents a number of arguments by a small but committed number

    of judges on the Supreme Court, especially in the 1980s, that made out a

    strong case for the abolition of the death penalty. Notable figures here

    would be V.R. Krishna Iyer, D.A. Desai, O. Chinnappa Reddy and P.N.Bhagwati.

  • 7/28/2019 Crime and Punishment in Liberal Democratic Doctrine

    3/14

    extinguish human life when provoked to extreme wrath, is obviously a

    legacy from less enlightened times of despotism. There was a practice

    in medieval times that an execution once ordered, had to be carried

    out swiftly. The executioner here was regarded as the kings

    champion, chosen to represent his will to do justice. Capital

    punishment was a gesture of absolute power that the sovereignauthority had reserved for himself, which necessarily would be

    imposed on one who had violated the law and caused injury to the

    body politic. If the execution was botched or for some reason

    failed, there would be a popular clamour for the pardon of the

    convict.2 A sovereign capable of implacable wrath and infallibility

    in establishing guilt and innocence, also had to execute his will

    with a comparable sense of purpose. A botched execution detracted

    from that image of a sovereign of unbending resolve and all-knowing

    power. It was an unwitting admission of fallibility which placed an

    obligation on him to rescind the sentence of death.

    Loosely applying these principles today, consider what it would mean

    for a government invested with the power to inflict death, that it

    should secure all necessary legal warrants for the purpose, but

    falter at the final stage. It is unable to determine if a convicted

    person deserves the invocation of the power of mercy. There is a

    failure of will and the edifice of absolute certainty and

    infallibility crumbles. A government that will brook no challenge to

    its will, fails to live upto its own self-image of being relentless

    in its determination to protect society from the reprobates who

    threaten its cohesion and peace. For the highest judicial body in the

    country to admit on various occasions that it has erred in theimposition of death is to shed the cloak of infallibility. Further, a

    delay in carrying out an execution represents a failure of will of

    the State.

    These arguments lead to a singular inference: with the transition

    from the medieval notion of the sovereign as the absolute power, to a

    modern principle of popular sovereignty, the death penalty itself

    needs to be abolished. To carry this argument any further, we need to

    make a further point: that popular sovereignty does not for its own

    purposes of self-affirmation, require the negation of life in any

    form, under any circumstances. From there we could conceivably moveon to making the further and stronger affirmation that the extinction

    of human life, whatever be the circumstances, is a negation of

    popular sovereignty.

    A plain assessment of relevant facts would show that we are a long

    way from arriving at either of these affirmations in the real world.

    The circumstances in which killing enjoys the sanction of society are

    today wide-ranging and we could quite credibly argue, that the

    2 Michel Foucault, Discipline and Punish, The birth of the prison, London

    1979, p 52.

  • 7/28/2019 Crime and Punishment in Liberal Democratic Doctrine

    4/14

    tolerance for inflicting death as a matter of social and political

    necessity, is on the increase.

    To put this in some perspective, let us refer to the executions that

    happen not just under the due processes of the law, but in what could

    be called the penumbra of the law. These are actions that haveacquired a special status within the popular vocabulary, as

    encounters carried out by officials of the state without the formal

    sanction of the law, but with an assurance thatpost facto legitimacy

    will be granted. Coincidentally, we had just a few days back, the

    release of the report on India by the U.N. Special Rapporteur on

    Extrajudicial, Summary or Arbitrary Executions. It reminds us that

    certain grim figures we should really have been more attentive to,

    have for long been in the public domain, without eliciting the kind

    of critical social response they called for. India has the dubious

    distinction as a country, of adding the term encounters and fake

    encounters into the international discourse on human rights. And ina period of fifteen years since 1993, we have had 2,560 deaths

    arising from encounters with the police. Of this number, almost half,

    i.e., 1,224 cases were established by the National Human Rights

    Commission (NHRC),3 a conformist body which does not step out of line

    of the official narrative unless the evidence is really compelling,

    as fake.

    There is a problem of consistency between various definitions. The

    National Crime Records Bureau (NCRB) has its own system of

    classification, in which we are given a rather different estimation

    of crimes involving uniformed officers of the State. It is notimmediately apparent if the definitions employed by the NCRB match

    those used by the NHRC. The lessons that the NCRB statistics impart

    though, are very clear: of all the complaints lodged against the

    coercive arm of the State, i.e., the police in any given year, well

    over half are dismissed on sight as unsustainable or spurious. Of the

    rest, well over 90 percent go before internal mechanisms of

    accountability. Fewer than 5 percent of cases are referred to

    magisterial or judicial procedures. And the susceptibility of

    magistrates and judicial officers at the lower rung to the sheer

    coercive power deployed by agencies of the executive such as the

    police is another real world factor that we have to bring intothis calculation.

    Clearly, there is a violation of the fundamental principle of fair

    legal process here: that no person can be judge in his own case. The

    consequence is a situation of absolute impunity in the matter of

    extra-judicial killings. It is only the very rare case, such as the

    recent killings of Sohrabuddin Sheikh and Ishrat Jahan, where the

    armour of impunity is breached. There are occasional expressions,

    3

    U.N. Human Rights Council, Twenty-third session, Agenda Item Three,Addendum, Report of the Special Rapporteur on Extrajudicial, Summary or

    Arbitrary Executions, Christoph Heyns Mission to India, April 26, 2013.

  • 7/28/2019 Crime and Punishment in Liberal Democratic Doctrine

    5/14

    somewhat more generalised, of dissent, as with the Supreme Court

    recently deprecating the State killing its own people, in the context

    of the encounters in Manipur state that have become the subject of a

    judicially mandated inquiry.4 The substantive impact of this manner

    of intervention is however, far from being clear. It may be premature

    to say that there is broad popular consent for the impunity that theapparatus of the law enjoys. But it certainly is true, that there is

    yet no organised or clearly articulated dissent. Where indeed, there

    is, it gains little voice or traction since the forces enforcing

    silence are far more powerful.

    So here is a situation of officers of the State enforcing violence

    not through the processes of the law, but with the assurance ofpost

    facto sanction, underwritten by the consent manufactured or

    otherwise is a question we should separately address -- of civil

    society. There is yet a third category of sanctioned violence that

    has been common in India. And this is a virulence that originateswithin civil society and runs its course with the tacit connivance of

    the State. The State is in modern political doctrine, the agency with

    a monopoly of legitimate violence, but there are situations in which

    it is prepared to yield this mantle of legitimacy to certain actors

    within civil society, on the strength of a largely unstated compact.

    Thus we have had episodes of mass violence virtually from the very

    beginning of Indias career as a sovereign republic. They have been

    classified under the scholarly and bureaucratic rubrics in various

    ways: communal violence and caste atrocities being the two main

    categories. But certain key characteristics are shared: a generalised

    failure of the State apparatus to contain the violence, impunity forthe perpetrators and little redress for the victims.

    Still another category of violence would be that which occurs

    securely within the domain of the family and the clan. The formal

    system of the law is explicitly in disapproval of this pattern of

    violence but has little ability or will to intervene or provide

    redress. In recognition of this incapacity, there are several who

    argue that the formal apparatus of the State should stay out of this

    domain and allow customary institutions and practices to prevail.

    This often has malign effects on even the formal guarantee of

    equality that the State holds out. We have had lawyers who joined inthe defence of widow immolation in Rajasthan becoming legal

    luminaries and in one case, a judge of the High Court.5 We have a

    4 This observation of the Supreme Court is mentioned in the report of the

    U.N. Special Rapporteur, cited in footnote 3.5In 2004, a lawyer who had joined an agitation in 1987 within Rajasthans

    Rajput community to permit a ritual observance glorifying the practice of

    widow immolation or sati, soon after a young woman from the state had

    reportedly burnt herself on her deceased husbands funeral pyre, was

    appointed to the High Court. This was despite a sustained agitation by

    womens rights groups and other civil rights advocacy organisations. See

    Sanghamitra Chakraborty, The Devis Advocate, Outlook, September 27,2004, extracted May 28 2013 at:

    http://www.outlookindia.com/article.aspx?225259 .

    http://www.outlookindia.com/article.aspx?225259http://www.outlookindia.com/article.aspx?225259
  • 7/28/2019 Crime and Punishment in Liberal Democratic Doctrine

    6/14

    Member of Parliament from the ruling party arguing that the

    institutions of caste such as the khap panchayat should be given

    their due recognition as instrumentalities of justice delivery where

    the law fails to reach.6

    Going beyond these categories now and moving to a different plane,how do we place these different modes in which violence occurs,

    within a broader conceptualisation of crime and punishment in a

    liberal democratic order? Since we are dealing with the death penalty

    which is the surviving relic of an older order, how do we see the

    persistence of this despotic instrument within what we imagine is an

    enlightened liberal dispensation? The story is obviously a

    complicated one but I have tried to simplify it here. My argument

    here is simply that in the transition from despotism to liberalism,

    certain exceptions were always considered warranted and necessary, so

    that the full charter of rights would not be applied universally.

    There were certain requirements that every aspirant had to fulfilbefore he gained entry into the liberal order. And those who failed

    to meet these requirements would suffer abridgments of their rights,

    of varying degrees of severity. These could cover the entire

    spectrum: from a denial of sovereignty or any opportunity to dispose

    of bodily skills and mental faculties in a manner of his or her

    choice, to an explicit denial of liberty and finally the denial of

    the right to life itself.

    I will consider the liberal philosophers from the formative years of

    modern western democracy here, since doctrinal conflicts and dilemmas

    are most sharply reflected during conjunctures of change. Once theforces of transformation have run their course and society has

    settled into a calm and consensual mode of functioning, philosophical

    thinking tends to lapse into conformism.

    Hobbes and Locke are two figures of special relevance here. Writing

    during the English civil war, Hobbes posited a model that saw man as

    6 Naveen Jindal a Member of Parliament representing the Congress party in

    Haryana and a former Chief Minister of Haryana, Om Prakash Chautala,

    recently made common cause arguing that the khap panchayat deserved a fair

    hearing in matters of enforcing marital law. The khap panchayats alacrityin enforcing honour killings on individuals who married outside their

    caste or within the same gotra a supposedly primeval but most likely

    socially constructed family lineage was at the time earning it much

    public opprobrium. But Jindal praised the institution for its role in

    administering society before the formal systems of law were instituted and

    urged that its demands for a legal ban on the forms of marriage deemed

    taboo, should be considered in all seriousness. See: Navin Jindal supports

    khap panchayat, The Hindu, May 10, 2010 (National News), extracted May 28,

    2013 at:http://www.hindu.com/2010/05/10/stories/2010051061441000.htm . In

    the case of Chautala, the support he extended to the khap panchayat was

    read as a way of entrenching his support among the Jat community. See

    Chautala backs khap marriage idea, The Indian Express, October 11, 2012

    (dateline Chandigarh), extracted May 28, 2013 at:http://www.indianexpress.com/news/chautala-backs-khap-marriage-age-

    idea/1015113/.

    http://www.hindu.com/2010/05/10/stories/2010051061441000.htmhttp://www.hindu.com/2010/05/10/stories/2010051061441000.htmhttp://www.indianexpress.com/news/chautala-backs-khap-marriage-age-idea/1015113/http://www.indianexpress.com/news/chautala-backs-khap-marriage-age-idea/1015113/http://www.indianexpress.com/news/chautala-backs-khap-marriage-age-idea/1015113/http://www.indianexpress.com/news/chautala-backs-khap-marriage-age-idea/1015113/http://www.hindu.com/2010/05/10/stories/2010051061441000.htm
  • 7/28/2019 Crime and Punishment in Liberal Democratic Doctrine

    7/14

    inherently acquisitive, driven into continual conflict with fellow

    man and requiring the strong hand of a sovereign to render him fit

    for an existence within society.7 All rights in other words,

    principal among these being the right to property, or the ability to

    determine what is mine, thine and his, rested with the sovereign

    and could be allocated among subjects in a manner of his choice. Thiswould seem to put Hobbes outside the liberal spectrum, casting him

    almost as an apologist for royal despotism. Yet, as the political

    theorist and philosopher C.B. MacPherson has shown, Hobbes is among

    the first to clearly enunciate the foundational principles of

    liberal-democratic philosophy. He drew on contempory conceptual

    breakthroughs by Galileo in the physical domain, which posited

    continual motion rather than a state of rest, as the basic state of

    nature. In course of his perpetual movement, man enters into

    collision with others of his species, his instinct for acquisition

    creating the grounds for conflict with his fellows, leading to a war

    of all against all in which life for all would be nasty, brutishand short. There was in other words, no alternative but to have a

    strong sovereign power an artificial man as Hobbes puts it

    which would stand above this state of unending war by imposing a law

    and ensuring that the norms of property (or propriety in Hobbes

    language) were duly respected.

    For those who failed to honour the law he laid down, the sovereign

    would reserve various kinds of punishments. A crime committed against

    an individual subject would attract one variety of punitive sanction,

    one committed against an official enforcing the sovereign will, quite

    another. In the former case, the harm was confined to one person,while in the latter, the damage extends it selfe (sic) to all.

    Anything that involved material damage to the sovereigns interests,

    such as the betraying of the strengths, or revealing of the secrets

    of the king to an enemy would be deemed a crime. So too would

    anything that tended to diminish the Authority of the same, either

    in the present time, or in succession.

    Stripped of its seventeenth-century idiom, Hobbes is clearly speaking

    here of the modern penal provisions of obstructing or in some way

    harming an officer of the law in the performance of his duties, and

    of treason and sedition. All of these are actions which involve achallenge to the majesty of the sovereign and would be categorised in

    modern legal parlance, as crimes against the State.

    Punitive sanctions in turn could take several forms: pecuniary,

    corporal and capital. Each has its specific place within the

    architecture of power. And capital punishment here is the Infliction

    of Death; and that either simply, or with torment. Though the

    ultimate purpose was to rid society of one who refused to live by its

    rules, the manner in which death was inflicted had its own didactic

    7C.B. MacPhersons introduction to a Penguin edition of Hobbes Leviathan,

    London, 1968.

  • 7/28/2019 Crime and Punishment in Liberal Democratic Doctrine

    8/14

    purpose. The preceding period of torment, when the convicted man was

    expected to make a public confession of his crimes, served the

    purpose of deterring any who might seek to follow in his path. It may

    be added here, that though torment has today been eliminated from

    the modes of inflicting death at least in terms of the formal law -

    - society still retains a sharp interest in the words and demeanourof a convict at the moment of his execution, as final validation of

    its power to extinguish life.

    A half-century or so after Hobbes, Locke observed a rather more

    placid state of affairs, with England in the rosy flush of the Stuart

    Restoration. He had in consequence, a much happier view. Man, said

    Locke, is inherently in harmony with society. Those who seemingly

    fail to get a fair deal out of bourgeois-liberal rules, must

    necessarily have invited that fate upon themselves by some act so

    much at variance with accepted norms of conduct, that death was the

    deserved punishment. Once reprieved by societys magnanimity, thedelinquent elements were obliged to repay the debt incurred by

    putting themselves, in body and soul, at the disposal of the wronged

    persons.8

    Locke was simply put, a firm and faithful adherent to the dogma of

    the original sin, which saw all social inequities as the

    consequence of some primeval act of transgress. The world was created

    in all perfection by divine ordainment. But there were regrettably,

    among the denizens of this perfect world, many who were unable to

    live by the indispensable rules that would ensure peace and

    tranquillity. Those guilty of contravening the rules handed down by abenevolent creator, would be spared a deserved retribution, only if

    they were to resign themselves to a lesser charter of rights.

    Every person was otherwise sovereign over his body, his labour and

    his faculties: every man has a property in his own person: this no

    body has any right to but himself. The labour of his body, and the

    work of his hands, we may say, are properly his. Whatsoever then he

    removes out of the state that nature hath provided, and left it in,

    he hath mixed his labour with, and joined to it something that is his

    own, and thereby makes it his property. It being by him removed from

    the common state nature hath placed it in, it hath by this laboursomething annexed to it, that excludes the common right of other

    men... Thus the grass my horse has bit; the turfs my servant has cut;

    and the ore I have digged in any place, where I have a right to them

    in common with others, become my property, without the assignation or

    consent of any body.

    From being a circumstance requiring a special justification,

    inequality and a forfeiture of rights over bodily capacities and

    8

    John Locke, An Essay on Government, available in numerous editions,including in e-books. The key sections here would be between paragraph 1

    and 50.

  • 7/28/2019 Crime and Punishment in Liberal Democratic Doctrine

    9/14

    faculties the turfs my servant has cut become an integral

    element within the liberal-democratic framework as conceived by

    Locke.

    Three varieties of power are in play in sustaining this state of

    liberal-democratic harmony: the parental, political and despotic.Parental power is something that all of tender years put themselves

    under with the sanction of society. It is what is today called the

    primary socialisation process, which equips them to deal with the

    world outside as they grow to mature years. And once of sufficient

    maturity to take part in public affairs, each individual who is

    sovereign in himself and enjoys full power to dispose of his person

    and faculties in any manner he thinks fit nevertheless sees a

    pragmatic purpose in delegating the authority to enforce this state

    of perfect concord, to a politically constituted entity or civil

    government.

    It is however, the third form of power in Lockes framework that is

    key here. Despotic power for him, is an absolute, arbitrary power

    one man has over another, to take away his life, whenever he pleases.

    This is a power, which neither nature gives, for it has made no such

    distinction between one man and another; nor compact can convey: for

    man not having such an arbitrary power over his own life, cannot give

    another man such a power over it.Despotic power rather, is the

    effect only of forfeiture, which the aggressor makes of his own life,

    when he puts himself into the state of war with another... for having

    quitted reason, which God hath given to be the rule betwixt man and

    man, and the common bond whereby human kind is united into onefellowship and society; and having renounced the way of peace which

    that teaches, ... he renders himself liable to be destroyed by the

    injured person, and the rest of mankind, that will join with him in

    the execution of justice, as any other wild beast, or noxious brute,

    with whom mankind can have neither society nor security.9

    Despotic power in other words, is invoked in a state of war, when

    society is forced to take up arms against elements within which

    threaten its internal harmony. And once despotic power is called into

    play, the common human decencies cease, since the target of social

    wrath is one who has forfeited all rights. It could be added here,that the Supreme Court of India has frequently in its rulings on the

    death penalty, echoed this sentiment of the brutish or beastly

    man being a menace to society. In the case of Kuljeet Singh (better

    known as the Billa and Ranga case), the court held that the survival

    of an orderly society demands the extinction of the life of persons

    like Ranga and Billa who are a menace to social order and security.

    And in the case of Ram Deo Chauhan, the court took the argument on

    the protection of society to what has been described as a new low,

    9 Ibid, section 172.

  • 7/28/2019 Crime and Punishment in Liberal Democratic Doctrine

    10/14

    by ruling that when a man becomes a beast and menace to the society,

    he can be deprived of his life.10

    Moving on in the evolution of the liberal-democratic doctrine

    to Immanuel Kant, we see the principle of man in conflict with

    society being elevated to little less than the principalmotive force, the mainspring, of human progress. For Kant, the

    antagonism of men in society was nothing less than the means

    that nature had itself decreed to accomplish the

    development of all (human) faculties. Ends that individual

    human beings would care little for if they knew about it are

    promoted by each pursuing his own ends according to his

    inclination and often one against another (and even one entire

    people against another). Given these inherent qualities of

    the individual and the human species, Kant saw the supreme

    test (that) nature has set for mankind as the evolution of a

    perfectly just civil constitution. Such a regime of lawalone could ensure the development of all faculties of man by

    his own effort. The greatest degree of freedom should be

    assured under the law, so that there is a very general

    antagonism of (a societys) members. But there should also be

    concurrently, a precise determination and enforcement of the

    limit of this freedom.11

    How does harmony emerge by some miracle, from the collisions

    of infinitesimal individuals who share nothing except the

    instinct for acquisition and a tendency to allow their egos to

    take over their existence? In his Critique of PracticalReason, Kant was to return to this issue, proposing among his

    most crucial axioms, that the human will should freely

    submit itself to the law. In this sense of free submission

    lay the preservation of individual liberty. Every individual,

    under the reign of reason, would be enjoined to act as though

    the exercise of his will could always at the same time hold

    good as a principle of universal legislation.12

    Kant was not of course a theorist of civil society in the manner that

    Hegel was. But his notion of a settled and agreed pattern of social

    practice that would conform with civilised norms, independent of theState and the coercive power it holds in reserve, is as clear a

    construct of civil society as can be found in the thicket of

    conceptual confusion that has sprouted around the term.

    Three principles are essential to the constitution of the civic

    state in Kants judgment: 1. The freedom of each member of society

    10 Both quotations from Lethal Lottery, as cited in footnote 1, pages 75

    and 87.11Immanuel Kant, Idea for a Universal History with Cosmopolitan Intent,

    in Allen W. Wood (editor), Basic Writings of Kant, New York, 2001, p 119.12Kant, Critique of Practical Reason, in Allen W. Wood (editor), op.

    cit., p 238.

  • 7/28/2019 Crime and Punishment in Liberal Democratic Doctrine

    11/14

    as a man; 2. The equalityof each member with every other as a

    subject; 3. The autonomy of each member of a commonwealth as a

    citizen.13 There was though, one condition that every person had to

    satisfy to qualify for all the rights available to a citizen. And

    these lines from Kant encapsulate the central dilemma of the liberal

    doctrine so well, that they need quotation at some length: Therequisite quality for (citizenship), apart from the natural one that

    the person not be a child or a woman (sic), is only this: that such a

    person be his own masterand hence that he have some property (under

    which we may include any art, craft, or science) that would provide

    him with sustenance. To put this another way, he must be a man who,

    when he must earn a livelihood from others, acquires property only by

    selling what is his own and not by conceding to others the right to

    make use of his strength.14

    Clearly then, the man who has no sovereignty over his person, over

    the manner in which his bodily strengths and mental faculties aredeployed, does not merit the rights of citizenship. It is a dilemma

    of liberal-democratic theory that persists to this day, one that

    detracts seriously from its claim to being a doctrine of equality.

    Let me quickly wind up this excursus into the history of ideas with a

    consideration of Immanuel Kants great contemporary Adam Smith. Now

    remembered as the founder of the modern discipline of economics,

    Smith was also a moral theorist profoundly concerned with the law and

    justice. Though he shared much in Kants worldview, in seeing the

    unfettered exercise of the human will as the best guarantee of

    progress, he saw a quite distinct process of mitigating the conflictpotential inherent in this situation. He considers the emotion of

    sympathy, in this respect: an emotion that every person is

    susceptible to, though one difficult to intuit since it goes beyond

    the senses and common faculties. The illustration Smith used was of a

    witness to torture. A person who sees a near and dear one upon the

    rack, he argued, would have no way of knowing through his senses and

    faculties, of his true suffering. But the sight nevertheless stirs up

    deep emotional turmoil. Sympathy, says Smith, once referred to the

    emotions of pity and remorse, but could more accurately be

    characterised as one mans sharing in the emotions whether merited

    or not of another.

    This was, said Smith, an illogical sentiment if any, which could be

    ascribed solely to the generalised dread of death that all humanity

    suffered. The emotion of sympathy arose from the sense of mortality

    that all humanity was condemned to live under, an emotion that indeed

    was one of the most important principles in human nature. Indeed,

    the fear of death made every individual intimately aware of the

    limits to which he could challenge or push back against the norms

    13

    Kant, Concerning the Common Saying: This May be True in Theory but Doesnot Apply to Practice, in Allen W. Wood (editor), op. cit., p 420.14 Ibid, p 424, emphases in original.

  • 7/28/2019 Crime and Punishment in Liberal Democratic Doctrine

    12/14

    imposed by society. This singular trait in human nature was

    responsible for the sense of discrimination that every individual

    possessed between justice and its opposite.

    The sense of Smiths remarks is clear. All life is finite and worth

    treasuring. But one who pushes too hard against social norms risksforfeiting his right to live. He will be dealt with either in

    accordance with societys powers of sanction -- if necessary through

    capital punishment -- or else through lesser devices. Though never

    quite convinced of the moral basis by which a society could deprive

    an individual of his life, Smith was prepared to put up with it as a

    necessary evil. The fear of death, he argued, was the great poison

    to the happiness, but the great restraint upon the injustice of

    mankind; which, while it afflicts and mortifies the individual,

    guards and protects the society.15 In contrast to Kant, who saw an

    exalted and rather reified notion of Reason as the ultimate arbiter

    in a society that would otherwise be torn apart by the competitiveinstincts of its members, Smith saw a kinder, gentler attribute of

    sympathy serving that function.

    The key issues here could be summed up in a few lines. The liberal-

    democratic order is built on a model of competitive man, which in

    turn is an acknowledgment that conflict is inherent in society.

    Conflict is contained by enacting a civil constitution that enshrines

    equality as a value without holding out any form of assurance of

    substantive equality. Individuals without sovereignty over their

    persons and their faculties would not be entitled to the full rights

    of citizenship. But as a pragmatic decision, they could be grantedformal rights since a benevolent State could conceivably create the

    conditions under which they could lift themselves out of deprivation

    into a state of genuine equality. All who choose to dishonour or defy

    the compact under which liberal-democratic society is established,

    forfeit the right to the protection of its laws. The right to life

    becomes in extreme cases, an indefensible entitlement for these

    recalcitrant elements.

    Let us turn now again to the situation in India and the manner in

    which the death penalty has been preserved as an element of the law

    and implemented over the years. This is only to consider it in itspolitical context, not in terms of the extensive jurisprudence that

    has come up around the theme. Two of the moral preceptors of Indian

    independence Gandhi and Ambedkar both expressed themselves not

    just once, but at several critical junctures, against the retention

    of capital punishment.16 And this was against the background of the

    Karachi session of the All India Congress Committee in 1931, the

    15 Adam Smith, The Theory of Moral Sentiments, New York, 2000, pp 3-9.16 It should be added here that at the time that the Indian Constitution

    was written and adopted, Ambedkar was certainly not recognised as a moral

    preceptor. That status came to him later, after roughly four decades ofIndias existence as a sovereign republic. He was however, acknowledged to

    be a person of great legal expertise and wisdom.

  • 7/28/2019 Crime and Punishment in Liberal Democratic Doctrine

    13/14

    first formal attempt at laying down a constitutional framework for

    Indian independence, making it an explicit commitment to do away with

    capital punishment.

    Yet, at the decisive moment, when the republican constitution was

    actually enacted, the death penalty remained on the statute. Whatexplains this seeming anomaly? The question prompts a reevaluation of

    some of the mythologies of our nationhood and a sober assessment of

    the pathway that brought us to independence and the strategies that

    have since been deployed in sustaining national unity. Paul Brass for

    instance, has said that the Indian constitution was born not in the

    abundance of hope and unbound ambitions, as we would like to believe,

    but in fear and trepidation. There were, on Brasss reading,

    several factors that contributed to the unsettled national mood at

    independence, notably the partition, the war in Kashmir, the near-

    insurrectionary conditions in Hyderabad state, and memories of the

    acute food crisis of the war years. The fear of disorder was alooming presence all through the Constituent Assembly debates and it

    led to a number of qualifications being inscribed into the

    Constitution on the fundamental rights of free speech and

    association. The numerous emergency powers conferred on the Central

    Government under the Constitution were, Brass argues, a direct

    outcome of this sense of trepidation.17 So too, we may add, was the

    retention of the death penalty.

    This fear of disorder led to a number of practical concessions being

    made to older power cliques whose sustenance otherwise would be in

    flat-out contradiction to basic republican values. There were alsosections that by virtue of the partition and the circumstances of the

    national unification that followed, were seen to be in forfeit on the

    rights that all others were guaranteed. These foundational

    characteristics of the Indian nation have created their own terrains

    of violence, a violence that is exercised within civil society, often

    with the active connivance of the State. They also determine to a

    great extent how the State exercises its right to violence: both the

    legitimate kind and in that other, more shadowy form in which

    legitimacy is conferred after the fact. In recent years and

    especially since the Indian elite began discovering in the battle

    against terrorism, an identity of interests with the western powersthat had earlier been elusive, that has become another rubric under

    which rights can be denied and even the due process of law made

    superfluous. That was the essence of two recent rulings by the

    Supreme Court, in one of which it upheld a death sentence despite the

    passage of endless years since it was imposed which in its more

    enlightened jurisprudence the court had likened to cruel and inhuman

    treatment on the grounds that the convict had been guilty of a

    crime of terrorism. Another convict who made a case on the same

    grounds for the commutation of his death sentence, was granted a

    17Paul Brass, The Strong State and the Fear of Disorder, in Francine

    Frankel (editor) Transforming India, Oxford, 2000.

  • 7/28/2019 Crime and Punishment in Liberal Democratic Doctrine

    14/14

    reprieve because he had been sentenced for a lesser crime than

    terrorism. In a context in which one of the aspirants for the Prime

    Ministership of the country is on record saying all Muslims are not

    terrorists, but all terrorists are Muslims, this fairly explicit

    exception to the guarantees of fundamental rights and lawful process,

    holds grim forebodings for the future of democracy in India.