CP Lecture

download CP Lecture

of 4

Transcript of CP Lecture

  • 8/14/2019 CP Lecture

    1/4

    Crime and Punishment

    A Lecture

    Russell McNeil

    Crime and Punishment illustrates an important idea. The idea is that "reason," that grand anduniquely human power, is limited in reach and scope. Social critic Friedrich August von Hayek

    commented once that, ". it may be that the most difficult task for human reason is to comprehend its ownlimitations. It is essential for the growth of reason that as individuals we should bow to forces and obey

    principles we cannot hopefully to understand, yet on which the advance and even the preservation of

    civilization may depend." Such limitations imply that on life's most important questions - particularly those

    of a moral or ethical nature -- reason alone can produce chilling consequences. Without adequate or any

    moral illumination, reason alone, when pushed to its limits, can produce consequences which stand

    dramatically opposed to those moral demands. Dostoevsky's narrative is directed as a specific critique ofRussian manifestations of purely rational political theories current in the 1860's in his homeland. But the

    challenge he poses has meaning for us at the end of the 20th century.

    Dostoevsky's parable focuses on a particular brand of 19th century Russian ideology, as it

    begins to crystallize in the mind of a young idealist. But the modeling procedure Dostoevsky uses in

    teasing out the contradictions of Raskolnikov's unguided application of a morally bankrupt theory, could

    equally well be applied to contemporary thinking around several important and equally bankrupt modern

    ideas - ideas harshly criticized by thinkers such as Hayek.

    Without direction - the source of which is ultimately beyond rational understanding - in thedomain of the meta-rational -- reason-as-reason will, sooner or later, run aground. Directed reason on the

    other hand provides an orientation - an orientation that gives purpose and direction to inquiry -- by allowingus to select from an infinite range of possibilities the right path - the "right" reason. Problems emerged for

    Raskolnikov then, and for us now when we deny the need to recognize, acknowledge and bow to

    external guidance. The rational and the meta-rational must operate symbiotically: one pointing the way, the

    other uncovering the Truth.

    Raskolnikov rationalized murder. We are appalled. Why? Each of us will attempt to answer in a

    different way. Fundamentally though I think that most of our answers boil down to the same idea. We are

    appalled because it wasn't the right thing to do.

    We know that - Raskolnikov himself eventually came to know that too. But the reason his crimewasn't right had nothing to do with Raskolnikov's rational theories. Political theories, scientific theories,

    medical theories, anthropological theories, psychological theories, as theories are nothing more than

    intricate exercises in calculus. They apply a coherent set of rules to the objects they reference. Likearithmetic or calculus this involves plugging in values, applying the rules, and observing the consequences.

    Theories as calculus have no moral content. Whatever moral framework we as humans use to regulate the

    operation of theories comes from a domain outside of the calculus. This all seems so obvious.

    But is it? Our century seems a poor test case for the symbiotic and morally illuminated

    application of theory. Global wars, genocide, environmental decay, and massive economic disparity are buta few examples of theories running aground in our century. We seem no better that our ancestors.

    We may be worse off. Not just because the consequences of unguided applications of reason are

    more far reaching now - global population is large and our technologies powerful. We may be worse off

    now because of the emergence of theories that not only deny the importance of a symbiotic relationship

    between the rational and meta-rational, they deny the meta-rational altogether. These theories enable their

    practitioners - like Raskolnikov tries to do in our story - to cross over the barriers erected by traditional

    morality, by denying the barriers. They are not meta-rational to Raskolnikov; they are irrational. Hence

    they are destructible. In crossing those barriers Raskolnikov is in a position to act outside the constraints ofgood and evil.

    Such theories (i.e. those of Raskolnikov) - unlike most ideas we draw on to shape our lives andgive meaning to our existence - actively close off and deny mystery.

    This is not true for physics or biology or political science generally. None of those systems

    make explicit moral demands as such - but nothing in those sciences as traditionally articulated expects

    their practitioners to be blind to the moral universe.

    I'd like to offer three contemporary examples. While each of these streams offers differing

    approaches, they are similar in this respect to the specific form of pure rationality Dostoevsky warns about:

  • 8/14/2019 CP Lecture

    2/4

    none of these systems are open to, make reference to, or are guided in any meaningful way by reference to

    externals. Universes onto themselves these systems attempt to capture the universe and make it their own.

    The first of these ideas is called historicism. An underpinning principle of the approach is that

    "Truth" with a capital "T" or "Truths" have no enduring meanings in human cultures In fact, the claim is

    that all historical ideas and arguments and moralities are relative only to the times in which they weredeveloped. No amount of dissection, interpretation or critical analysis of the past can provide us with

    anything other than a measure of Truths as they once were. There may be nothing rationally wrong withsuch a claim.

    If we deny the main claim of historicism and accept a priori that truth does endure we must

    draw on a belief which really can not be established rationally. To believe that Truths are intelligible and

    invariant is to believe something about the universe we can not establish with certainty - except as a kind of

    faith.

    A second modern purely rational stream is represented by an approach from within the positivesciences. It's called "scientism." Not all scientists think this way. In fact scientism isn't particularly

    scientific - it is more an attitude toward the positives sciences held by some both in and out of the sciences.

    The basic contention - and it may account for the disdain many of us have for modern science - is that the

    only knowledge in the would that has any validity is knowledge derived from the positive sciences.

    Scientism as scientism would claim that all ethical, moral, aesthetic, or metaphysical statements are

    meaningless. The only real meaning is that which can be attached to technical feasibility. If something is

    technically possible - it is morally admissible. We don't need Dostoevsky to respond here - Mary Shelley

    has already done so. What's wrong with building a monster, detonating a hydrogen bomb or cloning a BillClinton? Nothing - from the perspective of this purely rational approach.

    A third example arises from a position that argues that moral decisions should only be based onpragmatic considerations and that practical concerns should always prevail over theory or ethics. From a

    purely rational point of view - if we deny the universality or existence of external forces, we are rationally

    bound to follow such a course. In fact, the very word "rationalize" has come to imply the kinds of

    consequences flowing from this sort of reasoning. If you think about it, pragmatism - in this guise - taken to

    extremes can be used to rationalize just about any action any one or any nation has ever taken.

    The rational ideologies that were capturing the imaginations of the Russian intelligentsia in the

    1860's were a blend of ideas influenced by an intermingling of the currents of English Utilitarianism (Mill),

    Utopian Socialism (Marx and others), and Social Darwinism: all of these are reflected in some way in thecharacter of Raskolnikov. For example, Raskolnikov's notion that superior individuals had the right to act

    independently for the welfare of humanity reflects an influence of Social Darwinism. But Dostoevsky's

    main target seems to have been what has come to be known as Russian Nihilism - a rather negative doctrinewhich found nothing to approve in the established order of anything: morality, religion or politics.

    Joseph Frank who writes on this in the commentaries at the back of the Norton text. He argues

    that Raskolnikov's crime is planned on the basis of a rational Utilitarian calculus. Raskolnikov believes that

    his reason can overcome the most deeply rooted human feelings. Ordinary criminals, according to

    Raskolnikov's theories, are motivated by greed or viciousness. They break down when they do their deedsleaving all sorts of clues about, because inwardly they understand the justice of the laws they are

    transgressing. Conscience - which is outside rational framework - and after all a product of an irrational

    belief - interferes with such purely rational actions.

    For Raskolnikov this crime was not really a crime. His reason had persuaded him that the harm

    - he accepts some harm - would be far outweighed by the good. That's the calculus. Raskolnikov had to

    show that he was indeed up to the task. This conscience thing had to be overcome. Conscience - which is a

    product of some mythological conditioning in Raskolnikov's mind -- could not be allowed to distort his

    reason.Dostoevsky's procedure was to take such an ideological theory and show how -- when pushed to

    extremes - it would generate distasteful contradictions. The contradictions that emerge are in the form of aclash between Christian values - love, altruism, sympathy - and the amorality of his ideology.

    Of course in the novel Raskolnikov is not successful. Under the influence of the meek and

    illiterate Sonya - an embodiment of wisdom of the meta-rational kind - Raskolnikov's project eventually

    falters - or seems to. What did the defeat mean? Has Dostoevsky demonstrated the necessity of a symbiosis

    between the rational and mystery (or the meta-rational)?

    Let's examine the problem.

  • 8/14/2019 CP Lecture

    3/4

    My starting point works like this. I freely acknowledge that these meta-rational forces are not

    subject to rational analyses. But, when I ask myself this question: Can Truth present itself to me via a meta-

    rational path? I cannot say no. I can't say no because my reason alone can not negate the transcendental.

    Reasoning - as I understand reasoning - can not rule out the possibility that there are regions where

    conventional human reasoning is inoperative.The best way I understand to express this is to say that it is not irrational be receptive to

    mystery. This in no way proves the meta-rational - it simply declares that openness to mystery is notforbidden.

    In Christian discourse the label attached to this act of receptivity to mystery or meta-rational

    knowledge is called Faith. Enormous tensions emerge when rational reason - in Raskolnikov - encounters

    Faith - in Sonya. For Raskolnikov life is a calculus. Sonya knows but cannot express rationally why that

    cannot be so. She says simply that, "God has to be. "

    In Christian terms Faith provides the illuminating knowledge which guides reason. Thatknowledge - for Christians - as claimed in the gospels - is that Jesus Christ is, "the way, the Truth, and the

    Life." But this "knowledge" is offered, in the gospels, not as a rational argument, but as a revelation -

    provided by God as a free gift to anyone who is disposed to receive the gift.

    That knowledge provided through Faith is represented as fundamentally different from rational

    knowledge because it is experiential and interpersonal. It is analogous to the knowledge that we

    "experience" of "love" or "friendship" when we enter into human relationships. Loving relationships

    generate awareness and sensibility purely rational analyses of such relationships can never adequately

    explain. These mysterious understandings emerge when we surrender to the idea of love. Plato alludes tothis sort of thing in a pre-Christian context in the Republic and the Symposium when he references the

    domain beyond the divided line. In the Christian context, this openness to Faith requires that we divestourselves of arrogance, egoism and pride. That of course is a painful thing to do. Any such surrender is

    painful and humiliating. We must symbolically fall down, kiss the earth and accept the inevitable suffering

    - as Sonya urges Raskolnikov to do:

    "Go at once, this instant, stand at the crossroads, first bow down and kiss the earth you have

    desecrated, then bow to the whole world, to the four corners of the earth, and say aloud to the world: `I

    have done murder.'"

    And that Raskolnikov does seem to do - albeit half-heartedly: "He knelt in the middle of the

    square, bowed to the ground, and kissed its filth with pleasure and joy. He raised himself and then bowed asecond time.[but] . stilled the words `I am a murderer'."

    The importance of grounding certainties derived from meta-rational sources which then serve as

    references for philosophic inquiry is not confined to Christianity.Divested of the labels of religious terms, all Truth seeking can be seen as driven at its deepest

    level by what can best be described as a sense of "wonder." That wonder itself may be seen as powered by

    a rationally unconfirmed and unconfirmable "belief" that the search itself is meaningful - that there is some

    purpose for the search, and that although the goal may be only dimly perceived - there is a goal and that the

    goal is enduring. This "wonder driven" impulse can itself be understood as the external reference necessaryfor any meaningful inquiry. Wonder is a kind of faith.

    This notion that there are unverifiable universal principles that all philosophic systems share is

    sometimes also called "right reason." The abandonment of the idea of common references shared by all

    philosophies leads invariably to confusions and fragmentation. Each system of thought claims ownership

    of the all. This is sometimes called "philosophic pride."

    Whenever we abandon external reference our inquiries are subject to caprice and their

    achievements judged by pragmatic criteria or empirical data. The neglect of "right reason" leads to

    agnosticism and relativism and skepticism and undifferentiated pluralism. In effect all positions are equallyvalid and everything becomes reduced to "opinion." In his specific critique of Raskolnikov Dostoevsky

    shows how all of the above may emerge when any proudful theory rules our thinking.You might maintain that setting faith aside, trivializing wonder, or dismissing "right reason" is a

    sign of rational maturity - a liberating decision as we free ourselves from the chains of irrational

    mythologies. My only response to that is to offer that it is NOT freedom to decline to be open to the

    transcendental. Faith, wonder or right reason may be seen as the keys that can liberate reason - by enabling

    reason to attain correctly what it seeks.

  • 8/14/2019 CP Lecture

    4/4

    In the Judeo-Christian tradition - the context of external reference in this novel - the first man

    and woman in the allegory of Genesis - - had no need for reason - represented in Genesis by the tree of

    knowledge of good and evil. Human pride caused man to seek unreferenced knowledge. He did not need

    God.

    The Fall meant that from that point forward the path to Truth would become strewn withobstacles - reasoning would become inclined to falsehood. The coming of Christ was the saving event

    which redeemed reason from its weakness - in effect setting reason free. Faith for the Christian became theexternal reference and provided the orientation in the seeking of Truth through reason. Such faith is not

    grounded on rational evidence because it indeed is based on an interpersonal relationship which in some

    way is deemed richer than evidence.

    The Faith/Reason model in Truth seeking abandons the elitism attached to the purely rational

    Russian ideologies Dostoevsky is challenging in the novel. Truth is NOT something accessible only

    to the privileged few.All of the above brings intelligibility to the novel.

    What is the meaning and role of suffering? It is for Raskolnikov the experience of divesting

    himself firstly of his innate connection with external reference - that makes him ill. Redemption causes

    suffering too - Raskolnikov must abandon all he holds dear: that he is a superman, his pride, his arrogance,

    his despotism.

    What lies beneath the unexpected and unbelievably tumultuous psychological struggle

    Raskolnikov experiences? I think Dostoevsky is showing us how difficult it is to abandon the external

    reference: that the demands of conscience are so harsh points to the Truth of the source. The psychologicalstruggle is represented as a real spiritual drama between the protests of conscience and the justifications of

    reason.In the same sense finally, the duality of motive throughout the novel is another manifestation of

    that spiritual drama. Far from being a flaw in the story the conflicting motivations become the devices

    Dostoevsky uses to portray the struggle between a rejected morality that refuses to go away and

    Raskolnikov's rational ideology. Before the crime Raskolnikov in the early tavern scene with Marmeladov

    characterizes his motive in his theory of the altruistic Utilitarian crime.

    But the motive he confides to Sonya in his confession some time after the deed is far from

    altruistic. He admits that he committed the crime solely for himself - that is completely opposite to

    altruism. He killed to show that he was a superior being who - as such - stood outside of moral law -beyond good and evil. He did it to see if he was strong enough to have the right to kill - a kind of egomania.

    So what was it, egomania or altruism? The two motives seem mutually exclusive.

    I take Dostoevsky's warning seriously. Human survival may indeed - as Hayek says - depend onbowing to principles which will remain a mystery. Individual or global refusal to do that is represented in

    the character of Svidrigaylov. For Svidrigaylov good and evil are completely equivalent. Murder or

    generosity are morally neutral. Faced with the meaninglessness of such a life, Svidrigaylov realizes - as we

    might one day - that there is at the end of the day but one option for such a life - annihilation - or, "a trip to

    America."