Chapter 2. Lecture 1B. Responsibility

14
PHILOSOPHY OF THE HUMAN PERSON University of San Agustin AY: 2014-2015: First Semester CHAPTER 2: INTERPERSONAL DIMENSION Lecture 1B: The Human Person as a Social Being Responsibility Different Philosophers in this View Martin Buber’sI-Thou Relationship Martin Buber is an Austrian-born Israeli existentialist religious and social philosopher. He is a professor at University of Frankfurt am Main and Hebrew University of Jerusalem. Buber’s philosophy centred on relations between the “self” and others; he radically contrasted this to relations between the “self” and objects. He argued that central features of our ethical, social, and religious life become unintelligible if we understand human relations and relations to God in terms of our relations to objects. In human relations, we respond to the presence and individuality of others in forming joint human projects rather than seeing others as object to manipulate. His theology understood God as the ultimate “Thou.” His main works are I and Thou and Paths in Utopia. i Levels of Human Relationship According to Martin Buber, the world is twofold because the human attitude toward it is twofold. This twofold attitude is reflected in the formulations I–It and I–Thou (or I–You). For Buber, they are the two primary relationships between oneself and another. Buber realized that there is a basic difference between relating to a thing or to an object that I observe, and to a person or a Thouwho addresses me and to whose address I respond. This is the difference between the way people usually relate to inanimate things on the one hand and to living persons on the other. As a person is not a “what” but a “who”; a person is a “who” and not a “what”,the person is a subject and not an object or thing; and since the person is a subject, hence, the person is a self. The human person according to Martin Buber may adopt two attitudes toward another person and the world. 1

description

Chapter 2. Lecture 1B. Responsibility

Transcript of Chapter 2. Lecture 1B. Responsibility

PHILOSOPHY OF THE HUMAN PERSONUniversity of San AgustinAY: 2014-2015: First Semester

CHAPTER 2: INTERPERSONAL DIMENSIONLecture 1B: The Human Person as a Social Being

ResponsibilityDifferent Philosophers in this View

Martin BubersI-Thou Relationship

Martin Buber is an Austrian-born Israeli existentialist religious and social philosopher. He is a professor at University of Frankfurt am Main and Hebrew University of Jerusalem. Bubers philosophy centred on relations between the self and others; he radically contrasted this to relations between the self and objects. He argued that central features of our ethical, social, and religious life become unintelligible if we understand human relations and relations to God in terms of our relations to objects. In human relations, we respond to the presence and individuality of others in forming joint human projects rather than seeing others as object to manipulate. His theology understood God as the ultimate Thou. His main works are I and Thou and Paths in Utopia.[endnoteRef:2] [2: ]

Levels of Human RelationshipAccording to Martin Buber, the world is twofold because the human attitude toward it is twofold. This twofold attitude is reflected in the formulations IIt and IThou (or IYou). For Buber, they are the two primary relationships between oneself and another. Buber realized that there is a basic difference between relating to a thing or to an object that I observe, and to a person or a Thouwho addresses me and to whose address I respond. This is the difference between the way people usually relate to inanimate things on the one hand and to living persons on the other. As a person is not a what but a who; a person is a who and not a what,the person is a subject and not an object or thing; and since the person is a subject, hence, the person is a self. The human person according to Martin Buber may adopt two attitudes toward another person and the world. a) I-It level of relationshipA person as well as an inanimate thing can be viewed as a thing or in Bubers terminology an It. It can be both non-human objects and other persons, covering everything with which the I comes into contact and uses for its own utility. This is a relation between a user and an object of use or between an observer and an object of observation. In the I-It level of relatedness man is treated not as a subject but as an object or a thing. I-It is a relation of subject-to-object. This is also called a relationship of monologue wherein the other party is considered in the world of things. This is a one-sided relation, within which the I concentrates upon its own purposes and concerns and keeps the It at a distance, where it is measured and studied. In this relatedness, personal commitment does not exist. In many relationships people consider each other as mere objects. Buber further describes the level of I-It relationship to refer to the relation between subjects and objects; for example, between a human being and a pencil. The human being is active, whereas the pencil is passive. This distinction is often referred to in more philosophical language as a subjectobject relation, in which an active subject (in this case, the human being) relates to an inactive object (in this case, the pencil). According to Buber, the subject acts as anI, and the object as an It. The relation between the human being and pencil could thus be described as an IIt relation.b) I-Thou level of relationshipThou may be either human or not human.I-Thou is a relation of subject-to-subject.This is called a relationship of dialogue wherein unity of two beings takes place which is characterized by mutuality and reciprocity. A transition from I-It to I-Thou is possible from an impersonal relationship to a personal one. The I-Thou relationship is not an impersonal one but a personal one in as much as the I recognizes the other as a person. Thouis not an object to be manipulated. In this case, the I recognizes the others needs and rights as a person. Thus, the other is not considered by the I as an object to be used but as a person who has his own uniqueness and needs. Hence, the I respects the Thou because the I treats the Thou not as means to an end but as having value in himself. The I who is always conscious of himself as a who, a subject, and a self relates to another I (Thou) who is also conscious of himself as a who, subject and a self.The relationship becomes personal wherein the other is recognized as a person during the course of the encounter. The other is seen as not as a means but an end. The relationship becomes mutual. c) Eternal ThouA term for God used by Martin Buber in I and Thou in contrast to a human and temporal Thou. God There is a Thou (Absolute Thou) who by his very nature cannot become an It. A man may hate, or curse God, turn away from God when suffering of human destiny becomes unbearable. Yet, no man can reduce God to the status of a thing who no longer addresses him and who becomes one object among others in the world for him. As the eternal Thou, God is the ground of all IThou relations, but is not merely an abstract power. Our relation to God is an extension of the human IThou relation.

Paul Ricoeurs NeighbourPaul Ricoeur made a distinction between the terms: socius and neighbour. The narrative of the Parable of the Good Samaritan reveals the meaning of human existence and different historical and social moments. To highlight this point, following Ricouer, let us quote from the gospel of Luke, The Parable of the Good Samaritan: A certain man went down from Jerusalem to Jericho, and fell among thieves, who also stripped and wounded himand it so happened that a Priest went down the same wayIn like manner a Levite also passed byBut a certain Samaritan being on his journey came near him and seeing him, was moved with compassionwhich of these three men, in your opinion, was a neighbour to him that fell among the thieves? (Lk 10:30-37) The parable is about the interpersonal and social dimension of human existence. The neighbour, as exemplified by the Good Samaritan, implies personal encounters, where one makes himself available for the other, independent from his social roles. In the parable, the act of the Samaritan or his response to the event makes him the image of being a neighbour, for being a person for others. Socius refers to the functional relationships present in highly organized or structured groups or societies. The socius preoccupied with ones social role like the priest and the Levite, does not hear the message of the other human person, so that no face to face encounter takes place between them. To be a neighbourthentranspires when an event takes place without any social mediation. Being a neighbour is irreducible to being a social category. This is because being a social category means having a defined role in the society. The act of making oneself available is beyond any sociological abstraction. The neighbour is the person who goes beyond social mediation. For Ricoeur, being a neighbour lies in the habit of making oneself available. This means that one is not determined by his or her defined role. Why use the Samaritan as an exemplar in interpersonal relations? A Samaritan is considered as an outcast. He is conceived as someone who has no role to portray in the society. He has no social function. These characteristics enable the Samaritan to respond positively to the surprise of the event of the encounter. Thus, the Samaritan rises above it. Ricoeur says, he is the category of the non-category. The Samaritan as a self is a person for others, an actor who rises above social functions. Thus, the Samaritan is one who exemplifies the interpersonal because he acts not in view of any definite role or character. The Samaritan is simply his own person who rises above social mediation. There is nothing wrong, however, in being assigned a definite function in the society. This is because man is a social being. He has roles to play. He has to perform certain functions. This is exemplified by the priest and Levite. Both were unable to respond to the man who was robbed because they were caught up in their roles. They showcase the individual who is entrenched in the social scheme of things, one who is simply doing his job. Our social functions and roles are important in the sense that without them, there can never be order in the society. The wrong thing happens when people are too absorbed in their roles. People are sometimes too caught up in their functions that they no longer see the person for whom a certain task is performed. They dont see the person behind the face. Or worst, they dont even see the face as a person because they reduce human interaction to the functional.

Emmanuel Levinas The FaceThe Jewish thinker, Emmanuel Levinas (1906-1995), centres his entire philosophy on the human face. In Totality and Infinity, 1961, Levinas describes human relationships in great depth and complexity. Levinas' philosophy is directly related to his experiences during World War II. His family died in the Holocaust and as a French citizen and soldier, Levinas himself became a prisoner of war in Germany. While Levinas was forced to perform labour as a prisoner of war, his wife and daughter were kept hidden in a French monastery until his return. This experience, coupled with Heidegger's affiliation to National Socialism during the war, clearly and understandably led to a profound crisis in Levinas' enthusiasm for Heidegger. The following comments will help illuminate what Levinas means by the face of the Other:

a) Other (sometimes capitalized, sometimes not) usually translates the French word autrui, which means the other person, someone else (i.e., other than oneself). It is thus the personal other, the other person, whoever he/she is, that each of us encounters directly or experiences the traces of every day. Of course, we encounter a multiplicity of others, but Levinas more often uses the singular other to emphasize that we encounter others one at a time, face to face.

b) By face Levinas means the human face(or in French, visage), but not thought of or experienced as a physical or aesthetic object. Rather, the first, usual, unreflective encounter with the face is as the living presence of another person and, therefore, as something experienced socially and ethically. Living presence, for Levinas, would imply that the other person (as someone genuinely other than myself) is exposed to me and expresses him or herself simply by being there as an undeniable reality that I cannot reduce to images or ideas in my head. This impossibility of capturing the other conceptually or otherwise indicates the others infinity (i.e., irreducibility to a finite [bounded] entity over which I can have power). The other person is, of course, exposed and expressive in other ways than through the literal face (e.g., through speech, gesture, action, and bodily presence generally), but the face is the most exposed, most vulnerable, and most expressive aspect of the others presence.

The first word of the face is the Thou shalt not kill. It is an order. There is a commandment in theappearance of the face, as if a master spoke to me. However, at the same time, the face of the Other isdestitute; it is the poor for whom I can do all and to whom I owe all. (Ethics and Infinity 89)

According to Levinas,"...I am responsible for the Other without waiting for reciprocity, were I to die for it. Reciprocity is his affair. It is I who support all...The I always has one responsibility more than all the others."For Levinas, coming face to face with the Other is an asymmetrical relationship. I am responsible for the Other without knowing that the Other will reciprocate. Whether or not Others reciprocate is their affair not mine. Thus, according to Levinas, I am subject to the Other without knowing how it will come out. In this relationship, Levinas finds the meaning of being human and of being concerned with justice.

Levinas does not limit encounter with the face of the Other to the sighted. The Others face is seen in different ways, through tactile sensations, from a sense of presence, indirectly. Helen Keller, though blind and deaf, for example, through feeling her teachers lips, tongue, mouth, eyes, nose, and vocal cords encountered the command and authority of the Other. This encounter made communication and learning possible. The face, actually the whole person of the Other, puts me under a tremendous obligation. Even without saying a word, encountering another person speaks volumes. The human face comes with a built-in ought. I can recognize or refuse the gaze of the stranger, the widow, the orphan. Reading Levinas on Ethical Responsibility

For Levinas, there can be no doubt that human relation begins at the encounter with the face; this face-to-face relation is the basis for all otherdiscourse in society. He wants philosophy to begin with this relation, and this relation comes with an ethical demand, i.e., before the face of the Otheryou shall not killand in fact, you have to defend the life of the other. As you encounter anothers face, you cannot escape from this ethical command. It is inescapable. You cannot notrespond to the face of the other whom you encounter, and this response always comes with your responsibility for the other. For Levinas, to be responsible is to be responsible for theother. Once in his interview, he says:

Q.:Concretely,howistheresponsibilityfortheothertranslated?

Emmanuel Levinas:The Other concerns me inall his material misery. It is amatter, eventually, of nourishing him, of clothing him. It is exactly thebiblical assertion: Feed thehungry, clothethe naked,give drinkto the thirsty, give shelter to the shelter-less. The material side of man, the material life of the other, concerns me and, in the other, takes on for me an elevated signification and concerns my holiness. Recall in Matthew 25, Jesus You have hunted me, you havepursued me.When have we huntedyou, when havewe pursued you? the virtuous ask Jesus. Reply: when you refused to feed thepoor, when youhunted down thepoor, when youwereindifferent to him! As if, with regard to the other, Ihad responsibility starting from eating and drinking. And as if the other whom I hunted were equivalent to a hunted God. This holiness is perhaps but the holi-ness of a social problem. All the problems of eating and drinking, insofar as they concern the other, become sacred. (IB, 52)

Levinas here brings philosophy down from abstract ideas into a concrete experience concerned with the need of the Other. Atthe moment I face the Other, I cannot release myself from this ethical relation. I have to be responsible for the Other at the level of basic material needs. In the act offacing the Other, I cannot hide myself from the Other. I cannot enjoy my life within myself alone because an act of facing here is an openness of the selfto the Other without return to the self. This concrete situation moves the Itobe responsibleforthe Other; theethical relationshipis priorto anysystem ofmoral thought. When Levinas mentions the teaching in the Gospel, Matthew 25, here minds us about the way we treat the Other is the way we treat God. The infinite is revealed through the Other. He always refers to the Jewishproverb:theothersmaterialneedsaremyspiritualneeds.Ethical relation, for him, begins with the response to the Others material needs.To feed the hungry, clothe the naked, give drink to the thirsty, give shelter to the shelter-less, are my responsibilities. Holiness begins with practical morality, and practical morality is essentially based on ethical relation, and this relation cannot be abolished from human relationship.

He says, I have been speaking about that which stands behind practical morality; about the extraordinary relation between a man and his neighbour, a relation that continues to exist even when it is severely damaged. Ofcourse we have the power to relate ourselves to the Other as to an object, to oppress and exploit him; nevertheless the relation to the Other, as a relation ofresponsibility, cannot be totally suppressed, even when it takes the form of politics or warfare. Here it is impossible to free myself by saying, Its not my concern. There is no choice, for itis always and inescapably my concern. (LR, 247)

Responsibility is usually understood in relation to the I and its actions. If I fail to do this job, I have to be responsible for this failure. If the Otherfails, responsibility belongs to the Other and is not my concern. If the Otherdoes something wrong, she or he has to be responsible for that. Responsibility belongs to the subject who acts willingly and intentionally. This form of responsibility is limited to the doer and someone who co-operates in this doing. We can calculate how far this responsibility extends, and how many persons are concerned. For Levinas, however, responsibility is irreducible to any calculation and is not limited toany individual person. In his interview with Mortley, he says: I cannot live in society on the basis ofthis one-to-one responsibility alone. There is not calculation in thisresponsibility: there is no pre-responsible knowledge (Mortley, 1991, p.18). And elsewhere he observes: To be me is always to have one more responsibility (EN, 103)

Responsibility, for Levinas, is not conditioned by any knowledge. Instead, it happens at the moment we encounter the face of the Other. This ethical responsibility is prior to any knowledge of the other; in other words: I have to be responsible for the Other even though I do not know him or her. As Levinas puts it: I understand responsibility as responsibility for the Other, thus as responsibility for what is not my deed, or for what does not even matter to me; or which precisely does matter to me, is met by me as face (EI, 95). Before the Other, we have no choice, and we cannot escape from our responsibility for the Other. To discover in the I such an orientation is to identify the I and morality. The I before another is infinitely responsible (TTO, 353). If the Other is beyond any limit and grasp, then responsibility is limitless. Levinas uses the term infinite responsibility. Before the Other I have no choice, I have to be responsible for the other. To escape from this responsibility, for Levinas, is not possible. He says, To be an I then signifies not to be able to slip away from responsibility (TTO, 353). He talks firmly about this inescapability by mentioning the story of the prophet Jonah in the Bible. Jonah could not escape from his duty to God, and God commanded him to go to Nineveh and warn people there about the divine punishment for their sins. But for Jonah, the people of Nineveh were considered as the other and not his concern. He wanted to deny Gods command. According to Levinas, we cannot be free from responsibility just as Jonah could not escape from responsibility for the other. Jonah could not deny his responsibility for the people of Nineveh even though Jonah wanted to escape from this responsibility. This ethical responsibility is not a reciprocal relationship, where we ask something in return. This asymmetrical relationship imitates Gods mercy on the people of Nineveh. Jonah ought to perform his responsibilitywithout any expectation from them in return. For Levinas, the asymmetry of the ethical relationship is very important for human relationships. It does not imply demanding the Others responsibility for me; my responsibility for the other does not mean the Other will do the same in return. The model is not that of the Czars mother who, according to the story Levinas mentions, says to adying soldier: You mustbe very happy to die for your country. For him, this is a demandfrom the Other. Responsibility is not a demand from the Other. It is an asymmetrical relation, the departure from the I to the other without any return to the I. Levinas is very fond of quoting DostoyevskysThe Brothers Karamazov: We are all responsible for everyone else but I am more responsible than all the others.

In an interview with Richard Kearney, Levinas remarks As Alyosha Karamazov says in The Brothers Karamazov by Dostoyevsky: We are all responsible for everyone else but I am more responsible than all the others. And he does not mean that every I is more responsible than all the Other, for that would be to generalize the law for everyone elseto demand as much from the Other as Ido from myself. This essential asymmetry is the very basis of ethics: not only am I more responsible than the Other but I am even responsible for everyone elses responsibility.(Kearney, 1984: 67)To be responsible for the Other is, for Levinas, essentially to be a substitution for the Other. Being a substitution means: toput myself in the Others place, not to appropriate him or her according to my wishes, but to offer to the other what he or she needs, starting with basic material needs. To be an I is tosubstitute for the Other. To bean I does not begin and end in itself, but departs from the self to the Other without any return into the self. To substitute for the Other is to leave oneselffor the Other. It is to transcend ones egoism. In Otherwise than Being, Levinas says: Responsibility, the signification of which is non-indifference, goes one way, from me to the other. In the saying of responsibility, which is an exposure to an obligation for which no one could replace me, I am unique. Peace with the other is first of all my business (OB, 138-139).

Concerning this substitution, I am unique and no one can replace my responsibility. And this responsibility for the Otherstems from the alterity of the Other. An ethical relation from the I toward theOther is asymmetrical, and no one can take my place to be responsible for the Other. The unique-ness of the I is the uniqueness of being irreplaceable. Myresponsibility forthe Other also has to regard the Other as Other, and the Other is unique. This uniqueness of the Other cannot be reduced to be the same genus. This is the ethical relation of the uniqueness of the I to the uniqueness of the other.

In his interview with Mortley, Levinas says,When I talk about responsibility and obligation, and consequently about the person with whom one is in a relationship through the face, this person does not appear as belonging to an order which can be embraced, or grasped. The Other, in this relationship of responsibility, is, as it were, unique: unique meaning without genre. In this sense he is absolutely Other, not only in relation to me; he is alone as if he were the only one of significance at that moment. The essence of responsibility lies in the uniqueness of the person for whom you are responsible. (Mortley 1991: 16)

References:

Alimajen,Domingo Rafael A. Jr. WE: "Nosology of Communion". Jaro, Iloilo City: St. Vincent Ferrer Seminary Publications, 2009.Babor, Eddie R. The Human Person: Not Real, But Existing, Second Edition. Philippines: C & E Publishing, Inc. 2007.Bunnin, Blackwell Dictionary of PhilosophyHinacay, Marionito L. and Maria Belen S.E. Hinacay. The Human Person, 2006 Maiden Edition. Philippines: Vitasophia Book Center, 2006.http://gatewaytojesus.comhttp://www.preservearticles.comJohnson, Patricia Altenbernd.On Heidegger. California: Wadsworth Thomson Learning, 2000.McGrath,Alister E. Christian Theology: An Introduction. United Kingdom: Blackwell Publishing Ltd., 2011.Tangyin, Kajornpat. Reading Levinas on Ethical Responsibility. http://www.academia.eduTubo, Dennis Villanueva. Philosophy of Man: Existential- Phenomenological Approach, Revised Edition. Philippines: National Bookstore, 2006.Young, Bruce: Emmanuel Levinas and the face of the Other. http://english.byu.edu/faculty/youngb/levinas/face.pdf

8