Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

download Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

of 10

Transcript of Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

  • 8/20/2019 Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

    1/23

    OCR AS Philosophy and Ethics  1 Ancient Greek influences

    This unit looks at four of the traditional arguments for the existence of God. The

    Cosmological, Teleological and Moral Arguments seek to justify belief through things that

    we can experience. The Ontological Argument suggests that God’s existence can be

    demonstrated by reason alone.

    The specific topics covered are:

    • the Ontological Argument of Anselm and Descartes

    • the criticisms of the Ontological Argument by Gaunilo and Kant

    • the Cosmological Argument of Aquinas and Copleston

    • the criticisms of the Cosmological Argument given by Hume and Russell• the Teleological Argument of Aquinas and Paley

    • criticisms of the Teleological Argument given by Hume, Mill and Darwin

    • the Moral Argument of Kant and criticism of Freud.

    The following teacher notes link directly to the OCR specification, the OCR SOW and the

     AS Philosophy and Ethics student book to provide complete support throughout the delivery

    of the specification.

    Links to the CD-ROM resources are provided throughout and worksheets to support the

    activities follow these teacher notes as well as further exam support in the extended Exam

    Caf é.

    Introduction

    A general discussion regarding whether students do or

    do not believe in God and the reasons they may have

    for their beliefs might be a good way into the topic.

    What arguments are they aware of? This discussion

    may or may not be appropriate depending on what has

    been done at GCSE. Some students may be reluctant to

    give their views to the whole class. More impersonal

    questions such as ‘why do you think some people

    do/don’t believe in God?’ may be a good way to draw

    them into discussion without divulging their personal

    views. This is a useful strategy for a number of topics

    where the issue may be sensitive. The four sub-topics

    in this unit can be taught in any order. One approach

    may be to teach the topics alongside the challenges to

    religious belief given in unit 4. The problem of evil

    would follow the Teleological Argument. The issues

    surrounding religion and science could follow either

    the Teleological or Cosmological Argument.

    The Teleological Argument

    (lesson plan page 53, student book pages 52–53

    !tarter 

    A kinaesthetic way into this topic is the jigsaw activity

    given in the scheme of work and lesson plan 1. This

    gives a crude illustration of the difference betweenintelligent action and chance. This could then lead on

    to discussion of the key question: is a complex thing

    like the universe more likely to be the product of

    design or chance? Alternatively, ask students to bring

    in examples of things that nature or humans have

    designed, something that has beauty and so on (see

    lesson plan 1).

    The corresponding lesson plan activity has potential to

    lead to interesting discussions. It is worth trying to draw

    out what the key differences are between the objects and

    why some things can be argued to be the work of God.

    Key points may include the idea that things designed by

    46

    UNIT OVERVIEW

  • 8/20/2019 Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

    2/23

    OCR AS Philosophy and Ethics  1 Ancient Greek influences

    God show evidence of intelligence, they are beautifuland/or they are not caused by human beings.

    "e#elopment and resources

    Once students are clear on the Teleological Argument

    in simple form (the opening paragraph on page 52 of

    the student book is very useful in this respect), the

    arguments of Aquinas and Paley can be considered.

    The texts are available on the CD-ROM (‘Aquinas’

    Five Ways’ and ‘William Paley extracts’), while pages

    52–53 of the student book provide an accessibleintroduction to these thinkers and the activities

    encourage students to summarise the ideas of these

    philosophers in plain English – these activities can be

    used to check understanding.

     Aquinas

    Aquinas’ argument is based on the order and regularity

    that is observed within the universe. In addition to the

    analogy of the arrow on page 52 of the student book,

    another illustration that works quite well is the idea ofa garden. If you look at a garden and see that it is neat,

    plants grow in rows and the grass is tidy, the order and

    regularity of the garden suggests a gardener. Aquinas is

    saying a similar thing about the universe.

     Paley

    Paley’s argument is slightly different and is based on

    the notion that the way objects are put together enables

    them to fulfil a purpose. He gives two examples of this,

    the watch and the human eye, both of which are

    detailed in the student book with accompanying

    activities.

    "ifferentiation

    The student book material on pages 52–53 is accessible

    to all students. There are original (and fuller) extracts

    from Aquinas and Paley available on the CD-ROM

    which will be of interest to higher ability students or

    those who want to do further reading. It is well worth

    students looking at the original text as Paley gives

    several scenarios, such as the watch being broken, and

    argues that there would still be evidence of design.

    This may be useful as students in examinations oftengive the impression that they have only a vague

    knowledge of Paley.

    $lenar%&e'tension

    The student book activities encourage students to write

    out Aquinas’ and Paley’s arguments in plain English,

    and this is a good opportunity to check their

    understanding is correct.

    ume)s criticisms of the

    Teleological Argument

    (student book pages 5*–55

    !tarter 

    Explain to students that the easiest way for them to

    understand Hume is through his empiricism: he only

    believes what his senses tell him, hence he is sceptical

    about all supernatural statements. Students could read

    the introductory text on page 54 of the student book

    and respond to the quotation from ‘Dialogues

    Concerning Natural Religion’.

    "e#elopment and resources

    The student book (pages 54–55) goes into some detail

    regarding Hume’s criticism of the Teleological

    Argument and the weaknesses he sees in it. The

    accompanying activities are designed to draw out

    students’ understanding. The ‘For debate’ and

    ‘cabbage’ activities should prove engaging to all

    abilities. This is further complemented by worksheet

    3.1, which summarises Hume’s criticisms and asks

    students to evaluate them. The final activity on page 55

    of the student book consolidates this by asking students

    to rank Hume’s criticisms. The second criticism on

    worksheet 3.1 tends to be enjoyed by students as Hume

    sarcastically draws out the conclusions of the design

    analogies. Original extracts from the Dialogues are

    also available on the CD-ROM for distribution as you

    see fit. The CD-ROM also includes an additional

    PowerPoint file outlining Hume’s key ideas, and the

    task at the end of this file can be completed in

    47

  • 8/20/2019 Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

    3/23

    conjunction with the extracts from the Dialogues.

    "ifferentiation

    Students could either complete worksheet 3.1 as it is or

    they could rank the criticisms if this is found to be

    easier. Question 4 will provide some stretch and

    challenge and could be left until after Mill and Darwin

    have been studied. The textual extracts from the

     Dialogues (available on the CD-ROM) are also well

    worth looking at and may be distributed to the class or

    to more able students as you see fit.

    $lenar%

    Hume believed that comparing the world to a man-

    made machine was an invalid analogy. The world is

    more like something organic (a vegetable even!). A

    fun plenary could involve going round the group and

    each student contributing a sentence to the statement:

    ‘The world is like a machine/ a plant because ...’. A

    prize could be awarded for the most original

     justification of a view.

    +ill and "arin

    (student book pages 5-–5.

    !tarter 

    It is likely that some or all students will already have

    some awareness of Darwin and his theories. Ask

    students what they know, or think they know, about

    Darwinian thought and its implications for religious

    belief.

    "e#elopment and resources

    The text on pages 56–57 of the student book gives a

    good summary of Darwinian theory. It is important that

    students are able to explain how Darwin’s ideas affect

    the argument from design and not just state his theory

    of evolution. One way of enabling students to

    consolidate work on Darwin is by producing a

    PowerPoint® explaining his ideas on evolution and,

    most importantly in this subject, how it affects this

    argument.

    The second activity on page 56 of the student bookserves a similar function in that it asks students to

    bullet point Darwin’s case against the Teleological

    Argument. The ‘For debate’ activity on page 57 is also

    effective in getting students to consider how Darwinian

    theory might actually strengthen the Teleological

    Argument. As well as on page 57 of the student book,

    there are extracts from Mill’s original writings,

    together with a more detailed set of notes explaining

    his ideas, on the CD-ROM. Mill agrees with Hume

    about the imperfections within the world. This leadshim to conclude that there is a designer but not in the

    traditional Christian sense. The designer could not be

    both all powerful and all good. There is potential here

    to make links with the problem of evil or to remind

    students of Mill when they come to do this topic later.

    "ifferentiation

    The ‘Anthropic Principle’ worksheet, available on the

    CD-ROM, is in addition to the limits of the

    specification and is a ‘stretch and challenge’ sheet thatengages with the arguments of the 20th century

    following on from Darwin. It is worth stressing to

    students that even if Darwin is completely accurate on

    evolution, this need not rule out the involvement of

    God. Depending on time, there are some possible

    research avenues and the potential for excellent

    debates. The general rule of giving a little more time if

    students are enthused may apply here.

    $lenar%

    A possible 5–10 minute plenary could involve the

    teacher making a series of statements such as ‘human

    beings are so complex, they have to be designed by

    God’; ‘If Darwin is right, there can be no God’.

    Students move on one side of the room if they agree

    with the statement, the other if they don’t. Students

    who are unsure could be allowed to remain in the

    middle. If you have a little more time, you may wish to

    invite students to present arguments to persuade others

    to move.

    48

  • 8/20/2019 Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

    4/23

    OCR AS Philosophy and Ethics  1 Ancient Greek influences

    A/uinas) 0osmologicalArgument criticisms of it

    (student book pages *–*

    !tarter 

    A kinaesthetic opening to this argument is the domino

    rally task outlined in the scheme of work. Ask students

    what causes each item to fall. It is worth labouring the

    point until the start of the chain is reached. Students

    will usually say that the person pushing the firstdomino or book caused the event. Ask what caused the

    person to be there. Then what caused their parents to

    be there and so on. It is quite easy to trace this back to

    the start of the universe. Is there a first cause where the

    chain of events starts? For religious believers the

    answer is yes, the start of this chain is God.

    "e#elopment and resources

    It is worth making sure that students are clear on how

    Cosmological Arguments differ from TeleologicalArguments before getting too far into this topic. The

    Cosmological Argument is an argument about origins

    and asks what caused the universe to exist and what

    does its existence depend upon. The Teleological

    Argument examines the quality of the universe and

    asks how it appears to be so well designed.

     Aquinas

    Ways one, two and three of Aquinas’ Five Ways are all

    Cosmological Arguments and are illustrated on page

    49 of the student book (students can research the fourth

    and fifth Ways as a stretch and challenge activity).

    Aquinas’ first and second Ways are straightforward to

    grasp and can be read easily. The original texts are

    available on the CD-ROM for more in-depth study.

    Aquinas’ third Way from contingency is a trickier

    concept and requires more careful handling. Worksheet

    3.2 is a light-hearted ‘way’ into this. If students can

    understand that there are two types of existence, the

    contingent and the necessary, they should grasp the

    argument. Essentially, Aquinas argues that the

    explanation of the universe, both in terms of its origins

    and its continued existence, cannot be a contingentthing: so either nothing did it or a necessary being was

    responsible – that necessary being is God.

     Hume’s criticisms

    Hume’s criticisms of Aquinas are presented on page

    48–49 of the student book. The learning is further

    consolidated by worksheet 3.3, which presents a

     jumbled list of Hume’s criticisms for students to sort

    and match against a simple Cosmological Argument.

    Hume challenges all three points of the argument,including our seemingly common sense belief in the

    principle of cause and effect.

    49

  • 8/20/2019 Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

    5/23

    "ifferentiationThe tasks on worksheet 3.3 may prove too challenging

    for some students. Kinaesthetic learners may be able to

    access this by role-playing the conversation in small

    groups prior to writing.

    $lenar%&e'tension

    As a plenary or extension activity students could

    discuss Hume’s views on causation: that we cannot be

    certain of cause and effect; it may just be that we

    associate two things by habit. One way to illustrate thisis to drop a ruler to the floor and ask what caused it to

    fall. ‘The teacher did’ is the common sense view.

    Hume, as an empiricist, would ask ‘what do you see?’.

    The answer is two events: releasing the ruler then the

    ruler falling. Hume argues that it is our mind that

    assumes cause and effect. A similar example, but not

    one suitable for carrying out in the classroom, is

    provided in the student book to consolidate this point.

    0opleston and 4ussell(student book pages 5–51

    !tarter 

    Quickly recap, through class Q&A, the key principles

    of the Cosmological Argument to check students are

    familiar before tackling Copleston and Russell’s

    encounter.

    "e#elopment and resources

    Students should read through pages 50–51 of the

    student book, which include important extracts and key

    points from the debate. The accompanying activities

    consolidate the learning and enable you to check

    understanding.

    The transcript of the debate is available on the CD-

    ROM, together with an audio file reconstruction of

    some of the key sections.

    More able students should be able to access some

    extracts of the debate. Students could summarise the

    views of the thinkers by imagining that they are

    presenting a highlights programme (or as the studentbook puts it: ‘Philosophy Match of the Day’). Key

    questions to reflect upon: who ‘won’ the debate? What

    do you think and why? Is Russell answering or

    avoiding the question in saying that the universe is just

    a brute fact?

    "ifferentiation

    Some students will find the extracts of the debate

    difficult to access. It may be worth sticking to the

    student book pages 50–51 for these students. The keypoint to convey is that Copleston believes that all things,

    including the universe, require an explanation. Russell

    rejects this line of reasoning and does not consider the

    origin of the universe to be a worthwhile question.

    $lenar%

    Students could summarise this topic by producing a

    spider diagram showing the key ideas of each thinker

    on this argument. Alternatively the idea for a strip

    cartoon activity (page 51 of the student book) would

    work well as a plenary and/or homework activity.

    The +oral Argument from 6ant

    and challenges from 7reud

    (student book pages -–-3

    !tarter 

    The topic could be introduced via a ‘right or wrong’

    quiz where the teacher gives several actions and askswhether they are right or wrong. Focus on the areas

    where all students agree that an action is wrong (e.g.

    cannibalism, rape or setting fire to cats). What is it that

    makes these actions wrong? Is it wrong? Are there

    absolute values? Where do these values come from?

    Alternatively the conversation between teacher and

    student over the badly marked essay (worksheet 3.5)

    could be the basis of discussion. The ‘For debate’

    activity on page 60 of the student book could also be

    used as a starter activity. Explain that MoralArguments suggest there are absolute values and these

    cannot be explained without God.

    50

  • 8/20/2019 Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

    6/23

    OCR AS Philosophy and Ethics  1 Ancient Greek influences

    "e#elopment and resources

     Kant’s Moral Argument

    Use the student book (pages 60–61) to outline Kant’s

    argument and draw out the difference between

    hypothetical and categorical imperatives. (It may also

    be appropriate to review Kant’s ethics if this topic has

    already been taught.) Students should be able to work

    through worksheet 3.4 using differentiated resources,

    including the student book. It is worth pointing out two

    things that Kant does not do that often end upappearing on examination papers.

    Firstly, note that Kant does not claim to prove God’s

    existence. Rather he claims that if there is to be such a

    thing as absolute morality, then freedom, immortality

    and God’s existence have to be postulated. Hence the

    Moral Argument is not a proof. Kant himself said that

    God’s existence could never be proved: ‘I demolish

    knowledge to make room for faith.’

    Secondly, Kant’s Moral Argument is not a Divine

    Command ethic. Although morality may suggest the

    existence of God, it is not the case that God commands

    things to be right or wrong. We are able to arrive at this

    knowledge using our reason.

     Freud 

    It may be possible to draw on the knowledge of

    psychology students to give a general introduction to

    Freud. His ideas appear in a very accessible form on

    pages 62–63 of the textbook. There is an audio file that

    gives an imaginary interview with Freud, as well as a

    detailed PowerPoint®, on the CD-ROM with an

    additional task at the end. The CD-ROM also includes

    some original extracts from Freud. Together, these will

    enable students to complete worksheet 3.5.

    "ifferentiation

    There is a great deal of material on worksheet 3.5 and

    teachers will need to decide what is appropriate for

    their groups and how the work should be organised.

    Paired work or splitting the tasks between the groups

    may be a means of differentiation.

    The stretch and challenge activities on worksheet 3.5may be omitted, depending on time. However,

    Dawkins’ high profile in the media may also give

    students an interest in his view that morality is

    something that evolves: those who ‘behave well’

    towards others are more likely to pass on their genes.

    51

  • 8/20/2019 Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

    7/23

    $lenar%Discuss possible strengths and weaknesses of Kant’s

    argument (weaknesses do not need to be limited to

    Freudian criticisms). The ‘For debate’ activity on page

    63 of the student book invites students to debate

    whether ‘just because we know how we ought to

    behave doesn’t mean there is a God.’ This could be a

    good basis for discussion.

    The 8ntological Argument and

    criticisms of it(student book pages *2–*.

    This is often felt by students to be the hardest topic on

    the AS. Accordingly there are a number of worksheets in

    this pack that aim at clarifying the key thinkers’ ideas.

    !tarter 

    Review the difference between a priori and a

     posteriori by issuing a set of statements. Which are

    proved by logic? Which by experience? The

    Ontological Argument is unusual. It claims that one

    can know that God has to exist purely by logic in the

    same way that 2 added to 2 has to be 4. Prior to

    introducing them to the argument, I dramatically and

    seriously inform my students that when they see this

    argument, they will realise that God has to exist and

    they will become regular visitors to their local church

    or mosque.

    "e#elopment and resources

     Anselm and Gaunilo

    It may be worth splitting Anselm’s arguments and

    returning to the second argument after consideration of

    Gaunilo’s objection. Although students must be made

    aware that Anselm’s second argument is not written in

    response to Gaunilo. One way of making students think 

    is to introduce Anselm’s argument in the last 5–10

    minutes of a lesson. Invite students to think about the

    argument and comment in the next lesson. Goodstudents often anticipate the objection of Gaunilo,

    which is outlined on page 43 of the student book.

    Page 42 of the student book includes an illustration ofAnselm’s first argument, while worksheet 3.6 provides

    Anselm’s first argument in his own words. Students

    could research and find the second version in his own

    words, but the language is quite difficult in places.

    Drawing (worksheet 3.7) or describing (student book

    page 43) the perfect island can open up other elements

    of discussion. All our islands are different. Do we have

    different concepts of God? Which would be proved if

    the argument worked? Worksheet 3.7 enables

    clarification of Gaunilo’s views. He writes on behalf of 

    the fool in response to Anselm, who had quoted Psalm

    14: ‘the fool says in his heart, there is no God.’

    Anselm’s second argument (see pages 44–45 of the

    student book) could be used to counter this as he

    suggests that his argument can only work for a

    necessary being. Students may consider this to be a

    ‘cop out’. It is worth pointing out that Gaunilo does

    actually believe in God and is essentially adopting a

    devil’s advocate role. Some students in examinationsthink that Gaunilo proves that perfect islands must

    exist. Obviously he does not; he is using this argument

    as an analogy to show the flaws in Anselm’s thinking.

     Descartes

    The information on page 45 of the student book gives a

    good introduction to Descartes’ theory that existence is

    a necessary part of the meaning of God. The activity on

    composing analytic and synthetic sentences will prove

    useful both in understanding Descartes and in

    understanding Kant’s objections (worksheet 3.9).

    Worksheet 3.8 enables students to further explore and

    evaluate Descartes’ claim that God has to exist. It

    follows the structure of Descartes’ argument in chapter 5

    of his Meditations. Descartes starts by explaining certain

    things that are necessary to triangles and mountains.

    This enables him to define what the word necessary

    means (it cannot not be true). He then goes on to apply

    this to God. Descartes anticipates possible objections to

    his argument and suggests that it can only apply to God.

     Kant

    52

  • 8/20/2019 Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

    8/23

    OCR AS Philosophy and Ethics  1 Ancient Greek influences

    (See worksheet 3.9.) Students need to understand thatthe statement ‘God has necessary existence’ is analytic

    and can say nothing about whether God might exist. It

    merely defines the concept. It will be useful to refer

    students to page 46 of the student book to help them

    understand this point: in particular Kant’s quotation

    about the triangle.

    The activities within worksheet 3.9 should enable you

    to check whether the students have grasped the ideas of 

    this tricky thinker.

    "ifferentiation

    After working through the three possible arguments

    against Descartes, most students should be ready to

    tackle an examination style question. The Exam Caf é 

    in the textbook shows some answers of varying quality

    to questions on the Ontological Argument. These

    answers may give guidance to weaker students to draft

    a reasonable answer to a question. More able students

    should see these answers as a challenge: they can be

    bettered!

    More able students may wish to consider whether there

    is any place for the Ontological Argument today by

    researching modern versions such as those of Malcolm

    and Plantinga.

    $lenar%&consolidationStudents could produce a revision booklet giving the

    key points of each thinker and strengths and

    weaknesses. The Exam Caf é in this PDR contains

    some blank templates that could be used to structure

    students’ thoughts.

    9'am 0af:

    The Exam Caf é in the student book and in this PDR

    reinforces the skills needed to succeed at this course.

    The student book (page 64) gives the ‘seven deadly

    sins’ committed in exams on these topics. It is well

    worth getting students to look at these or some will

    most likely repeat some of the errors. The revision

    checklists can be used by students to get a feel for how

    they are doing on each topic. There are sample answers

    on an Ontological Argument part a) in the student

    book. Material on the part b) is found in this PDR. As

    always students may learn a lot from looking at these

    answers and discussing what makes them good or not

    so good as the case may be.

    53

  • 8/20/2019 Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

    9/23

    3 Traditional arguments for the e'istence of God OCR AS Philosophy and Ethics

    ;esson $lan< The Teleological Argument

    0hapter 3< ;esson plan

    Heinemann recognises that the teaching of this qualification will vary greatly from school to school and from

    teacher to teacher With that in mind! this lesson "lan is offered as a "ossi#le a""roach #ut will #e su#$ect to

    modifications #y the individual teacher %esson length is assumed to #e one hour

    ;earning ob=ecti#es for the lesson

    O#$ective & 'tudents to understand the #asic "remise #ehind Teleological (rguments

    O#$ective ) 'tudents to #e a#le to e*"lain +aley,s analogy in a clear and straightforward way

    4ecap of pre#ious e'perience and prior knoledge

    • Review of arguments for -od .o they #elieve in -od or not/ What reasons might "eo"le have for #elieving

    in -od/ What reasons might other "eo"le have for not #elieving in -od/ The nature of this discussion will

    de"end on students, e*"erience at -0'E 'ome may have a good 1nowledge of this already If good

    discussion develo"s it may #e worth giving this e*tra time

    0ontent

    Time 0ontent

    15 minutes Warm2u" activity reviewing the arguments for and against -od 3descri#ed a#ove4'tudents to summarise the discussion #y writing u" arguments "resented as a ta#le

    1 minutes 'tudent activity5 $igsaws 'tudents are issued with sim"le $igsaws 3u" to )6786 "ieces4E*"lain that this is a rare chance to do an e*"eriment in R' 'ome grou"s attem"t tosolve the $igsaws #lindfolded 3or #y throwing "ieces u" in the air94 whereas others use their intelligence and sight It can #e treated as a race

    1 minutes Review and discussion of activity Is it "ossi#le for the $igsaw to #e solved #lind orrandomly/ (re com"le* "u::les more li1ely to #e solved #y intelligence or chance/ Is acom"le* thing such as the universe more li1ely to #e designed or the "roduct of chance/Is the $igsaw a fair analogy/This discussion may #e worth giving more time to if students "articularly warm to itTeacher to write a sim"le Teleological (rgument on the #oard5 ;(ll com"le* things requireintelligence to #ring them a#out! the universe is a com"le* thing! therefore the universerequired intelligence to #ring it a#out,

    15 minutes 'tudent activity5 issue a summary or e*tract of +aley,s watch analogy 'tudents read andsummarise his argument .o they acce"t his claims that the analogy still wor1s if we don,t1now what the o#$ect is! or if the watch is #ro1en/ Is it fair to com"are the universe to awatch/ 'tudents write down initial res"onses

    0onsolidation

    Time 0ontent

    5 minutes Teacher to chec1 what has #een learned

  • 8/20/2019 Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

    10/23

    OCR AS Philosophy and Ethics 3 Traditional arguments for the e'istence of God

    3?10riticisms of the TeleologicalArgument b% "a#id ume

    Hume (1711–76) criticised the design argument in his Dialogues concerning Natural Religion (1779). His arguments are based on his empiricism. This empiricism logically leads, for Hume, to

    naturalism and scepticism. He argued that design is something that we perceive and assume. Even if 

    the world appears to be designed, this may just be due to our interpretation of the data that our

    senses provide.

    Summary of Hume’s criticisms

    1. Humans do not have sufficient knowledge of the origins of the world to assume that there is only

    one designer. As humans we only have experience of the things that we design and create. These

    may not be an adequate analogy. We know that houses require a designer because we haveexperience of many houses being built. We only have experience of this universe. He argued that

    it was impossible to draw conclusions about the whole from a small part. Also the universe is not

    like a vast machine. It is more like a living thing such as a vegetable or inert animal, something

    that grows of its own accord rather than something made by hand.

    2. Even if design analogies were valid it would not necessarily follow that the designer was the

    God of theism. Hume suggests that we might have the work of several lesser gods or an

    ‘apprentice’ god who went on to create bigger and better worlds or ‘the production of old age

    and dotage in some superannuated deity.’ He speculates that there may be other worlds that are

    not as good as this one, made whilst this God was practising.

    3. Hume felt that people who believe in God project human beliefs onto a non-human world. He

    argued that to discuss design in human terms is not an acceptable analogy on the grounds that

    God by definition transcends understanding. If we use a human analogy it is more usual for a

    machine to be the product of many hands rather than one designer.

    4. Hume also used the ideas of the Greek philosopher Epicurus (the Epicurean Thesis). Epicurus

    puts forward the possibility of infinite time. In infinite time there is a huge but finite number of

    particles freely moving about. In infinite time, they go through every possible combination. If

    any one combination happens to represent a stable order, it must occur. The very nature of a

    stable order is that it must fit together well – it would have the appearance of design. It could be

    in such a place that we find ourselves. Thus, apparent design could happen at random – there is

    no necessity to infer a designer.

    1. Find out what empiricism means. Why does it logically lead to scepticism and naturalism?

    2. Explain why Hume thinks that the uniqueness of the universe prevents us from reaching

    conclusions about its origin. Is his conclusion correct?

    3. What are Hume’s conclusions about the designer, if there is one?

    4. Why does he reach these conclusions? Assess whether his conclusion is correct.

    5. Imagine that Hume was able to discuss the Teleological Argument with the other thinkers that

    you have studied during this topic. Write a dialogue summarising their discussions. You are

    allowed to use humour but not at the expense of content.

    5*  > $earson 9ducation ;td 2

  • 8/20/2019 Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

    11/23

    3 Traditional arguments for the e'istence of God OCR AS Philosophy and Ethics

    3?2A/uinas) argument from contingenc%(third @a%

    1. What is meant by contingent? Give an example of a contingent truth.

    2. What is meant by necessary? Give an example of a necessary truth.

    Aquinas argues that:

    > There are things which are contingent; they may or may not exist. They do not have to exist.

    > ontingent things are !inite. They come into existence and then "ass o#t o! existence.

    > $t is im"ossi%&e !or contingent things to have a&ways existed; there m#st have %een a time whenno contingent things existed.

    > '#t things that %egin to exist on&y do so when ca#sed %y something that a&ready exists.

    > The "revio#s two "oints &ead to the concsion that nothing exists now( %#t this is a%s#rd.)o there m#st %e in existence something that is necessary.

    > This %eing derives its necessity !rom itse&!( it does not de"end on anything e&se and isres"onsi%&e !or a&& things. This is the conce"t that "eo"&e re!er to as *od.

    3. Write a dialogue similar to that between Stu and Lou with the aim of explaining the rest of thisargument.

     > $earson 9ducation ;td 2 55

    Stu: Things don’t have to be the way they are, it could be different.

     Lou: You appear to be considering the idea of contingency, colleague. For instance, I currently exist

    but I don’t have to. Had my parents not met I would not exist at all. This prompts philosophers to

    suggest that all things in this world are contingent.

    Stu: So although I have never had a girlfriend, it doesn’t have to be this way?

     Lou: Technically yes, but bad example, my friend.

    Stu: Great! I’m going to find my maths teacher. She has marked my homework incorrectly.

     Lou: How come?

    Stu: I worked out that triangles have 4 sides. She said it was wrong! Now I have philosophical

    evidence that it doesn’t have to be wrong.

     Lou: Your maths and your love life are equally embarrassing, colleague. It is a necessary truth that

    triangles have 3 sides. It is a statement that cannot be false. Still, at least you’re only contingently

    stupid!

  • 8/20/2019 Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

    12/23

    OCR AS Philosophy and Ethics 3 Traditional arguments for the e'istence of God

    3?3ume)s criticisms of the 0osmologicalArgument

    A simple Cosmological Argument would say: all events have a cause→ there must be a firstcause→ that first cause is God.

    Hume’s criticisms of this argument

    > +e cannot esta%&ish !or certain the "rinci"&e o! ca#se and e!!ect. ,#me arg#es that we see event- !o&&owed %y event '. This does not "rove that - ca#ses '.

    > rom an e!!ect( we cannot in!er a ca#se greater than that re/#ired to "rod#ce the e!!ect. +e

    o%serve a wor&d that is im"er!ect and &imited !inite. There!ore it might %e more &ogica& to say

    that the ca#se is a&so !inite !inite ca#ses are &ie&y to "rod#ce !inite e!!ects. $n !act( why not say

    that the wor&d is ca#sed %y ma&e and !ema&e *ods who are %orn and who die

    > id $ show yo# the "artic#&ar ca#ses o! each individ#a& in a co&&ection o! twenty "artic&es o!

    matter( $ sho#&d thin it very #nreasona%&e( sho#&d yo# a!terwards as me( what was the ca#se o! 

    the who&e twenty. This is s#!!icient&y ex"&ained in ex"&aining the ca#se o! the "arts. This is the

    a&&acy o! om"osition. ,#mes "oint is that i! we now a%o#t ca#ses within the #niverse( we

    do not a&so need to ex"&ain the #niverse as a who&e. #sse&& a&so maes this "oint it is one thing

    to say that every h#man %eing has a mother( %#t we cannot move !rom this to say that there is a

    mother !or the who&e h#man race.

    >  o statement a%o#t existence can %e &ogica&&y necessary. -ny %eing c&aimed to exist may or maynot exist. This is %ased on ,#mes !or. To say that a statement is necessary means that its

    o""osite wo#&d %e a &ogica& contradiction. :et it is "ossi%&e to say that *od does not exist( it is

    not &ie saying that triang&es have !o#r sides.

    > +hy may not the materia& #niverse %e the necessari&y existent 'eing... +e dare not a!!irm that

    we now a&& the /#a&ities o! matter. ,#me arg#es that one o! the "ro"erties o! matter might %e

    that it has to exist and cannot "ass o#t o! existence !or a&& we now. )o the #niverse itse&! may

     %e necessary.

    > -n in!inite series o! ca#ses is "ossi%&e. oes the chain o! ca#ses have to end somewhere $! the#niverse were eterna&( it wo#&d %e a%s#rd to ta& o! it having a ca#se.

    1. Rewrite Hume’s criticisms in your own words, placing them in three separate groups according

    to which premise of our simple argument they are attacking.

    2. Which of his arguments are successful and why? Try to draft a response to Hume’s arguments

    that would be made by a theist.

    4. Write 1–2 paragraphs on your views on whether Aquinas’ or Hume’s arguments are stronger.

    5-  > $earson 9ducation ;td 2

  • 8/20/2019 Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

    13/23

    3 Traditional arguments for the e'istence of God OCR AS Philosophy and Ethics

    3?* The +oral ArgumentUse the student book together with your class notes to work through these tasks.

    1. Sentences a) to j) are either true or false. Copy or correct them accordingly.

    a) Kant believed that the Moral Argument proves the existence of God.

    b) He believed that morality is a rational thing which gives everyone an obligation as to what is

    right and wrong.

    c) His principle of universal law was a categorical imperative.

    d) A categorical imperative is a principle that you follow in order to achieve something.

    e) A categorical imperative logically has to be obeyed.

    f) For morality to exist we have to assume freedom, God and immortality.

    g) Kant believed that the aim of morality is to obey God’s commands.

    h) To say that we ‘ought’ to do something implies that we can.

    i) The Summum Bonum is possible, but not in this life.

     j) This highest good requires the existence of God and a ten-year period after our deaths.

    2. Explain carefully why freedom is necessary for there to be any morality. Kant argues that ‘ought

    implies can’. What does he mean?

    3. What is the Summum Bonum and why does Kant suggest that this requires an unlimited time?

    4. Why does Kant believe that the notion of Summum Bonum implies the existence of God?

    5. Kant has come up with an explanation of why we have morality. What other explanations mightthere be? How would these affect his argument?

    6. Make a table of the strengths and weaknesses of Kant’s argument. Aim to cover 3–4 of each.

    Exam practice

    Look at the OCR specification for the Moral Argument, together with past examination questions.

    Working in pairs, try to devise two possible exam questions. Draft bullet-pointed answers to your

    questions.

     > $earson 9ducation ;td 2 5.

  • 8/20/2019 Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

    14/23

    OCR AS Philosophy and Ethics 3 Traditional arguments for the e'istence of God

    3?5 0riticisms of the +oral ArgumentCriticism 1: Freud

    One possible line of attack against Moral Arguments generally is to find an alternative explanation

    of morality. This is precisely what Sigmund Freud attempted to achieve. Freud’s view of religion is

    influenced by Feuerbach’s theory that God is wish fulfilment. Religion is a ‘universal obsessional

    neurosis, an illusion that we construct psychologically. Our mind is made up of Id, Ego and Super-

    ego. The Super-ego is the source of our morality.’

    1. Using the student book and the resources on the CD-ROM, produce some detailed notes on

    Freud’s criticism of the Moral Argument by elaborating on the themes that are in bold.

    Criticism 2: Moral Relativism

    Perhaps more common is the approach that says there is no absolute morality by arguing from the

    fact of moral and cultural relativism. The following conversation, between a teacher who has just

    given a U to a student who has written an excellent essay arguing that there is no such thing as

    morality, may bring this approach into question.

    Who do you think is right in the above argument? Must the student accept that there are actualmoral values in order to win the argument?

    Other criticisms

    2. Stretch and challenge: in pairs, research one of the areas below and present it to the class.

    > arxs view that o#r %e&ie!s a%o#t mora&ity are ca#sed %y society.

    > awins %io&ogica& ex"&anation o! mora&ity.

    > -yers view that mora& $earson 9ducation ;td 2

    Student: Excuse me, Sir, but this mark seems a little harsh. In fact, I notice that you gave an A

    to Charlotte’s essay, which was quite similar, so mine should have got a similar mark.

    Teacher: That would require the assumption that I was marking fairly.

    Student: You seem to be picking on me, this is the third U this year. It’s unfair!

    Teacher: You’re right, I am being most unfair.

    Student: So, you admit you are behaving wrongly towards me. This is appalling!

    Teacher: Ironic! I seem to remember you arguing that there was no such thing as right and wrong.

    Yet your outrage at my discrimination against you suggests that you do, in practice,

    think that some things are right or wrong.

  • 8/20/2019 Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

    15/23

    3 Traditional arguments for the e'istence of God OCR AS Philosophy and Ethics

    3?- Anselm)s 8ntological ArgumentRead the extract below from Proslogion chapter 2 and answer the questions that follow.

    ‘ And indeed we believe you are something greater than which cannot be thought. Or is there no

    such kind of thing, for “the fool said in his heart, ‘there is no God’” (Ps. 13:1, 52:1)? But certainly

    that same fool, having heard what I just said, “something greater than which cannot be thought,”

    understands what he heard, and what he understands is in his thought, even if he does not think it

    exists. For it is one thing for something to exist in a person’s thought and quite another for the

     person to think that thing exists. For when a painter thinks ahead to what he will paint, he has that

     picture in his thought, but he does not yet think it exists, because he has not done it yet. Once he has

     painted it he has it in his thought and thinks it exists because he has done it. Thus even the fool is

    compelled to grant that something greater than which cannot be thought exists in thought, because

    he understands what he hears, and whatever is understood exists in thought. And certainly that

    greater than which cannot be understood cannot exist only in thought, for if it exists only in thought 

    it could also be thought of as existing in reality as well, which is greater. If, therefore, that than

    which greater cannot be thought exists in thought alone, then that than which greater cannot be

    thought turns out to be that than which something greater actually can be thought, but that is

    obviously impossible. Therefore something than which greater cannot be thought undoubtedly

    exists both in thought and in reality.’

    1. Write Anselm’s definition of God in your own words.

    2. What does Anselm think that even the fool has to admit?

    3. Why does he think ‘that greater than which cannot be understood’ can’t just exist in the mind?

    4. Why does God have to exist, according to Anselm?

    5. What does it mean to call this an a priori argument?

    Now read this modern paraphrase of Anselm’s second argument from Proslogion 3:

    ‘Come to think of it, God so exists that He cannot be thought not to exist. Given that God can’t

    logically be thought not to exist, He is greater than all things that do exist but can be thought of as

    not existing. In fact if God could be thought of as not existing then he is not “that than which no

    greater can be thought.” And the definition would be contradictory. God has to exist and cannot be

    thought of as not existing. By definition it is not possible for Him not to be.’

    6. Does this help to improve the argument? Give a reason for your answer.

     > $earson 9ducation ;td 2 5

  • 8/20/2019 Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

    16/23

    OCR AS Philosophy and Ethics 3 Traditional arguments for the e'istence of God

    3?. Gaunilo)s criticism of AnselmIt’s not very often that you are given permission to daydream in class. Spend a few minutes drawingyour perfect holiday island. When you return from your dreaming, the argument on this page may

    give you some pleasant news!

    1. Explain Gaunilo’s objection in your own words (2–3 sentences).

    2. Gaunilo doesn’t really believe in the island’s existence. He is using a device known as reductio

    ad absurdum.

    Find out what reductio ad absurdum means and explain how Gaunilo’s argument is a good exampleof it.

    3. Why does Gaunilo entitle his response ‘On behalf of the Fool?’

    4. Anselm thought that he could counter Gaunilo’s objection and had possibly already done so in

    his second argument. How could Anselm respond?

    5. Who has the stronger argument, Anselm or Gaunilo? Give a reason for your answer.

    -  > $earson 9ducation ;td 2

    Gaunilo’s reply to Anselm

    ‘For example, they say there is in the ocean somewhere an island which, due to the difficulty (or

    rather the impossibility) of finding what does not actually exist, is called “the lost island.” And they

    say that this island has all manner of riches and delights, even more of them than the Isles of the

    Blest, and having no owner or inhabitant it is superior in the abundance of its riches to all other

    lands which are inhabited by men.

    ‘If someone should tell me that such is the case, I will find it easy to understand what he says, since

    there is nothing difficult about it. But suppose he then adds, as if he were stating a logical

    consequence, “Well then, you can no longer doubt that this island more excellent than all other

    lands really exists somewhere, since you do not doubt that it is in your mind; and since it is more

    excellent to exist not only in the mind but in reality as well, this island must necessarily exist,

    because if it didn’t, any other island really existing would be more excellent than it, and thus that

    island now thought of by you as more excellent will not be such.”

    ‘If, I say, someone tries to convince me through this argument that the island really exists and thereshould be no more doubt about it, I will either think he is joking or I will have a hard time deciding

    who is the bigger fool, me if I believe him or him if he thinks he has proved its existence.’

  • 8/20/2019 Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

    17/23

    3 Traditional arguments for the e'istence of God OCR AS Philosophy and Ethics

    3? "escartes) 8ntological ArgumentRené Descartes’ version of the Ontological Argument is in some ways clearer than that of Anselm.

    Stage 1: Explain what ‘necessary’ means

    Descartes argues that we cannot (logically) conceive of a triangle without it having three angles; nor

    can we think of a mountain without a valley. These ideas are necessary to the definition of the

    words. In the same way there are certain ideas that are necessary to the definition of God.

    Stage 2: Give your argument

    Descartes’ argument can be simplified as follows:

    > *od %y de!inition is a s#"reme&y "er!ect %eing.

    > - s#"reme&y "er!ect %eing has a&& "er!ections.

    > >xistence is one o! these "er!ections.

    > There!ore *od has existence( he exists.

    Therefore, according to Descartes, we cannot think of God without conceiving of him as existing.

    We may not ever think of God but if we do, we will work out by logic and reason that he has to

    exist. It is necessary. Descartes admits that we may be slightly stunned by this and think that he has

    tricked us but he is adamant that he hasn’t.

    Stage 3: Why this argument absolutely works!

    Descartes attempted to guard against the sort of attack that Gaunilo developed against Anselm. He

    says that:

    > The arg#ment can on&y wor !or a "er!ect and necessary %eing it cannot( there!ore( %e a""&ied

    to something &ie a &ost is&and.

    >  ot everyone has to thin o! *od( %#t i! they do thin o! *od then *od cannot %e tho#ght not to

    exist.

    > *od a&one is the %eing whose essence= entai&s *ods existence. There cannot %e two or more

    s#ch %eings.

    * Essence means the characteristics or properties of a thing.

     > $earson 9ducation ;td 2 -1

  • 8/20/2019 Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

    18/23

    OCR AS Philosophy and Ethics 3 Traditional arguments for the e'istence of God

    3?"escartes) ontological argument(continued

    Look at the following arguments. Summarise them in your own words and consider how

    effective they are as criticisms by responding to the questions below.

    a) Aquinas had previously rejected precisely the point that Descartes wants to make. Descartes

    says we can know God’s essence and therefore we can say that God must exist. Aquinas

    does not think that God's essence is knowable to us.

    1. Do you think this is true and, if so, how would this affect Descartes?

    b) A philosopher named Gassendi criticised Descartes in a similar way to Gaunilo’s criticism of 

    Anselm. Gassendi suggests that if Pegasus is by definition a perfect horse then Pegasus mustexist. Descartes disagreed by arguing that triangles, mountains and God are real ideas

    whereas Pegasus and the Perfect Island are made up.

    2. Has Descartes successfully avoided the Gaunilo-Gassendi type argument or is his argument

    circular in presuming what can and cannot exist? What do you think?

    c) Maybe Descartes is right: it is impossible to have a triangle without it having three angles,

     just as it is impossible to have a spinster who is not female: the predicates* follow from the

    subjects. However, all this tells us is something about the idea of a triangle and not about

    whether there are any triangles. I could say that ‘It is necessary for a unicorn to have a horn’and this may indeed be true, but this does not prove there are any unicorns.

    d) Russell argued that only propositions can be necessary. Statements regarding existence must

    always be contingent. A being may or may not exist. A bachelor has to be an unmarried man

    (but this merely defines the concept, it does not tell you whether bachelors actually exist).

    3. What do you think?

    4. Is Russell correct or would God be a ‘special case’?

    * Look up the meaning of the word ‘predicate’. It will be useful when we go on to study Kant’s objection.

    -2  > $earson 9ducation ;td 2

  • 8/20/2019 Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

    19/23

    3 Traditional arguments for the e'istence of God OCR AS Philosophy and Ethics

    3?6ant)s criticism of the 8ntologicalArgument

    Kant’s argument part 1: Two types of statements

    In certain phrases meanings are implied by the choice of certain words. For example, bicycle

    implies two wheels. We do not need to say ‘a two-wheeled bicycle’. If we do say this, we add

    nothing new to our understanding. A bicycle logically has two wheels. Kant calls this an ‘analytic 

    statement ’: one in which we learn nothing new about the world.

    Kant distinguishes these from ‘synthetic statements’, which tell us something about the real world.

    Examples of synthetic statements would be: ‘It is raining outside’, or ‘The car is blue’. These

    statements can be verified or falsified by experience.

    1. Check that you understand the difference between analytic and synthetic statements. Give an

    example of an analytic and a synthetic statement for each of the following:

    a) A bachelor. b) A triangle. c) A black box.

    When we say that God is a necessary being, we are making an analytic statement. Necessary

    existence is part of our concept/idea of God, but tells us nothing about whether God actually

    exists. We end up saying no more than, ‘If God exists, then his existence is necessary’. So Kant

    argues that the Ontological Argument is based on a mistake. So what is the mistake?

    Kant’s argument part 2: Existence is not a predicate

    2. Look at the subject and predicates below. What do you think is unusual about the last one?

    (subject) (predicate) (verb + object)

    The boy kicks the ball/dances madly for 28 hours without stopping/exists.

    Kant said existence is not a predicate. It is not a property that a concept either has or does not

    have. In adding existence to a concept we do not describe the idea any further. So Kant presents

    the Ontological Argument with a possibly fatal challenge. If God’s necessary existence is an

    analytic statement, then it is a definition and tells us nothing about whether he actually exists. If

    it is a synthetic claim, then there is nothing necessary about God’s existence as only analytic

    statements would have logical necessity. All statements about existence are synthetic.

    3. What do you think? Write a paragraph giving your views on whether Kant’s criticism defeats

    the Ontological Argument.

     > $earson 9ducation ;td 2 -3

  • 8/20/2019 Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

    20/23

    3+ore arguments

    for God

    Get the result!

    Matt’s answer:

    -* 9'am 0af:  > $earson 9ducation ;td 2

     Anselm’s Ontological Argument is meant to

     prove the existence of God. Anselm thought

    that if you had an idea of God in your mind,

    then God would have to exist in reality in order

    to be the greatest conceivable being. Descartes

    would agree with Anselm that God’s existence is

    a logical necessity. So God has to exist. Gaunilo

    disagreed with Anselm. Gaunilo argued that we

    might have an idea of the perfect island, this

    doesn’t mean it has to exist. So Gaunilo would

    argue that God’s existence is not logically

    Exam question

    (b) Evaluate the claim that God’s existence is not a logical necessity. (10 marks).

     Another argument against the Ontological

     Argument is from ant. ant argued that

    existence is not a predicate. !his shows that

     Anselm’s argument is false. !herefore this

    shows that the Ontological Argument does not

     prove the existence of God.

    Some philosophers thin" that the Ontological

     Argument can wor" because God is very

    different from all other things in the universe so

    it might be that God has to exist but # don’t

    thin" that this is the case.

    The e'aminer sa%s<

    There is not a lot here a#out

    ;necessity, ?att seems to #e

    answering this as a general

    ;(ssess the Ontological

     (rgument, question The first

    two sentences leave the

    e*aminer to ma1e the

    connection How does @ant

    show that (nselm is wrong/ (

    counterargument is given ;I

    don,t thin1, is an assertion if itis not #ac1ed u" with an

    argument

    The e'aminer sa%s<

    ?att is answering this question

    #ut is doing so indirectly He

    seems to #e e*"laining the

    arguments of the thin1ers This

    shows he understands the

    Ontological (rgument #ut he

    should remem#er that this is an

     (6) question He should #e

    considering and discussing the

    argument rather than $ust hinting

    at it Aor instance! saying that.escartes would agree isn,t

    really an argument If he could

    un"ac1 some of these ideas in a

    little more detail! this would turn

    a reasona#le answer into a

    good one He also

    misre"resents (nselm,s

    argument that! if you understand

    the conce"t of -od! you realise

    he must e*ist ?att seems to #e

    imagining -od into e*istence

  • 8/20/2019 Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

    21/23

    3+ore arguments

    for God

    Zahid’s answer:

     > $earson 9ducation ;td 2 9'am 0af: -5

    ant would also agree that the existence of God

    is not a logical necessity. $point% &e argued that 

    existence is not a predicate. ant explained that 

    to say that something has existence does not

    add anything to the concept. !o say that God is

    all powerful would add information to the

    concept of God. &owever existence does not add 

    anything to the concept or idea of God. #t is part 

    of the sub'ect. $explanation% !his responded to

    the argument of Descartes who had previously

    stated that existence was a property necessary

    to the concept of God. $Other point of view%

    #t seems that ant is (uite correct to argue that

    matters concerning existence are synthetic and

    could only be verified by sense experience.

    )oncepts and ideas tell us nothing about what

    actually exists. As in *aths, to say that a

     pentagon has + sides does not mean that there

    are any pentagons existing anywhere within the

    world. $conclusion and example%

    The e'aminer sa%s<

    I have annotated "arts of

    Bahid,s answer that are

    "articularly good ?y "oints are

    in Csquare #rac1etsD

    These are the second and third

    "aragra"hs of Bahid,s answer

    The first "aragra"h of his

    answer loo1ed at -aunilo,s

    argument Why not try writing

    it/

    Matt: ‘I know now that I need

    to read the question more

    carefully and not just launch

    into my pre-prepared list of

    strengths and weaknesses of

    the topic.’ 

    Zahid: ‘I am pleased with my

    mark. I used the Exam af! as

    well as guidance from my

    teacher to impro"e my

    technique on part #$ question.’ 

    The e'aminer sa%s<

    I have annotated "arts of

    Bahid,s answer that are

    "articularly good ?y "oints are

    in Csquare #rac1etsD

    These are the second and third

    "aragra"hs of Bahid,s answer

    The first "aragra"h of his

    answer loo1ed at -aunilo,sargument Why not try writing it/

  • 8/20/2019 Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

    22/23

    3+ore arguments

    for God

    Once you have filled out this diagram, why not create similar charts to help you revise the other topics you

    have studied?

    -- 9'am 0af:  > $earson 9ducation ;td 2

    8ntological

    Arguments

    Anselm)s first #ersion

    Anselm)s second #ersion

    "escartes) #ersion

    +odern #ersions (e'tension

  • 8/20/2019 Chapter 3 - Traditional Arguments for the Existence of God (and Its Criticisms)

    23/23

    3+ore arguments

    for God

    Once you have filled out this diagram, why not create similar charts to help you revise the other topics you

    have studied?

    0hallenges to the

    8ntological Argument

    Gaunilo)s challenge

    6ant)s challenge

    8ther challenges

    +% #ie on the argument

    and h%???