Burke - Review of Vergangene Zukunft by R. Koselleck

download Burke - Review of Vergangene Zukunft by R. Koselleck

of 2

Transcript of Burke - Review of Vergangene Zukunft by R. Koselleck

  • 7/23/2019 Burke - Review of Vergangene Zukunft by R. Koselleck

    1/2

    Book Reviews

    Futures Past: o

    th

    Semantics ofHistoricalTime, R. Koselleck, trans. Keith Tribe, Studies

    in Contemporary German Social Thought (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1985),

    xxvi + 330 pp., H.C. 28.75.

    Reinhart Koselleck is one of the leading intellectual historians in Europe today, yet he

    remains little known in the English-speaking world. Like the scholars of his favourite

    period, the Enlightenment, he may be described as a philosophical historian. Not only in

    the sense that he has spent much of his time working on the history of ideas or more

    exactly the History of Concepts

    (Begriffsgeschichte),

    and especially on the collective six-

    volume work

    Geschichtliche Grundbegriffe.

    Koselleck is also a philosophical historian in

    the sense of a historian who takes philosophy seriously, whose work is indeed

    impregnated by philosophy, notably that of Martin Heidegger and his follower Hans-

    Georg Gadamer. Like his fellow-student at Heidelberg, Hans Robert Jauss, Koselleck has

    taken Heideggers idea of a horizon of expectation

    (Erw artungshorizont)

    and made it the

    basis for his empirical work. Implicit in the

    Grundbegriff

    this notion is made explicit in

    the volume under review, fourteen essays of the 1960s and 1970s the majority of which

    deal with the changing relationship between past and future in European historical

    thought.

    The essays overlap, interweave and echo one another to such an extent that they can be

    discussed together. Their range is wide-from classical Athens to the Third Reich-but

    they focus on one period, the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries, which

    Koselleck knows best and which he sees as a decisive turning-point (Sartelzeit). They also

    concentrate on one region, Germany (especially Prussia), from Frederick the Great to

    Lorenz von Stein; Koselleck is in fact the author of a large and important monograph on

    the political and social history of Prussia in the early nineteenth century. Most of the

    examples discussed in detail in this volume are German, including relatively minor figures

    such as J.C. Chladenius or J.W. von Archenholtz (Koselleck has curiously little to say

    about Ranke).

    The central argument, however, deals with the West in general. It is essentially that a

    major shift in perceptions of the past and future alike took place after the French

    Revolution. There was an inversion in the horizon of expectations. The end of the world

    appeared to recede, and prophecy declined, to be replaced by political prognosis and a

    sense of living in a new age, indeed the new age, Modernity (Neuzeit). The examples of the

    past no longer seemed relevant; the future was coming to seem more open, though also

    subject to control and planning.

    These profound changes were registered by significant shifts in the meaning of a

    number of concepts. Revolution, for example, a term which had originally implied an

    analogy between the world of history and the world of nature (with events moving in

    cycles like the stars and perhaps under their influence), was now associated with the sense

    of an unknown future. The term

    Histoire

    was replaced by

    Geschi cht e,

    the plural form

    helping to indicate what Koselleck calls the convergence between the process of events

    and their apprehension in consciousness. Written history was seen to depend on a

    selection made from a particular point of view

    (Sehepunkt),

    while events themselves, past

    and future, came to be seen as constructible (verfiigbar). t will be noted that Koselleck,

    like Foucault, sees the years around 1800 as a kind of

    coupure epi stemologique

    in Western

    thought, but also that he argues his case, in his chosen field, with considerably more rigour

    than Foucault d&l.

    Kosellecks essays do not make easy reading. He has a gift for the essay form, as he has

    for the selection of telling examples, quotations and anecdotes. He expresses himself

    lucidly, economically and elegantly. The elegance, however, has evaporated in the

    translation, which is not infrequently clumsy and infelicitous (particularly unfortunate is

    the essay title On the Disposability of History, which may well suggest to the reader that

    the place of the past is in the wastepaper basket). In any case, readers in the English-

  • 7/23/2019 Burke - Review of Vergangene Zukunft by R. Koselleck

    2/2

    ook Revi ew s

    745

    speaking world are likely to have difficulties when they encounter a conceptual universe,

    which is still at least half-alien. Kosellecks own Grundbegrzyfe, such as planes of

    historicity, space of experience and so on, are not all naturahsed in English.

    The real problem

    however, lies in rebus. The essays are difficult because they tackle a

    difficult subject; and that is why they are worth making an effort to read. Fortunately, the

    first two essays are among the most important in the whole collection. The one thing the

    author could have done and probably should have done to make things easier for his

    readers was to turn the essays into a book, eliminating repetitions and expanding passages

    which are difficult because they are elliptical and allusive.

    The important question, however, is whether these essays carry conviction. The

    argument of almost every piece is powerful, if not compelling, and they work on the

    reader more strongly together than any of them can do separately. All the same, I do have

    some reservations, or at any rate some questions. For example, although the author has

    himself written social history, he sometimes discusses major changes in ideas without

    making it clear whose ideas are under consideration. This omission may not be a necessary

    result of the method of

    Begrzffsgeschjchte

    (whose complex relationship to social history is

    analysed in an important essay in this collection), but it is at least a danger associated with

    this semantic approach.

    Again, the concept of the Suttelzeit is not as clear as it may look. At times Koselleck

    places great emphasis on the French Revolution, whether as cause or symptom of other

    changes. It may be the case that in Germany the shifts in perception with which he is

    concerned happened more or less together at that time (or a little earlier, in the age of

    Chladenius and Frederick the Great). Elsewhere in Europe, however, some of them go

    back further, to the Scientific Revolution of the seventeenth century or, in Italy at least, to

    the political calculations of Machiavelli. There is a paradox of which Koselleck is aware

    but which plays perhaps too little part in his discussion and that is that his moderns

    themselves date the beginning of modernity to the years around 1500, to the Renaissance

    and the Reformation. There are times, as in the essay on the dissolution of the Ciceronian

    topos histori a mag~st a vi tae, when the author seems to view European thought before

    1789 as that great student of topoi E.R. Curtius regarded the Middle Ages, as a more or

    less static intellectual

    anci en r.kgime.

    With the consequent peri of failing to notice that the

    same topos is different when its intellectual and social context changes. Among the

    dangers inherent in the method of Begriffsgeschichte is hat of failing to notice that new

    wine is sometimes poured into old bottles as well as the other way round.

    Emmanuel College Cambridge

    Peter Burke

    Ihe Emergence of Probability: A Philosophical Study of Early Ideas About Probability

    Induction and Statistical Inference

    Ian Hacking (Cambridge University Press,

    1985) 203 pp., P.B. E6.95.

    Hackings book, when first published in the mid-1970s tokened a new

    rapprochement

    between Anglo-Saxon anafytical philosophy and the history of ideas. Analytical

    philosophy with its positivist canon and cartographical approach to language has

    traditionally been somewhat dismissive of the history of ideas as a properly philosophical

    activity.

    Hacking brings to the study of the historical development of the concepts

    o prob bility

    and inductive inference a refined knowledge of contemporary philosophic concerns with

    these areas. However the major task he sets hims lf in this book is a historical one. How,

    he asks, was it possible that such a fundamental concept as probability could emerge so

    suddenly in European thought. Before 1660 and the deliberations of Pascal and the

    Logicians of Port Royal there was, he insists, no coherent concept of probability either