Brittain, C. - Review of Bailey

5
 The Scepticism of Sextus Sextus Emp iricus and Pyrrhonea n Scepticism by A. Bailey Review by: Charles Brittain The Classical Review, New Series, Vol. 53, No. 2 (Oct., 2003), pp. 326-328 Published by: Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Classical Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3662119  . Accessed: 24/01/2013 11:51 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at  . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp  . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].  . Cambridge University Press and The Classical Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Classical Review. http://www.jstor.org

description

Review of Bailey

Transcript of Brittain, C. - Review of Bailey

  • The Scepticism of SextusSextus Empiricus and Pyrrhonean Scepticism by A. BaileyReview by: Charles BrittainThe Classical Review, New Series, Vol. 53, No. 2 (Oct., 2003), pp. 326-328Published by: Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Classical AssociationStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3662119 .Accessed: 24/01/2013 11:51

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    Cambridge University Press and The Classical Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserveand extend access to The Classical Review.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded on Thu, 24 Jan 2013 11:51:57 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

  • THE CLASSICAL REVIEW THE CLASSICAL REVIEW

    a new type of comedy called Maeson (but see the Latin original: Maeson persona comica appellatur . . ., dici ab inventore eius Maesone comoedo, ut ait Aristophanes grammaticus). On p. 325, she seriously misunderstands Sopatros' characterization of the style of Aelius Aristides: Sopatros says that Aristides 'gives more to thinking than to wording' (rrjs AEeEcoW rr7TAova MSlovs t-r voEdv), but for M.-R. this means that Sopatros 'betont dessen Konzentration auf den Stil'-which is quite the opposite of what Sopatros says. On p. 491 she wrongly paraphrases the word avaTrrvets (used in Procl. In Tim. I p. 129.19) as 'in die Form des Mythos gekleidete Darlegung', whereas it clearly means 'explanation'.

    Typographical errors are too frequent to be enumerated here in detail; in most cases they will not hamper the reader's understanding, but they indicate hasty revision and proof-reading, as do some infelicitous phrasings; for example, on p. 105, we read that Longinus has '18 Biicher Chronik in 228 Olympiaden zusammengefaBt'; it should be the other way round. On p. 112 M.-R. produces the sentence 'Ein Zusammenhang ... konnte ... zusammenhangen'. At the bottom of p. 149, the sentence should read '... Begebenheit, in der [instead of 'nach welcher'] der Rhetor Diophanes eine rhetorisch stilisierte [instead of 'mit einer . . . stilisierten'] Apologie vorgelesen . . . habe'. On p. 279 she confuses the Alexandrian scholar Lysimachus ('des bereits erwahnten'-but he has not been mentioned before) with Lycophron (who indeed is mentioned on the preceding page). More infelicities of this kind could be added.

    The biggest flaw of the book, however, may be its bulk. As I said, M.-R.'s interpretations are often excellent, providing all the information a reader might wish for; nevertheless the paraphrases of the quoted texts might have been more succinct, insights and results are too often repeated with slight variation, and the overall structure of the book (see above) encourages repetitiveness. Some digressions could be missed without great loss; why, for example, must we get a full history of Palmyra before Longinus' time, almost four pages long (pp. 115-18)? A few months (or perhaps only weeks) of additional work on the structure of this book and more rigorous editing of its contents, shedding, say, 150-200 pages, might have given us the definitive publication on Longinus for a long time to come; the book now published represents only a step-though a major one-in that direction. Georg-August University, Gittingen HEINZ-GUNTHER NESSELRATH

    THE SCEPTICISM OF SEXTUS

    A. BAILEY: Sextus Empiricus and Pyrrhonean Scepticism. Pp. xvi + 302. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2002. Cased. ISBN: 0-19-823852-5. Sextus Empiricus and Pyrrhonean Scepticism sets out to show that Pyrrhonism is a form of global scepticism about rationally justified belief which is consistent and immune to standard self-refutation arguments. Bailey argues that the Pyrrhonist has 'the view that no claim is ever rationally preferable to its contradictory' (p. 9); and that the Pyrrhonist can have this view, and also act in the world, because he has (involuntary) beliefs about his own impressions, but also about the world, which he does not consider to be rationally justified (Chapter 11). This seems a promising variant of a familiar, if controversial, view, and worth further elaboration than it receives.

    The book has three parts: Chapters 1, 6, 10, and 11 sketch B.'s positive view; Chapters 2-5 give a historical outline of ancient scepticism; and Chapters 7-9

    ? The Classical Association, 2003

    a new type of comedy called Maeson (but see the Latin original: Maeson persona comica appellatur . . ., dici ab inventore eius Maesone comoedo, ut ait Aristophanes grammaticus). On p. 325, she seriously misunderstands Sopatros' characterization of the style of Aelius Aristides: Sopatros says that Aristides 'gives more to thinking than to wording' (rrjs AEeEcoW rr7TAova MSlovs t-r voEdv), but for M.-R. this means that Sopatros 'betont dessen Konzentration auf den Stil'-which is quite the opposite of what Sopatros says. On p. 491 she wrongly paraphrases the word avaTrrvets (used in Procl. In Tim. I p. 129.19) as 'in die Form des Mythos gekleidete Darlegung', whereas it clearly means 'explanation'.

    Typographical errors are too frequent to be enumerated here in detail; in most cases they will not hamper the reader's understanding, but they indicate hasty revision and proof-reading, as do some infelicitous phrasings; for example, on p. 105, we read that Longinus has '18 Biicher Chronik in 228 Olympiaden zusammengefaBt'; it should be the other way round. On p. 112 M.-R. produces the sentence 'Ein Zusammenhang ... konnte ... zusammenhangen'. At the bottom of p. 149, the sentence should read '... Begebenheit, in der [instead of 'nach welcher'] der Rhetor Diophanes eine rhetorisch stilisierte [instead of 'mit einer . . . stilisierten'] Apologie vorgelesen . . . habe'. On p. 279 she confuses the Alexandrian scholar Lysimachus ('des bereits erwahnten'-but he has not been mentioned before) with Lycophron (who indeed is mentioned on the preceding page). More infelicities of this kind could be added.

    The biggest flaw of the book, however, may be its bulk. As I said, M.-R.'s interpretations are often excellent, providing all the information a reader might wish for; nevertheless the paraphrases of the quoted texts might have been more succinct, insights and results are too often repeated with slight variation, and the overall structure of the book (see above) encourages repetitiveness. Some digressions could be missed without great loss; why, for example, must we get a full history of Palmyra before Longinus' time, almost four pages long (pp. 115-18)? A few months (or perhaps only weeks) of additional work on the structure of this book and more rigorous editing of its contents, shedding, say, 150-200 pages, might have given us the definitive publication on Longinus for a long time to come; the book now published represents only a step-though a major one-in that direction. Georg-August University, Gittingen HEINZ-GUNTHER NESSELRATH

    THE SCEPTICISM OF SEXTUS

    A. BAILEY: Sextus Empiricus and Pyrrhonean Scepticism. Pp. xvi + 302. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2002. Cased. ISBN: 0-19-823852-5. Sextus Empiricus and Pyrrhonean Scepticism sets out to show that Pyrrhonism is a form of global scepticism about rationally justified belief which is consistent and immune to standard self-refutation arguments. Bailey argues that the Pyrrhonist has 'the view that no claim is ever rationally preferable to its contradictory' (p. 9); and that the Pyrrhonist can have this view, and also act in the world, because he has (involuntary) beliefs about his own impressions, but also about the world, which he does not consider to be rationally justified (Chapter 11). This seems a promising variant of a familiar, if controversial, view, and worth further elaboration than it receives.

    The book has three parts: Chapters 1, 6, 10, and 11 sketch B.'s positive view; Chapters 2-5 give a historical outline of ancient scepticism; and Chapters 7-9

    ? The Classical Association, 2003

    326 326

    This content downloaded on Thu, 24 Jan 2013 11:51:57 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

  • THE CLASSICAL REVIEW

    challenge three dissenting interpretations of Sextus. The whole is completed by a 'select bibliography' (pp. 291-6)-which is too short and dated to be of much use-and a brief index (pp. 297-302).

    The historical section (pp. 21-118) sets out the standard modern view of the evolution of Pyrrhonism, and its relation to Academic scepticism (Chapters 3-4) and medical Empiricism (Chapter 5.3). The exposition is vitiated by errors, its reliance on misleading translations, and a dispiriting lack of generosity to its modern sources. Minor errors include passages such as those on Philo on p. 32 and Dionysius of Aegae on p. 86, the latter presumably relying on the mistaken authority cited in p. 87 n. 44 (cf. Deichgraber, Die Griechische Empirikerschule [Berlin, 1965], p. 336). The superseded Loeb translation by Bury seems to be responsible for several confusions about the meaning of Sextus' Greek (see below on Chapter 7); more depressing is the apparent misreading of an ellipse in Long & Sedley with the result that B.'s Cyrenaics 'suspend judgement about everything' (p. 42) in Plutarch Adv. Col. 1120c (= The Hellenistic Philosophers [Cambridge, 1987] i.440, misconstrued). These flaws are perhaps venial; but it is sad to read, in a section on medical Empiricism which seems to derive almost entirely from the work of Michael Frede, that 'Even if Frede is right to claim ... [P], it seems that . . . [Q]' (p. 91), when Frede argued precisely P & Q ('The Ancient Empiricists', Essays in Ancient Philosophy [Oxford, 1987], pp. 243-60, at pp. 246-50 and 251-7, respectively).

    A more original suggestion is that the Academics' universal suspension of judgement is compatible with holding views about-i.e. assenting to-the (phenomenal) content of their own impressions. B. supports this, without appeal to any relevant evidence, by claiming that the Stoics must have taken assent to mean having a belief about something that 'exists in a way that is independent of anyone's psychological state' (p. 48). But this arbitrary supposition falsely implies that, according to the Stoics, one cannot have beliefs about one's own or others' psychological states (contra Cicero Ac. 2.51-3); and it also contradicts B.'s central argument in Chapter 7.

    The polemical section of the book (pp. 147-255) takes on the views that the Pyrrhonist has no beliefs (Chapter 7), no philosophical beliefs but only ordinary beliefs like everyone else (Chapter 8), and only (rationally justified) beliefs about his own impressions (Chapter 9). Many of the arguments here are, understandably, familiar, but some are new and provocative. First up is the view that the sceptic has no beliefs because the 'appearance statements' to which he assents were not considered to be true or false in antiquity. B.'s principal counter-argument is the fact that the Cyrenaics clearly did think that such statements were susceptible of truth-ascriptions (Chapter 7.4). An interesting supporting argument to the effect that Sextus is also committed to this possibility is flawed by B.'s philological methods. His case depends on two claims: first, plausibly, that such a commitment might be shown by linguistic practices that imply that there are facts about appearances; and secondly, that Sextus has such linguistic practices-because Bury's Loeb translation offers, for example, 'the fact that' to render the Greek hoti, the marker for indirect speech (p. 159).

    Chapter 8 deals with the position that the sceptic has ordinary beliefs. B. rightly reiterates inter alia the objection that Sextus' apparent support for 'ordinary life' is undermined by his use of 'ordinary views' to support one side of a sceptical antithesis (leading to the suspension of judgement about the issue)-for example, on the existence of motion (PH 3.65, discussed at pp. 200-8). But B.'s focus on the philosophically undeveloped variants of the 'ordinary belief' view leads him to miss the difficulties which are most relevant to his own interpretation (see below).

    327

    This content downloaded on Thu, 24 Jan 2013 11:51:57 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

  • THE CLASSICAL REVIEW

    The third polemical chapter launches a battery of arguments against the 'proto-phenomenalist' view of Pyrrhonism. B.'s strongest argument is that Sextus' five modes undermine all claims to self-evidence, and hence also the alleged self-evidence of one's own impressions that would rationally justify the phenomenalist position (Chapter 9.5). This is supported by an argument against the phenomenalists' reliance on induction to underwrite expectations about their own future impressions-though B. rather oddly appeals to Hume's famous argument, as if that warranted Sextus' primitive versions (Chapter 9.4). The chapter is weakened, however, by two feeble attempts to show that phenomenalist interpretations are inconsistent with Sextus' text: first, an overlong and anachronistic appeal to 'our' linguistic intuitions about a claim supporters of this position do not endorse (pp. 221-8); and, secondly, the suggestion that Sextus' use of ad hominem arguments presupposes that he has beliefs about his opponents' minds. If this works against the phenomenalist view, so would citing any doxographical passage, e.g. PH 1.1-3.

    The principal evidence for B.'s positive interpretation is set out in the relatively non-controversial Chapters 6, 10, and 11.2: Sextus allows that the Pyrrhonist is constrained to assent to some impressions, and thus has 'beliefs' (in some sense) which can guide his action. Since Sextus' arguments also rule out rational justification for any beliefs, B. infers that the only consistent interpretation of Pyrrhonism is one that allows it 'constrained' beliefs which are explicitly considered not to be rationally justified. Unfortunately, he does not elaborate on this view: Chapter 11.3 merely reiterates his interpretation of Sextus' anti-rationalist endorsement of 'commemor- ative signs' (cf. Chapters 6.2, 8.2, and 9.4); Chapter 11.4 just notes that it is inconsistent with some of Sextus' characterizations of the Pyrrhonist's appearances (e.g. M 11.8; B. is apparently unaware of the controversy surrounding these non-epistemic locutions); and the concluding section merely reaffirms some old errors about Pyrrhonists-that the Pyrrhonist is not very interested in the discovery of truths (p. 285) and is 'not a philosopher' (p. 288)-which are patently rejected by Sextus in PH 1.1-10.

    Still, B.'s view that the Pyrrhonist accepts (explicitly) rationally unjustified beliefs about 'matters of objective fact'-e.g. that other people exist (p. 282)-as well as about his own impressions, seems promising, because it leaves room to explain how the sceptic can follow his ancestral customs and laws, and benefit from the teaching of crafts (PH 1.23-4). But a fuller explanation of the sceptic's ordinary life, e.g. as an Empiricist doctor, like Sextus, will have to do more than merely assert that the sceptic suspends judgement on whether motion or the gods etc. exist, but non-rationally believes that they do. Most examples of the doctor's 'rationally unjustified' practical beliefs will be the products of his medical training and of following established intellectual procedures in medicine: he will tell people to walk to the temple's healing sanctuary because that has helped others with similar symptoms, in his experience. His 'rationally unjustified' beliefs will therefore look just like anyone else's contextual knowledge; and one might think that the only sense in which they are not rationally justified will be that he does not pretend that they meet contextually irrelevant philosophical criteria.

    An elaboration along these lines would align B. with the more philosophically developed 'ordinary belief' interpretations he failed to discuss, e.g. Frede's ('The Skeptic's two kinds of assent and the possibility of knowledge', op. cit., pp. 201-22). At any rate, an elaboration is needed to supplement the borrowed history and lengthy polemic of this book.

    328

    Cornell University CHARLES BRITTAIN

    This content downloaded on Thu, 24 Jan 2013 11:51:57 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    Article Contentsp.326p.327p.328

    Issue Table of ContentsThe Classical Review, New Series, Vol. 53, No. 2 (Oct., 2003), pp. i-xii+275-530Volume Information [pp.517-529]Front Matter [pp.i-xii]Editorial [pp.ix-xi]ReviewsPolitics in the "Iliad" [pp.275-276]Revaluing the Epic Cycle [pp.276-278]Solon's Political Poems [pp.278-279]What Is Iambic? [pp.279-281]Tragic Voices [pp.281-282]Tragic Space [pp.282-284]Sophoclean Self-Knowledge [pp.284-285]Hippolytus [pp.285-286]Euripides' "Cretans" [pp.287-288]Satyr Plays [pp.288-290]Plutus [pp.290-291]Aristophanic Metatheatre [pp.292-293]Gorgias [pp.293-295]Herodotus VI [pp.295-296]Plato's "Alcibiades" [pp.296-298]A More Socratic "Meno" [pp.299-301]Demosthenes' "Fourth Philippic" [pp.301-302]Didymus the Brazen-Bowelled [pp.303-304]The "Poetics" [pp.304-305]Aristotle on Bodies and Motion [pp.305-307]Commentaries on the "Metaphysics" [pp.307-308]Euhemerus [pp.309-311]Coi Sacra Philitae [pp.311-312]Hellenistic Poetry and Propaganda [pp.312-313]Epistolary Functions [pp.313-314]Philo the Academic [pp.314-316]Strabo VII-IX [pp.316-318]Appian on Africa [pp.318-319]Appian on the Mithridatic War [pp.319-321]Plutarch's Moralia [pp.321-323]Longinus the Platonist [pp.323-326]The Scepticism of Sextus [pp.326-328]A Cambridge View of the Second Sophistic [pp.329-331]Ancient Technical Literature [pp.331-334]Diocles of Carystus [pp.334-337]A Neglected Work of Galen [pp.337-338]Soranos' Gynaecology [pp.338-339]A Medical Miscellany [pp.339-340]On the Interpretation of Dreams (Etc.) [pp.341-344]Cicero's Letters Completed [pp.344-346]Cicero and the Written Word [pp.346-347]De Consolatione [pp.347-348]Philosophia Togata [pp.349-350]Defining Didactic [pp.350-352]Rethinking Reality [pp.352-354]Catullan Concatenations [pp.354-355]Poets as Literary Historians [pp.355-357]History and the Poets [pp.357-358]Influences on the "Georgics" [pp.359-360]Translating the "ODES" [pp.360-361]Livian Portraits [pp.361-363]Propertius on Vertumnus and Actium [pp.363-365]An Ovidian Vade Mecum [pp.365-367]De Clementia [pp.367-369]The New Loeb of Seneca's Tragedies [pp.369-370]Bonum Vita Iucundius Ipsa [pp.370-372]Petronius [pp.372-374]Institutio Oratoria [pp.374-376]Martial VII [pp.376-377]Suetonius on the Flavians [pp.378-379]Two Books of Apuleius (I) [pp.379-381]Two Books of Apuleius (II) [pp.381-383]Fishy? [pp.383-384]Ausonius' Epigrams [pp.384-385]Terentianus Maurus [pp.385-388]Sermonis Pompa Romani [pp.388-389]Historiography of the Late Empire [pp.389-391]Ennodius [pp.391-394]A Byzantine Chronicle in Latin [pp.394-395]A Long History of Time [pp.396-397]More Equal than Others? [pp.397-400]Ostracism [pp.400-402]Antidemocratic Ideology in Athens [pp.402-403]Greek Cavalry [pp.403-405]What Was It to Be Greek? [pp.405-407]Hellenistic Egypt [pp.407-409]Italian State Formation [pp.409-411]Umbria [pp.411-412]The Roads of Italy [pp.412-414]Cinnanum Tempus [pp.414-415]The Army and Roman Society [pp.416-417]Augustus Re-Examined [pp.417-419]Politics at Pompeii [pp.419-421]Women and the Law [pp.421-423]Women, Wealth, and Power [pp.423-424]The Julian Marriage Laws [pp.425-426]Emperor Worship [pp.426-428]The Synagogue at Ostia [pp.428-429]Military Religion in the East [pp.429-431]The Army in Syria [pp.431-433]Palmyra [pp.433-435]Cappadocia [pp.435-436]Iberian Sanctuaries [pp.436-437]The Libyans [pp.437-438]Mobility in Gaul [pp.439-440]The Christianization of the Aristocracy [pp.440-442]The Late Antique Economy [pp.442-444]Towns in Late Antiquity [pp.444-446]A Century of Minoan Archaeology [pp.446-448]Power in Minoan Crete [pp.448-449]Athenian Archaeology [pp.449-450]Women in Athenian Art [pp.450-452]Landscape in Greek Art [pp.452-454]Eretrian Epigraphy and Early Hellenistic History [pp.454-458]Samnite Epigraphy [pp.458-460]The Metropolis in the Mediterranean [pp.460-462]Roman Tomb Decorations [pp.462-463]A Colloquium on Ancient Music [pp.463-464]Athletics [pp.464-465]Athletic Vocabulary in Aristophanes [pp.465-467]Eros in the Gymnasium [pp.467-468]Amor Graecus. Or Romanus? [pp.468-470]Past Times [pp.470-472]Commenting on Commentaries [pp.472-474]Sulpicia through the Ages [pp.474-476]The Aqueduct Hunters [pp.476-478]Classics in America [pp.478-479]The Life of Mommsen [pp.479-481]The Boston Fake Goddess? [pp.481-482]

    Noticesuntitled [pp.483-484]untitled [pp.484-485]untitled [pp.485-486]untitled [p.486]untitled [pp.486-487]untitled [pp.487-488]untitled [p.488]untitled [p.489]untitled [pp.489-490]untitled [p.490]untitled [pp.490-491]untitled [pp.491-492]untitled [p.492]untitled [pp.492-494]untitled [p.494]untitled [pp.494-495]untitled [p.495]untitled [pp.495-496]untitled [p.496]untitled [p.497]untitled [pp.497-498]untitled [p.498]untitled [pp.498-499]untitled [pp.499-500]

    Books Received [pp.501-515]Back Matter [pp.530-530]