Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

download Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

of 58

Transcript of Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    1/58

    Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture: An Evolutionary

    Perspective on the Design of Organizations and their Evolvability1

    SENDIL K ETHIRAJ

    University of Michigan Business School701 Tappan, D5203

    University of Michigan, Ann Arbor MI 48109

    Ph. 734-764 1230Fax. 734-936 8716

    Email: [email protected]

    DANIEL LEVINTHAL

    The Wharton School of Business

    3620 Locust Walk, Suite 2000University of Pennsylvania, Philadelphia PA 19104

    Ph. 215-898 6826Fax. 215-898 0401

    Email: [email protected]

    October 12, 2004

    1We thank Reed Nelson, three anonymous referees, and seminar participants at Stanford University, Northwestern

    University, New York University, University of Pennsylvania, University of Michigan, the University of Michigan-

    Santa Fe Institute Workshop, and The Lake Arrowhead Conference on Computational Modeling in the Social

    Sciences for useful comments and suggestions. Errors and omissions remain our own.

    mailto:[email protected]:[email protected]:[email protected]:[email protected]:[email protected]:[email protected]
  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    2/58

    2

    Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture: An Evolutionary

    Perspective on the Design of Organizations and their Evolvability

    Abstract

    The problem of designing, managing, and coordinating the efforts of different parts of complexorganizations is central to the management and organizations literature. A central element, in

    turn, of Simons (1962) argument, which provides a foundation for understanding complex

    organizations, is that the fundamental properties of complex systems are hierarchy and near-decomposability. These dual properties are argued to enhance the evolvability of such systems.

    A critical question, however, is whether boundedly rational managers will be able to identify and

    uncover some true, latent structure of hierarchy and decomposability. This question is intimatelyrelated to broader issues of concern to organization theory including the usefulness and value of

    design efforts and the implications of organizational change processes. In an effort to unite

    Simons ideas about complexity with mainstream organization theory, we address three researchquestions: (1) how does the architecture or structure of complexity affect the feasibility and

    usefulness of boundedly rational design efforts; (2) do efforts to adapt in the space oforganizational forms complicate or complement the effectiveness of first-order change efforts;

    (3) to what extent does the rate of environmental change nullify the usefulness of design efforts.We employ a computational model of organizational adaptation to examine these questions. Our

    results, in identifying the boundary conditions around successful design efforts, suggest that the

    underlying architecture of complexity of organizations, particularly the presence of hierarchy, isa critical determinant of the feasibility and effectiveness of design efforts. We also find that

    design efforts are generally complementary to efforts at local performance improvement and

    identify specific contingencies that determine that extent of complementarity. We discuss theimplications of our findings for organization theory and design and also the burgeoning literature

    on modularity in products and organizations.

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    3/58

    3

    1. Introduction

    Simons (1962) the Architecture of Complexity provides the foundation for viewing

    organizations, as well as other systems such as products or technologies, as complex adaptive

    systems (Cohen and Axelrod, 1999). A central element of Simons argument is that the

    fundamental features of complex systems are hierarchy, the fact that some decisions or structures

    provide constraints on lower-level decisions or structures, and near-decomposability, the fact that

    patterns of interactions among elements of a system are not diffuse but will tend to be tightly

    clustered into nearly isolated sub-sets of interactions. These dual properties of hierarchy and

    near-decomposability are argued to enhance the evolvability of such systems. While hierarchy

    and near-decomposability may be desirable attributes of an adaptive entity, how can we presume

    that boundedly-rational managers will be able to identify and uncover some true, latent structure

    of hierarchy and near-decomposability? This is a particularly important question for the growing

    literature on the power of modular organizational and product architectures (Baldwin and Clark,

    2000; Sanchez and Mahoney, 1996) that has offered considerable insight regarding the power of

    modular designs but has left largely unaddressed the question of the feasibility of boundedly

    rational actors identifying more or less appropriate modular architectures.

    The essential tension between designing complex systems that are hierarchical and

    nearly-decomposable and the limits to rationality of human agents is captured in the following

    passage from Simon (1962):

    The fact, then, that many complex systems have a nearly decomposable, hierarchic

    structure is a major facilitating factor enabling us to understand, to describe, and even tosee such systems and their parts. Or perhaps the proposition should be put the other way

    round. If there are important systems in the world that are complex without being

    hierarchic, they may to a considerable extent escape our observation and ourunderstanding. Analysis of their behavior would involve such detailed knowledge and

    calculation of the interactions of their elementary parts that it would be beyond our

    capacities of memory or computation. I shall not try to settle which is chicken and whichis egg: whether we are able to understand the world because it is hierarchic, or whether it

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    4/58

    4

    appears hierarchic because those aspects of it which are not elude our understanding and

    observation. I have already given some reasons for supposing that the former is at leasthalf the truth that evolving complexity would tend to be hierarchic but it may not be

    the whole truth (Simon, 1962: 477-478, Emphases added)

    In the quote above, Simon raises the puzzle about the direction of causality between

    bounded rationality and complexity. Does bounded rationality allow us to perceive and analyze

    only hierarchical systems, or is it that because complex systems are hierarchical that we are able

    to observe and analyze them. The essential question remains: to what extent is the architecture of

    complexity (i.e., hierarchy and decomposability) the ultimate arbiter of feasible design efforts.

    This question is intimately related to a central research agenda in organization theory

    concerning the design of organization forms. Two contrasting themes in organization theory

    provide the starting point for thinking about the feasibility and value of adaptation in the space of

    organization forms themselves. Contingency arguments implicitly assume that high-level actors

    within an organization are able to identify and comprehend the demands imposed by their current

    environment and are able to design the appropriate organizational architecture to respond to

    those demands. The role of the manager is, therefore, to respond to the changing environment by

    continuously adapting to the contingencies that confront the organization (Astley and Van de Ven,

    1983). The research in this tradition, however, has devoted little attention to the feasibility and

    efficacy of adaptation in the space of organizational forms, focusing instead on the fit between

    environmental contingencies and organizational forms and the nature of lower-order adaptation

    or flexibility that different organizational forms make possible.

    Population ecologists (Hannan and Freeman, 1977), in contrast, argue quite explicitly

    about the difficulty of identifying what form may seem most apt for a particular environment or

    niche and, furthermore, make salient the challenges of shifting from one form to another. This

    perspective highlights the limits to the degree of strategic choice and the capacity of organization

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    5/58

    5

    structures to adapt to different niches (Aldrich, 1979). Moreover, even if organizations are able to

    engage in adaptation in the space of organizational forms, if the rate of environmental change is

    faster than the rate at which organizations can adapt their organizational forms, then such

    adaptation efforts are likely to be fruitless (Hannan and Freeman, 1984).

    The roots of the contrasting positions of the contingency and the ecological views are

    embedded in both implicit and explicit assumptions about individual behavior underlying

    adaptive efforts in the space of organization forms and the complexity of the challenge

    represented by such efforts. As contingency theories of fit between environmental contingencies

    and organization design features depend crucially on the ability of managers to discover and

    achieve such a fit, it is important to examine whether managers, viewed more realistically as

    boundedly rational, can indeed engage in effective adaptation in the space of organization

    forms to achieve such a fit with the environment. At the same time, if the relative futility of

    managerial action or the benefits of inertia really depends on the rate of change in the

    environment, then it is also useful to examine the relationship between the rate of environmental

    change and the effectiveness of efforts at adaptation.

    A related theme, but treated largely as a distinct line of work, is the examination of first-

    and second-order change processes (Argyris and Schn, 1978; Bartunek, 1984; Miner and

    Mezias, 1996; Tushman and Romanelli, 1985). First-order change is viewed as incremental, local

    adaptation within a given structure (e.g., changes in pricing policies, product launches or

    withdrawals, changes in investments in R&D or advertising) involving the working out of

    specific choices within a given organizational structure. In contrast, second-order change

    represents change in the underlying structure itself (e.g., change from a unitary to M-form

    structure). Related to the prior questions of whether change in the space of organizational forms

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    6/58

    6

    is feasible and useful and how it is influenced by environmental change, are questions related to

    the interrelationship between first and second-order change processes.

    The interrelationship between first-order and second-order adaptation is far from

    straightforward. On the one hand, since first-order adaptation is likely to yield diminishing

    returns as the space of possibilities within an existing organizational architecture is exhausted, a

    major shift in the organizational form (via second-order adaptation) may enhance the

    effectiveness of first-order adaptation by creating new configurations for experimentation

    (Levinthal, 1997), much as breakthrough innovations set the stage for subsequent refinements

    (Nelson and Winter, 1982). Empirical research on learning curves (Argote , et al., 1990) and

    quality improvement efforts support this possibility. On the other hand, aggressive second-order

    adaptation can undo the learning and first-order adaptations of the past, creating conditions akin

    to the liability of newness (Amburgey, et al., 1993). The ambiguity of predictions suggests that it

    is useful to examine the impact of second-order adaptation on the efficacy of first-order

    adaptation and the circumstances under which they are complementary or conflicting.

    We wish to connect Simon the system designer who exposes the power of hierarchical

    and nearly-decomposable systems with Simon the forceful proponent for the notion of bounded

    rationality. Uniting Simons contrasting ideas about bounded rationality and complex system

    design, we seek to address three questions that speak to the literature on organization design and

    change processes: (1) how does the architecture or structure of complexity affect the feasibility

    and usefulness of boundedly rational design efforts; (2) do efforts to adapt in the space of

    organizational forms complicate or complement the effectiveness of first-order change efforts;

    (3) to what extent does the rate of environmental change nullify the usefulness of design efforts.

    In the process of addressing these questions, we hope to delineate at least a skeleton of a micro-

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    7/58

    7

    foundation for some of the important macro questions regarding the design and evolution of

    organizational forms.

    We examine these questions in the context of a computational model of organizational

    adaptation. Such a methodological approach has the virtue that it allows us to examine the

    complex interaction among search processes at different levels of analysis (the space of

    alternative structures and the set of alternative actions) and, in a controlled manner, to consider

    how these processes are affected by different environmental settings and varying degrees of

    environmental change. As a model, by necessity, it comprises a stylized representation of actual

    processes of organizational adaptation. We build closely on prior work on models of

    organizational adaptation (Lant and Mezias, 1990; Levinthal, 1997) and specify a process of

    adaptive search for organizational form that roughly parallels these existing specifications of

    local search processes. Our characterization of an organizational form focuses on the

    segmentation or departmentalization of activity and the allocation of specific functions to a

    particular organizational subunit (c.f., Marengo, et al., 2000; Rivkin and Siggelkow, 2003). This

    is not to suggest that there are not other important facets of an organizations form one might

    want to consider, including the informal pattern of interaction among actors or some notion of

    values or organizational culture. However, as Scott (1998: 26) suggests, a distinctive feature of

    organizations are their relatively formalized social structures and these features of structure

    upon which we do focus comprise the central elements that are manipulated in the process of

    restructuring (Kelly and Amburgey, 1991).

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    8/58

    8

    2. Complex organizations and their environments

    2.1. Complex organizations and the design problem

    Building on the work of Simon (1962: 468) and Perrow (1972), complex organizational

    systems can be characterized as consisting of a large number of elements that interact in a non-

    simple2

    way. The complexity that stems from a large number of elements interacting in non-

    trivial ways is two-fold. First, the large number of elements creates difficulty in comprehending

    the structure that binds them. Second, even if one is able to uncover and comprehend the

    structure that binds the elements, anticipating the effects of the interactions on system behavior

    and performance is non-trivial (Cohen and Axelrod, 1999; Kauffman, 1993). The complexity

    increases as the system gets larger since designers need to first discover which elements interact

    with which others and then discover the nature of the interaction relationship (see Perrow, 1999

    Chapter 3 for an extensive discussion of the distinguishing aspects of complex systems). The

    following quote describing the complexity of Xeroxs photocopiers (Adler and Borys, 1996)

    vividly portrays the difficulty inherent in comprehending and intervening in complex structures:

    During the 1970s, Xerox photocopiers grew vastly more sophisticated in theirfunctionality. As a result, even simple tasks such as copying, loading paper, and

    resupplying ink became more complex, and recovery from routine problems such as

    paper jams became more difficult. It became increasingly common for users to walkaway from the machine rather than waste time trying to work out how to clear a paper

    jam or replace the ink supply. This resulted in unnecessary downtime and expensive

    service calls (Adler and Borys, 1996: 68).

    Similarly, Chandlers (1962) description of Du Ponts growing pains highlights the

    challenges of complexity in an organizational setting:

    The essential difficulty was that diversification greatly increased the demands on thecompanys administrative offices. Now the different departmental headquarters had to

    2For instance, predicting system behavior is relatively easy if the interactions between the elements are linear. On

    the other hand, if elements interact such that the relationship within and between then is non-linear, i.e., positive

    over some range and negative or unrelated over other ranges, then predicting system performance becomes a

    difficult problem.

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    9/58

    9

    coordinate, appraise, and plan policies and procedures for plants, or sales offices, or

    purchasing agents, or technical laboratories in a number of quite differentindustriesCoordination became more complicated because different products called for

    different types of standards, procedures, and policiesAppraisal of departments

    performing in diverse fields became exceedingly complex. Interdepartmental

    coordination grew comparably more troublesome. The manufacturing personnel and themarketers tended to lose contact with each other and so failed to work out product

    improvements and modifications to meet changing demands and competitive

    developments(Chandler, 1962: 91).

    The problem of adaptive change in such settings is made even more salient, particularly if we

    assume managers are boundedly rational, since any adaptive attempt is based on guesses about

    the nature of interactions and interaction relationships among organizational choices and

    decisions.

    The design of complex organizations, in its simplest form, invokes two important

    principles: reductionism, the breaking up of a complex whole into simpler units, and division of

    labor, grouping of tasks or units based on similarity in function. The two principles serve to

    economize on the cognitive demands placed on the designer (Miller, 1956) and also minimize

    redundancies in task performance. This idea has persisted in and remained central to the ideas of

    more recent organization theorists, albeit under various labels such as nearly decomposable

    systems (Simon, 1962), loosely-coupled systems (Weick, 1976), or pooled, sequential, and

    reciprocal interdependence (Thompson, 1967).

    Among the many coordination benefits of specialization and division of labor, one of the

    most important ones from an adaptive standpoint is the potential for relatively autonomous

    adaptation within the specialized units or departments. This allows for localized adaptation

    within problematic parts of the organization, while simultaneously buffering the unaffected parts

    (Thompson, 1967) or engaging in parallel and simultaneous adaptive attempts in different

    departmental units (see Weick, 1976: 6-9 for seven adaptive benefits of loose coupling).

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    10/58

    10

    A second basic principle for dealing with complexity is the notion of hierarchy.

    Specialization or division of labor can help eliminate redundancies and duplication of effort.

    However, the decisions or activities that are compartmentalized still may need to be coordinated.

    Among other roles, hierarchy serves the important function of the temporal ordering of activities

    and helps eliminate endless cycling in their performance. Using the fable of the two

    watchmakers, Simon (1962) suggests that complex systems that resemble hierarchies tend to

    evolve faster and toward a stable, self-reproducing form as compared with non-hierarchic

    systems. The property of hierarchy is argued to be found not by chance, but favored by

    evolutionary selection processes.

    The notion of hierarchy is often used interchangeably with organizational fiat

    (Williamson, 1975) or authority (see Rivkin and Siggelkow, 2003 for an implementation of

    hierarchy as authority using a modeling structure similar to ours). Rather, in this paper, the

    notion of hierarchy is used in the sense of nested hierarchies (Baum and Singh, 1994) where

    there is a precedence ordering of tasks or activities in the organization. In the context of

    organization design, the line of hierarchy denotes the flow of information, or constraints, from

    the immediately higher department or unit. Similarly, in an organizational context, Simons

    (1957) notion of decision premises has the property of a nested set of constraints on

    organizational decision-making. The important function of hierarchy is not only to resolve

    conflicts between sub-systems (Thompson, 1967: 60), but also to facilitate learning through trial

    and error by allowing systematic and orderly local search and exploration. Hierarchy enables the

    recognition of progress towards ones goals and the evolution of a system through several

    intermediate stable configurations (Perrow, 1972: 44-52). In contrast, non-hierarchic systems,

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    11/58

    11

    which display no particular order in their configuration, make local search and trial and error

    learning much more difficult to accomplish.

    Interestingly, Xeroxs response (Adler and Borys, 1996) to the growing complexity of its

    copiers and that of Du Pont to its diversification (Chandler, 1962) was to redesign their product

    and organization, respectively, conforming to the twin principles of decomposability and

    hierarchy:

    Through its physical structure and the displays it offered, the machine provided a

    succession of informative views of the copiers functioning and of the users interaction

    with it at various stages of the copying experience. As the views unfolded, they helpedusers form mental models of the machines subsystems and of the experience of

    interacting with those subsystems. The views included step-by-step presentations ofmachine subsystems, their functions, and the corresponding task sequences. The views

    supported copying tasks by talking the users through them neither concealinginformation nor overloading users with incomprehensible or unrelated information. The

    interiors, for example, were designed to express various layers and degrees of interaction

    to users and service people. The user-accessible components of the interiors (such aspaper-loading, jam clearing, and simple maintenance) were placed in the foreground of

    the visual field, and the technician-accessible components of the interior (for more

    complex maintenance and repairs) were placed in receding layers in the background(Adler and Borys, 1996: 68-69).

    No member of the Executive Committee should have direct individual authority or

    responsibility which he would have if he was in charge of one or more functional

    activities of the CompanyFor example, our plan provides that one member of theExecutive Committee, who may be best fitted by experience for his duty, will coordinate

    the sales function by holding regular meetings with appropriate representatives of the five

    Industrial DepartmentsAccording to this plan, the head of each Industrial Departmentwill have full authority and responsibility for the operation of his industry, subject only to

    the authority of the Executive Committee as a whole. He will have under him men who

    will exercise all the line functions necessary for a complete industry, including routineand special purchasing, manufacture, sales, minor construction(Chandler, 1962: 107)

    The description of the copier redesign effort and the restructuring of Du Pont invoke the

    twin principles of complex system architecture advocated by Simon (1962): decomposability and

    hierarchy. The design of the copier into subsystems and concealing irrelevant information within

    modules or subsystems (Baldwin and Clark, 2000) corresponds to near decomposability or the

    loose-coupling of structural elements. Similarly, identifying task sequences and separating the

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    12/58

    12

    various layers and degrees of interaction is consistent with the principle of hierarchy. By the

    same token, the creation of multiple, autonomous divisions in Du Pont corresponds to the

    principle of decomposability, i.e., group activities that are strongly interdependent, whereas the

    members of the Executive Committee approximate the principle of hierarchy in achieving

    coordination where inter-departmental interdependence was involved. While the flexibility and

    coordination benefits of design architectures that are hierarchical and nearly decomposable are

    widely reported in the literature (Adler , et al., 1999; Baldwin and Clark, 2000; Lawrence and

    Lorsch, 1967), how one discovers or designs such an architecture for a complex product or

    organization is relatively underexplored. The design challenge is compounded when we

    consider, not omniscient designers, but, boundedly rational designers engaging in local and

    imperfect search in the space of design possibilities. Does the tractability of the design challenge

    for boundedly rational agents vary with the underlying architecture of the complex problem? We

    propose to explore this complex design challenge in a setting where there is an explicit

    recognition of the limits to the adaptive and inferential capacity of the design effort.

    2.3. Contingent Logic of Alternative Environments

    As suggested above, we focus on two aspects of organization design: (1) how to group

    organizational functions into two or more departments or units; and, (2) specify the hierarchy of

    information flow or task ordering between the departments. As a result, the critical features of

    the environment from the perspective of our analysis is the net effect of task, technology, and

    institutions, on the choices of the number and nature of departments and the information flow

    between them. Consistent with contingency logic, there should be some ordering among the set

    of possible organizational forms based on their fit with a given set of environmental conditions

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    13/58

    13

    different groupings of organizational choices and the direction of information flow among them

    will vary in their efficacy, depending on the myriad environmental influences at work.

    Accepting the existence of some inherent contingency logic regarding the desirability of

    alternative forms, if managers make guesses about structures and observe the consequences of

    their choices, it is reasonable to expect to observe (boundedly rational) efforts at adaptive

    organizational change. For instance, if a multinational corporation (MNC) operating in several

    countries all over the world employs a functional structure to coordinate its activities and

    observes the dysfunctional effects of the uniformity of policies in different countries, such

    information constitutes feedback about the inappropriate grouping of organizational choices and

    functions. It is reasonable to expect the managers of the MNC to engage in efforts to adapt the

    organization structure in the light of such feedback. While bounded rationality suggests that they

    are unlikely to discover the appropriate structure in the first attempt, it is certainly possible that

    repeated, small adaptive attempts will generate progress toward the appropriate structure.

    There is, however, a second complication. The adaptive walk toward discovering the

    appropriate structure of a complex organization given its environment is likely to be relatively

    effective only if the environment is itself stationary. Over time, the MNC might enter or exit

    from different technologies, countries, and businesses, making the appropriate structure defined

    by the environment a moving target. What constituted an appropriate grouping of organizational

    functions at one time might be inappropriate at another time point. This brings us back to the

    central questions posed in this paper. Can boundedly rational managers of complex organizations

    engage in effective design activities in the space of organizational forms given that the

    environment which defines the appropriate organizational form is itself changing?

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    14/58

    14

    2.3. First-order and second-order adaptation

    The roots of the distinction between first-order and second-order change processes can be

    traced to Argyris and Schn (1978). First-order adaptation occurs within the parameters of an

    existing architecture or design and is geared to improving performance and finding durable fixes

    and solutions to identified problems (Bartunek, 1984). For instance, in the photocopier example,

    first order adaptation would involve incremental tweaks to the design, such as making it easier to

    open a door to remove paper jams or load paper. Such incremental changes are a result of

    cumulative learning-by-doing over long periods of time (Adler and Clark, 1991; Nelson and

    Winter, 1982). In contrast, second order adaptation involves a change in the existing architecture

    itself. Thus, fundamental shifts in strategy or structure would fall within the ambit of second-

    order change (Bartunek, 1984). Analogously, adaptation in the space of organizational forms or

    designs is akin to second-order adaptation, whereas incremental adaptation within a given

    organizational form is akin to first-order adaptation (Fiol and Lyles, 1985). The obvious

    downside risk of second-order adaptation is the obliteration of prior first-order adaptation efforts

    (Tushman and Romanelli, 1985). For instance, with a complete re-design of the architecture of

    the copier, the difficulty of retaining all the incremental first-order adaptive efforts of the past is

    quite apparent. Often, realizing the full benefits of second-order adaptation requires the

    elimination of prior first-order adaptations.

    On the upside, second-order adaptation can open up new opportunities for successful

    first-order adaptation efforts. This is because opportunities for first-order adaptation often exhibit

    diminishing returns over time. In complex interdependent systems, first-order adaptation efforts

    are rarely costless. Improvement in one dimension often comes at the cost of deterioration in one

    or more other dimensions. As more and more such adaptations are carried out, the available

    opportunities for productive adaptation declines over time (Tushman and Anderson, 1986). In

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    15/58

    15

    such cases, a change in the architecture or second-order adaptation can create new opportunities

    for first-order adaptation (Henderson and Clark, 1990).

    The preceding discussion hints at a trade-off between first-order and second-order

    adaptation. But what is unclear is the precise nature of the trade-off. The empirical literature in

    organization theory remains inconclusive. Carroll and Hannan (2000) present a list of 15 papers

    in organization theory with eleven studies finding a positive relationship between organizational

    change and mortality and eight [some studies show both findings] studies document a negative

    relationship. Carroll and Hannan (2000) suggest that changes in core aspects of organizations are

    likely to threaten survival, while incremental and peripheral changes are likely to be less

    disruptive. However, as a field we need greater conceptual clarity as to what constitutes core

    versus peripheral changes. As an initial step in this direction, we seek to examine the boundary

    conditions under which first-order and second-order adaptations are complements and the

    conditions under which they counteract each other.

    In sum, we seek to investigate three distinct, but interrelated questions that comprise the

    foundational structure of organization theory: (1) how does the architecture or structure of

    complexity affect the feasibility and usefulness of boundedly rational design efforts; (2) to what

    extent does the rate of environmental change nullify the usefulness of design efforts; and, (3)

    how does second-order adaptation design efforts affect first-order adaptation incremental

    performance improvement efforts. The first question speaks to the fundamental dilemma of

    causality between bounded rationality and complexity posed by Simon (1962). The next two

    questions examine how our understanding of environmental change and organizational

    adaptation processes tempers the practical usefulness of design efforts. In other words, does the

    primacy of environmental and organizational change processes overwhelm the feasibility and/or

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    16/58

    16

    functionality of organization design efforts? The following section describes a formal modeling

    structure that we set up to explore the research questions outlined above.

    3. Model3

    The first question we sought to investigate was how the architecture of complexity affects

    the feasibility and usefulness of boundedly rational design efforts. In addressing this question,

    we sought to hold constant the boundedly rational nature of the search processes and contrast the

    relative effectiveness of this search process as the architecture of complexity varies. Toward this

    end, we set up four alternative states of the world (what we term generative structures from

    hereon) that vary in the nature of the underlying complexity discussed above decomposability

    and hierarchy: (1) hierarchical and loosely-coupled (cf. Figure 1a); (2) non-hierarchical and

    loosely-coupled (cf. Figure 1b); (3) hierarchical and tightly-coupled (cf. Figure 1c); and, (4) non-

    hierarchical and tightly-coupled (cf. Figure 1d)4. In the figures, an alphanumeric notation

    represents each decision variable. The alphabetic portion denotes the department, while the

    numeric portion denotes the respective decision choice. The xs in each row-column intersection

    identify interdependence between decision choices. Reading across a row, an x indicates that

    the row variable is affected by the column variable. Conversely, reading down a column, an x

    indicates that the column variable affects the row variable. Therefore, xs positioned

    symmetrically above and below the principal diagonal represents reciprocal interdependence

    between decision choices.

    Within each department, each decision choice is tightly-coupled with other decision

    choices in the same department what Thompson (1967) terms reciprocal dependence. Figure 1a

    3 In the interest of readability, details of the formal implementation are provided in a separate technical appendix.4 Note that Figures 1a-1d bear a resemblance to two recent published papers (Ethiraj and Levinthal, 2004; Rivkin

    and Siggelkow, 2003). The similarity is a function of the common modeling apparatus employed. The research

    questions examined here, however, share no overlap with the research questions of either of these two papers.

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    17/58

    17

    depicts a structure that is hierarchical and loosely-coupled, i.e., departments 2 and 3 have a

    weakly coupled relationship with the next higher department, denoted by a single x below the

    principal diagonal. The presence (absence) of hierarchy is identified by the asymmetry

    (symmetry) in between-department interaction. The degree of loose coupling is a function of the

    strength (magnitude) of between department interactions. If there are no interactions between

    departments, then the organization is fully de-coupled. In Figure 1a, decision a 2 influences the

    payoff associated with decision b3. This also corresponds to sequential or hierarchical

    interdependence between departments (Thompson, 1967).

    >

    Figure 1b denotes a loosely-coupled but non-hierarchical structure. The structure is still

    loosely-coupled, since the interaction within departments is stronger than interaction between

    departments. However, the structure is not hierarchical, since there is no precedence ordering of

    activities between the departments. Departments a and b are characterized by reciprocal

    interdependence (Thompson, 1967) and symmetry in between-department interactions. Figure 1c

    describes a hierarchical, but tightly-coupled structure. The interaction between departments a

    and b and departments b and c is as strong as the interaction within the respective

    departments. In this organization, however, hierarchy is preserved since there is only sequential

    interdependence between departments, i.e., department a affects department b, but not vice

    versa. Finally, Figure 1d represents a non-hierarchical and tightly-coupled structure. In the four

    settings, the degree of coupling in Figure 1a and Figure 1b (and Figure 1c and 1d respectively) is

    held constant as the total number of interactions off the principal diagonal is equal.

    Each of the four structures, in a stylized manner, represents different contexts that

    managers encounter. For instance, the hierarchical and loosely-coupled structure might

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    18/58

    18

    characterize the relationship between the R&D and manufacturing departments of a

    pharmaceutical company. The process of drug discovery including drug development and

    clinical trials usually spans between 3.5 and 13 years (Dranove and Meltzer, 1994). Moreover,

    since the FDA approval rate for new drugs is only about 17-20 percent (DiMasi, 2001), it is

    likely that the R&D process is highly de-coupled from the manufacturing process with the latter

    emerging as a significant issue only after the FDA approval of the drug. This suggests that

    Figure 1a might be representative of the hierarchical and loosely-coupled relationship between

    R&D and manufacturing in pharmaceutical firms5. On the other hand, in more process intensive

    industries such as chemicals and semiconductors, it is likely that manufacturing considerations

    will be tightly-coupled with R&D decisions (Ulrich and Eppinger, 1999: 20). This leads us to

    expect that the R&D-manufacturing relationship in the semiconductor industry is likely to be

    non-hierarchical and tightly-coupled as in Figure 1d.

    Both situations are in contrast to the case where the relationship between R&D and

    manufacturing is loosely-coupled but mutually consultative in nature (i.e., Figure 1b), i.e., R&D

    iterates its designs based on input from manufacturing. This is likely to be the case in the

    automotive industry, though the strength of the relationship likely depends on the extent to which

    manufacturing cost considerations dominate (Clark and Fujimoto, 1991). Lastly, the relationship

    between R&D and manufacturing in the biotechnology industry seems representative of the

    hierarchical and tightly-coupled structure. A biotechnology product is a protein-based drug, in

    contrast to a pharmaceutical product which is chemical-based. Protein-based drugs are derived

    from living organisms, human blood and plasma, and proteins. As a result, the manufacturing

    5 Note that in the pharmaceutical example there is a temporal separation between R&D and manufacturing. The

    meaning of hierarchy in our models is simply the unidirectional flow of decision constraints. Such unidirectionalflow may be a result of temporal separation of decisions (as in the pharmaceutical example) or simply the ordering

    of decision constraints between sets of activities at a point in time (see Cusumano and Selby, 1998 for an example of

    how Microsoft partitions its decision constraints in organizing its software development activity).

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    19/58

    19

    process cannot be divorced from product development R&D. Thus, the separation between R&D

    and manufacturing that exists in chemical-based drugs is not possible in protein-based drugs

    (Dove, 2001) and leads us to expect that the R&D-manufacturing relationship in the latter will be

    hierarchical, but tightly-coupled as in Figure 1c. The descriptions of the four contrasting contexts

    of the R&D-manufacturing relationship suggest that the four structures might depict alternative

    states of the world, each of which might pose different design and coordination challenges.

    Addressing the three research questions posed earlier requires the specification of the

    following: (1) the four generative structures; (2) boundedly rational second-order adaptation; (3)

    boundedly rational first-order adaptation; (4) environmental change; and, (5) selection. The

    following sub-sections provide an intuitive explanation for the modeled processes. The attached

    appendix provides a formal description.

    3.1. Modeling the generative structures

    We represent an organization as a set of N decision variables, some subset of which is

    interdependent. For simplicity and without loss of generality, in our model each decision variable

    is assumed to take on two possible values (0,1). Thus, the space of possible organizational action

    consists of 2N

    possible sets of behaviors. For instance, if we consider the manufacturing strategy

    of a business firm, then a setting of 1 might represent a policy of outsourcing production activity

    and a setting of 0 might connote engaging in in-house manufacturing. It follows that different

    settings for the decision variables of the organization have different performance implications.

    Continuing with the organizational example, choices about production are likely to have

    interactions with the investments in information technology, rate of product introductions, and so

    on. For instance, it is conceivable that rapid and highly variable patterns of product introductions

    may enhance the value of outsourcing and of a sophisticated information technology system that

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    20/58

    20

    can link retail activity to external suppliers. In other words, some combinations of decision

    choices may yield performance improvements while others may undermine it (Macduffie, 1995).

    The performance of the organization ultimately depends on the settings (1s or 0s) of the

    decision variables. However, the ability of the organization to engage in effective first-order

    adaptation and identify a more or less desirable set of choices is, in turn, a function of the

    organizations structure --- in particular, the set of interactions among the decision choices, as

    described by Figures 1a-1d. When there are no interactions between decision variables, each

    decision makes an independent contribution to organizational performance. As the interactions

    between decision variables increase, the contribution of each decision variable to organizational

    performance becomes increasingly interdependent. Overall performance is an average of the

    performance contribution of individual decision variables.

    In modeling the four generative structures, there are both systematic and stochastic

    manifestations of each structure. First, the number of departments, D, was specified subject to

    the constraint that each department contained an equal number of decision choices. This was

    done so as to reduce the combinatorics of the possible structures we need to consider as we vary

    N and D. In specifying the interaction structure across decision variables, we assume that, as

    depicted in the illustrative Figures 1a-1d, all decisions within a department interact with one

    another. Further, for the loosely-coupled structures, we assume that the number of cross-

    departmental interactions is 2(D-1), or, on average, two interactions between each pair of

    departments. For the tightly-coupled structures, we assume that the number of interactions across

    departments are 2(N/D * N/D), or half the degree of within department interactions. While the

    magnitude of the degree of interactions is specified in this manner, the particular variables that

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    21/58

    21

    interact with one another are chosen randomly.6

    Thus, overall interdependence in Figures 1a and

    1b (the loosely-coupled structures) was always equal, with hierarchical and non-hierarchical

    structures having the same total number of between department interactions. Similarly, in the

    case of the two tightly-coupled structures (Figures 1c and 1d) the total magnitude of between

    department interactions is the same.

    3.2. Modeling boundedly rational second-order adaptation

    We assume that managers make two organization design choices: (1) how many

    departments or units to create; and, (2) the assignment of functions to departments. We model an

    evolutionary search process wherein managers engage in boundedly rational adaptive attempts to

    discover superior structures as defined by the appropriate number of departments and the

    appropriate mapping of decision variables to departments in the context of one of the four

    underlying generative structures. We implement three search operators that collectively represent

    second-order adaptation: (1) splitting; (2) combining; and, (3) re-allocation.

    Splittingmay be seen as the breaking up of existing departments into two or more new

    departments. As departments within organizations grow larger, the same piece of information is

    likely to have to pass through a larger number of potentially redundant individuals before

    resulting in an action or decision. In such cases, splitting an existing department can help

    economize on information flow (Arrow, 1974). Splitting is also necessitated when a department

    is engaged in a number of unrelated activities, each of which requires different skills, people,

    and/or resources. In such settings, splitting facilitates differentiation (Lawrence and Lorsch,

    1967) among organizational units to allow specialization to their specific contexts.

    6 We did robustness checks (available on request) that vary the degree of within department interactions and the

    treatment of loosely- versus tightly-coupled structures. The qualitative results remain as long as the ordering of theintensity of interactions remains the same, ranging in intensity from within department interactions, interactions

    across departments in the tightly coupled structure, to the degree of interactions across departments in the loosely-

    coupled structure.

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    22/58

    22

    Combining is simply the opposite of splitting. This is akin to combining or integrating

    two or more departments. From the seminal work of Lawrence and Lorsch (1967), we know that

    organizational structures are constantly balancing the contrasting forces of differentiation and

    integration. While pressures for local adaptation dictate greater differentiation, the pressures for

    broader efficiencies in organizational performance demand greater integration. Indeed, there is

    empirical evidence that organizations often cycle between extended periods of increasing

    decentralization (differentiation) and increasing centralization (integration) (Cummings, 1995;

    Mintzberg, 1979; Nickerson and Zenger, 2002) suggesting that the combining operator might be

    an important counterpart to splitting.

    In addition to the splitting and combining of departments, organizations often simply

    transferorreassign functions from one subunit to another. Such reorganization does not lead to

    a more (as in splitting) or less (as in combining) partitioning of tasks, but simply involves the re-

    allocation or re-assignment of functions between departments. For instance, the shift from an

    organization structured along geographic lines to a product structure (Bartlett and Ghoshal,

    1989) or from a functional structure to a product structure (Chandler, 1962) has no clear

    implication for the number of subunits, but obviously would involve the wholesale

    reconfiguration of organizational activity.7

    Collectively, these operations of combining, splitting,

    and transfer are the mechanisms that generate change in both the number of departments within

    the organization and the assignment of decision variables to departments, what we consider to be

    an organizations architecture.

    7 In the context of the splitting and combining operators, we consider substantial, discrete points of restructuring.

    With respect to the transfer of activities, we examine reallocation of individual elements from one subunit toanother, or what Eisenhardt and Brown (1999) refer to as a form of patching. Note, however, that such

    incremental efforts at reorganization can, over time, cumulate in broad changes.

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    23/58

    23

    The inference involved in the three operations is boundedly rational. Managers employ

    the operations of splitting, combining, or transfer based on their understanding of whether one or

    more decision choices belong to their respective department. The inferential process is imperfect

    in that only pairs of departments are compared at a time and, furthermore, the examination of

    each department is only local. As a result, the eventual outcome of the attempts at redesign is not

    always functional from the organizational standpoint, thus rendering second-order adaptation

    imperfect. In addition, observing such patterns of influence does not assume that managers

    understand cause and effect processes at the department level. The only behavioral assumption

    made is that the designers are able to observe the effect of their actions through a crude form of

    root cause analysis (Macduffie, 1997) (the formal specification of the splitting, combining,

    and transfer operators is provided in the technical appendix).

    3.3. Modeling boundedly rational first-order adaptation

    First-order adaptation is implemented as follows. In each period of the experiment, the

    actors within each department attempt to enhance the performance of their particular department.

    Actors are assumed to see the performance of their given department and can anticipate what

    incremental changes from the existing decision string would imply for department performance.

    Thus, adaptation occurs through a process of off-line, local search implemented simultaneously

    in each of the departments (cf., Marengo , et al., 2000; Rivkin and Siggelkow, 2003)8. Within

    each department, a decision choice is selected at random and actors within each department

    evaluate the efficacy of flipping the decision choice (0,1) by the criterion of improvement in

    department performance. The change is implemented if there is a perceived increase in

    8 This capability, as suggested by Rivkin and Siggelkow (2003), may be a function of effective accounting systems

    that are able to facilitate the evaluation of department level performance. Indeed, activity based costing is widely

    deployed to track the performance of organizational sub-units (Cooper and Kaplan, 1992).

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    24/58

    24

    department performance. However, since these change attempts occur in parallel in each of the

    departments and the departments may have some degree of interdependence, there is no

    presumption that these change efforts will in fact improve organizational performance, or even

    department performance.

    3.4. Modeling environmental change

    Environmental change, according to the contingency view, causes a mis-alignment

    between organizational structures, choices, and environmental demands. As described in 3.2,

    managers engage in second-order adaptation in the space of organizational forms in order to

    align the organization structure with the unknown generative structure. A change in the

    environment will have at least two effects on organizations. First, environmental change can

    obviate prior first-order adaptations and in that sense environmental change can be competence

    destroying (Tushman and Anderson, 1986). Second, environmental change may render less

    appropriate a given organizational form (Stinchcombe, 1965). For instance, continuing with the

    example of a multinational firm, if political change in the host country in which the firm operates

    increases the asset expropriation threat, then the old policies that guide investment and growth

    are unlikely to remain relevant. The organizations managers now need to balance the pursuit of

    growth against the threat of expropriation.

    To capture the effects of the possible obsolescence of organizational competence, as

    expressed in the reduced performance associated with the current set of policy choices, and the

    possible mis-alignment between environmental demands and the organization structure, we

    allow the environment to change every period with some probability, . A stable environment is

    specified as =0 and the environment changes every period with certainty when =1. For all

    intermediate values of, the environment changes probabilistically.

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    25/58

    25

    >

    Specifically, following each environmental change, we re-specify the coupling of

    decision variables within departments and the nature of between-department interactions that

    makes up the generative structure. Contrasting Figure 1a with Figure 1e illustrates the effect of

    environmental change for the hierarchical and loosely-coupled structure. Two changes are visible

    in a comparison of the two figures. First, the composition of the departments is altered in the

    sense that decision variables subscripted a, b, and c are no longer clustered together in the same

    department. Second, the between-department interactions are altered as well. We implemented

    environmental change in the three other structures along similar lines

    9

    . Given the newly specified

    structure, the performance landscape is re-seeded to generate a new mapping between decision

    variables and performance outcomes. We note that the form of environmental change we

    implement is best described as radical in the sense that all prior adaptations and learning is

    destroyed after the environmental change. We recognize that such radical change is perhaps quite

    rare. Change, more often, tends to be incremental and tends to devalue some prior adaptations

    while preserving others. In this sense, this characterization of environmental change is relatively

    favorable to the possibility of useful second-order adaptation efforts. As one moves along the

    continuum from a stable to a radically changing environment, the value of second-order change

    efforts changes commensurately.

    3.5. Modeling selection

    Organizational selection processes are modeled as being proportionate to fitness. The

    probability that an organization will be selected equals its performance level divided by the sum

    of the performance of all organizations in the population at that time. This is a standard

    9 We also implemented environmental change as triggering also a change in the number of departments that

    represent the generative structures. The results were identical and are available with the authors on request.

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    26/58

    26

    assumption in modeling biological processes (Wilson and Bossert, 1971) and has been used in a

    number of models of organizational selection (see Lant and Mezias, 1990, 1992; see Levinthal,

    1997).

    4. Analysis

    For each run of the model, a generative structure is specified as characterized in section

    3.1. In addition to initializing the performance landscape, the states (0,1) of the vector of

    decision choices are drawn at random at the start of an experiment. Since any single run is

    sensitive to the inherent randomness in both the initial states of the decision choices and the

    initialization of the performance landscape, we replicated each experiment 100 times with

    different starting seeds for both the specification of the performance landscape and the starting

    state of the system. The reported results, unless mentioned otherwise, are averaged over the 100

    runs to remove the stochastic component endemic to any single run. Figure 1f illustrates an

    interaction matrix for a single organization at the start of a typical experiment. As can be seen

    from the figure, the starting organization design contains unequal sized departments with no

    systematic pattern of interactions among decision choices. In each run we generate 100

    organizations where for each organization the number of departments and the allocation of

    activities to departments is randomly specified, as are the settings for the decision choices. Thus,

    at the start of each run there are typically 100 different organizational forms, each of which

    independently engages in second-order adaptation.

    >

    4.1. The architecture of complexity and the effectiveness of design efforts

    The first experiment seeks to answer the question, how does the architecture of

    complexity affect the feasibility and usefulness of boundedly rational design efforts (i.e., second-

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    27/58

    27

    order adaptation). The second-order adaptation challenge entails discovering the set of

    interactions among the N decision variables and clustering those decision variables that seem to

    have strong interactions with each other. We examine whether the problem of second-order

    adaptation is tractable and whether and how it varies systematically with the architecture of

    complexity.

    A key performance variable we track is the number of organizational forms as the

    simulation progresses. If second-order adaptation is fully successful, then the number of

    organizational forms would converge to one, i.e., the generative structure that represents the

    correct number of departments and the correct mapping of decision choices to the departments.

    This is an important performance metric since, as Simon (1962) points out, an important goal of

    organization design is to reach evolutionary stability. In the absence of any degree of stability,

    the efficacy of adaptation efforts is impaired.

    Figure 2 plots the number of organizational forms (averaged over 100 runs) as the

    simulation progressed in each of the four generative structures. The figure shows that as long as

    the structure is hierarchical, even at extreme levels of tight coupling (Figure 1c) where all

    decision choices of one department affect all decision choices of the immediately succeeding

    department (i.e., all decision choices of department 1 affects all decision choices of department 2

    and so on), the process of second-order adaptation is always able to discover and stabilize on the

    corresponding generative structure used to generate the performance landscape. On the other

    hand, when we introduced reciprocal interaction between departments, i.e., the generative

    structure is non-hierarchical (Figures 1b and 1d), organizations never manage to reach a stable

    state. In the non-hierarchical and loosely-coupled structure (Figure 1b), organizations converge

    on the generative structure most of the time, but the violation of hierarchy triggers instability

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    28/58

    28

    with about six different organizational forms continuing to survive even at the end of the

    experiment. In the case of the non-hierarchical and tightly-coupled structure (Figure 1d), the

    violation of both principles (hierarchy and loose-coupling) results in the generative structure

    never being identified. The initial diversity of organizational forms continues to be preserved,

    suggesting that second-order adaptation is relatively ineffective.

    >

    We examined the sensitivity of the results in Figure 2 for changes in the size of the

    organization (i.e., N) and the number of underlying departments (i.e., D). We find that the results

    are robust to changes in both the size of the organization and the number of underlying

    departments10

    . We observed an approximately linear positive relationship between organization

    size and the time periods to converge on the generative structure.11

    4.1.1. The impact of environmental change on design efforts

    In the previous section, we saw that managers were able to successfully converge on the

    underlying generative structure when such structures were hierarchical. These results were

    observed in a stable environment. However, environments are rarely stable over long periods of

    time and, as a result, the question arises as to whether second-order adaptation efforts continue to

    be effective when the environment changes periodically. We re-ran the models presented above

    introducing environmental change every period with a probability of=0.05 (see 3.4 for a

    description of how environmental change was implemented).

    >

    10 These results are not attached due to space constraints and are available from the authors.11 In sharp contrast, Schaefer (1999) finds that, in general, with a randomly specified structure, the problem of

    identifying the correct modularization of an organizational (or product) design is NP-complete (Garey and Johnson,

    1990).

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    29/58

    29

    The results with environmental change are presented in Figure 3. Whenever

    environmental change occurs, the cumulative adaptations of the previous periods are rendered

    ineffective and the organization designs are no longer aligned with the changed generative

    structure. The second-order adaptation efforts of the past are effectively reset and the process

    begins again. From the figure, we observe that the effectiveness of second-order adaptation in the

    presence of environmental change is considerably reduced. About 25-35 organizational forms

    continue to survive in both the loosely-coupled structures (both with and without hierarchy) and

    the hierarchical and tightly-coupled structure. The non-hierarchical and tightly-coupled structure,

    as in the case of the stable environment, makes the least progress in the process of second-order

    adaptation and, in this case, the initial diversity of organizational forms continues to persist.

    The pattern of results suggests that the effectiveness of second-order adaptation in the

    presence of environmental change is likely to be sensitive to two parameter settings of the model.

    First, the frequency of environmental change is critical to the effectiveness of second-order

    adaptation. As the rate of environmental change increases, the process of second-order

    adaptation becomes relatively ineffective. More subtly, the size of the organization is also critical

    to the effectiveness of second-order adaptation. As observed in the previous section, there is a

    linear positive relationship between the size of the organization and the time periods for the

    second-order adaptation process to be effective. Thus, if the environment changes faster than the

    time it takes for second-order adaptation to work, we can expect such efforts to be futile. For

    instance, we ran a set of models setting N=60 and the probability of environmental change at

    0.20 and found that, on average, the initial population of 100 organizational forms reduced to

    only about 50, even in the context of hierarchical generative structures. Similarly, as the

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    30/58

    30

    radicality of environmental change declines, the efficacy of second-order adaptation efforts

    correspondingly improves.

    In sum, the process of second-order adaptation is effective when there is a hierarchical

    precedence structure underlying between-department interactions and the pace of environmental

    change is moderate. Deviations from hierarchy lead to a complete collapse of the effectiveness

    of second-order adaptation in the context of tightly coupled structures. This finding regarding

    hierarchy formalizes Simons (1962) intuition that complex systems that are hierarchical tend to

    evolve faster and toward more stable structures. Hierarchy appears to be a necessary and

    sufficient condition for successful second-order adaptation. Nevertheless, as a practical matter,

    second-order adaptation is reasonably successful even when the generative structure is not

    hierarchical, but is loosely-coupled. We saw that, with a loosely-coupled structure, even when

    hierarchy is violated, the set of organizational forms reduces to a modest number (about 6 in the

    stable environment and about 30 in a changing environment). In contrast, the search process is

    less effective when the generative structure violates both hierarchy and loose-coupling.

    Apart from the diversity of organizational forms that are present, there is the important

    question of the degree of equifinality among these forms. Even if efforts at adaptive second-

    order change prove unsuccessful or lead to a fixation on a structure inconsistent with the

    generative structure, this need not imply that such organizations will fail to engage in effective

    first-order change. We explore these issues in the next set of experiments.

    4.2. Interaction between first-order and second-order adaptation

    As highlighted earlier, the extant literature on organization design offers ambiguous

    predictions on the relationship between first-order and second-order adaptation in complex

    organizations. The conditions under which they are substitutes and/or complements are yet

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    31/58

    31

    unclear. The set of experiments reported in this section is designed to clarify the interaction

    relationship between first-order and second-order adaptation efforts.

    Adaptation in loosely-coupled structures

    To explore the interaction between first-order and second-order adaptation, we preserved

    the process of second-order adaptation as implemented in experiment 1. In addition, we include

    the process of first-order adaptation.

    Figure 4 plots the average performance results from 100 runs of four models where the

    generative structure was loosely-coupled, both with and without hierarchy (i.e., Figures 1a-b)

    with an underlying structure of 5 departments (N=30). In two of the settings, there is a

    simultaneous process of first-order and second-order adaptation. In the other two settings, only

    first-order adaptation occurs and the organization persists in the initial random initialization of

    the department structure.

    >

    Comparing the four models in Figure 4 suggests that first-order adaptation shares strong

    complementarities with second-order adaptation. In settings with both first-order and second-

    order adaptation, performance not only increases faster, but also asymptotes at a higher level

    than in the case where there is first-order adaptation alone. However, a surprising and, in some

    sense, re-assuring finding is that the process of first-order adaptation continues to be quite useful

    even when the organization design is misaligned with the corresponding generative structure.

    This property manifests itself in two respects. First, even in the absence of second-order

    adaptation, in which case we know that in almost all circumstances the organizational structures

    that provide the context for first-order adaptation efforts are mis-specified, the process of local

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    32/58

    32

    adaptation is effective, reaching a performance level of 0.614 by the 100th

    period12

    . Second,

    when the generative structure is non-hierarchical, we know from the prior analysis that the

    process of second-order adaptation results in modest diversity in the set of organizational forms.

    Despite this, we find no significant performance differences between the hierarchical and non-

    hierarchical structures. Thus, the process of second-order adaptation, even in non-hierarchical

    structures, is generally effective in discovering a small subset of functionally equivalent designs

    in that each of these designs tends to yield equivalent first-order adaptation benefits, lending

    some support to the principle of equifinality (Gresov and Drazin, 1997). At least in loosely-

    coupled systems, it appears possible to realize the benefits of parallelism and localized

    adaptation even when the organization design is mis-aligned with environmental demands.

    Departures from hierarchy do, however, cause the process of first-order adaptation to be

    less monotonic, particularly in the absence of second-order adaptation.13

    In the absence of

    hierarchy, actors engage in local adaptation efforts that, ex post, turn out to be damaging to

    organizational performance as a whole. This is a consequence of the unanticipated and unknown

    reciprocal interactions between departments.

    Adaptation in tightly-coupled settings

    We engaged in a parallel analysis in which the generative structure was tightly-coupled

    (Figures 1c-d). Figure 5 indicates the results of first-order adaptation in four tightly-coupled

    structures: hierarchical, with and without second-order adaptation; and, non-hierarchical, with

    and without second-order adaptation. The results here partially diverge from that observed in

    loosely-coupled structures. First, the non-monotonicity in organization performance over time is

    12 Note that in this setting the performance asymptote is not reached by the 100th period. The process is still moving,

    though admittedly quite slowly, uphill.13 Indeed, the degree of non-monotonicity is somewhat masked by the fact that the reported results are averages over

    a 100 runs. Single runs of the model exhibit a greater degree of non-monotonicity.

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    33/58

    33

    much greater. This is due to the fact that the likelihood of incorrect first-order adaptation efforts

    is increasing in the degree of coupling between departments. Second, we find that the

    complementarity between first-order and second-order adaptation is robust even in tightly-

    coupled structures. First-order adaptation in conjunction with second-order adaptation tends to

    outperform the former alone.

    >

    These results lend robustness to the findings of the first set of experiments. If the

    condition of hierarchy is met, second-order adaptation is quite effective and first-order

    adaptation is then useful in generating performance improvements at the department level.

    Interestingly, we find that the performance asymptote (0.676) here is not statistically

    significantly different from the performance asymptote (0.684) in the case of loosely-coupled

    structures (see Figure 4). This suggests that if the underlying structure is hierarchical and

    designers engage in second-order adaptation, the success of first-order adaptation efforts is not

    sensitive to the degree of coupling.

    However, the violation of hierarchy tends to be damaging to first-order adaptation efforts.

    The disruptive consequences of first-order adaptation when hierarchy is violated are somewhat

    mitigated by second-order adaptation. Even though we found that the initial diversity of

    organizational forms persists in the face of second-order adaptation in non-hierarchical and

    tightly-coupled structures, it seems that the identification of this subset of designs enhances the

    effectiveness of first-order adaptation as compared with the random grouping of functions in the

    case where organizations engage in first-order adaptation alone. Thus even when hierarchy is

    violated, the process of second-order adaptation is an extremely useful design activity since it

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    34/58

    34

    results in more orderly structures that facilitate the process of first-order adaptation. This

    strengthens our initial findings on equifinality in loosely-coupled structures.

    In sum, the results in the stable environment indicate that second-order adaptation shares

    strong complementarities with first-order adaptation efforts. In the extreme case where the

    generative structures are neither hierarchical nor loosely-coupled, first-order adaptation efforts

    without second-order adaptation is largely futile. In general, the violation of hierarchy is less

    critical to first-order adaptation efforts than the violation of loose-coupling.

    4.2.1. The impact of environmental change on the complementarity of first- and second-order

    adaptation

    We found that first-order and second-order adaptation share strong complementarities in

    stable environments. Since environmental change renders second-order adaptation relatively less

    effective, we sought to examine whether the observed complementarity of first-order and

    second-order adaptation is robust in the presence of environmental change.

    We replicated the experiments reported in 4.2 with the addition of environmental

    change set at =0.05. As expected, the performance of organizations declined somewhat in a

    regime of modest environmental change. Otherwise the pattern of results14

    for both loosely-

    coupled structures and tightly-coupled structures were largely identical to that in Figure 4 and

    Figure 5 respectively, with the complementarities between first-order and second-order

    adaptation largely robust to modest levels of environmental change.

    In the first set of experiments that modeled the process of second-order adaptation alone,

    we saw that as the size of the organization and the probability of environmental change increase

    respectively, then the marginal value of second-order adaptation declines. The simple intuition

    here was that when the environment changes faster than the rate at which organizations can

    14 These results are not attached due to space constraints. They are available with the authors on request.

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    35/58

    35

    effectively adapt in the space of organization designs, then such adaptations are likely to be futile

    (Hannan and Freeman, 1984). We examine this possibility here as well.

    From an evolutionary standpoint, since selection will tend to favor higher performing

    organizations, if second-order adaptation generates performance gains, then organizations that

    engage in second-order adaptation will have an evolutionary edge over organizations that do not

    engage in second-order adaptation. Conversely, if increases in organization size and frequency of

    environmental change, respectively, obliterate the value of second-order adaptation, then we

    should find that such efforts at second-order change do not provide any evolutionary edge. In this

    case, we should find that organizations that are inertial, i.e., do not engage in second-order

    adaptation, should face no differential selection pressures as compared with organizations that do

    engage in second-order adaptation. We investigate this possibility by populating the landscape

    with 100 organizations with a randomly specified number and composition of departments and

    settings for the decision variables. We set N=60, D=5, and =0.25. All 100 organizations engage

    in first-order adaptation, but 50 randomly selected organizations also engage in second-order

    adaptation every period while the remaining 50 are inert. In each period, 100 organizations are

    selected with replacement and we track the number of surviving organizations that are inert with

    respect to their structure and the number of survivors that engage in second-order adaptation. An

    increase in the population of inert firms would suggest that inert firms enjoy an evolutionary

    advantage, whereas a significant decrease would indicate an evolutionary disadvantage.

    >

    Figure 6 graphs the number of inert organizations that survive in each period of the

    simulation in each of the four generative structures. The results confirm the relative futility of

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    36/58

    36

    second-order adaptation15

    . The population of inert firms continues to drift randomly around 50,

    suggesting that they face no significant advantage or disadvantage as compared with firms that

    engage in second-order adaptation.

    At the end of the experiment, there was no statistically significant difference in the

    average performance levels of the inert and non-inert organizations in all four structures.

    However, examining the variance in performance over the 50 simulation periods, we find that

    populations of organizations that include second-order adaptation exhibit twice the variance in

    performance as compared with organizational populations that remain inert with respect to their

    structure. This result confirms the intuition behind Hannan and Freemans (1984) argument that

    adaptation efforts in the space of organization forms reduces reliability rather than enhancing

    performance when the environment changes faster than the pace at which organizations adapt.

    In sum, the results including environmental change suggest that when change is episodic

    and infrequent then the complementary effects of first-order and second-order adaptation are

    robust. However, as organizations grow larger (thus slowing the effectiveness of second-order

    adaptation) and the rate of environmental change increases, then second-order adaptation

    becomes largely ineffective. In such settings, the processes of first-order and second-order

    adaptation cease to be complements.

    >

    Table 1 summarizes these results, the implications of which we discuss in the following

    section.

    15 We ran these models for only 50 periods rather than 100 since there is no additional information conveyed in

    modeling the second 50 periods. Also, this analysis took about 200 hours to run on a state-of-the-art PC. Thus,

    reducing the simulated periods was a pragmatic concern as well.

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    37/58

    37

    5. Discussion

    The primary objective of this paper was to begin to explore a fundamental set of

    questions about organization design including the feasibility and value of design efforts (i.e.,

    second-order adaptation) and the interrelationship between design efforts and incremental

    adaptation efforts (i.e., first-order adaptation). Simon argued strongly both that complex systems

    tend to be hierarchical and loosely-coupled (Simon, 1962) and that individual cognition is

    substantially bounded relative to the complexity of the task environments that people face

    (Simon, 1955; Simon, 1957). Again, for Simon, these two properties, one of systems and the

    other of individuals, raise the question to what extent is the architecture of complexity (i.e.,

    hierarchy and decomposability) the ultimate arbiter of feasible and effective boundedly rational

    design efforts. This comprises a rather fundamental puzzle for modern organization theory as

    well. A puzzle closely related to the long-standing debate in the literature between contingency

    perspectives on organizational change that suggest both a high level of plasticity in organizations

    and, at least implicitly, a high level of cognitive reasoning on the part of managers and ecological

    perspectives that treat organizations as being relatively inert or subject to dysfunctional

    consequences as a result of change efforts. Our work seeks to engage these important questions

    in an even-handed manner that recognizes both the constraints on adaptation efforts and the

    importance of the structure of the firms task environment.

    In general, we find that the underlying structure of complexity is an important

    determinant of the success of design efforts. In particular, hierarchy is shown to be a necessary

    and sufficient condition for the success of design efforts, in contrast to the relatively greater

    saliency given to the property of loose-coupling in this literature (Simon, 2002; Simon and Ando,

    1961). Loose-coupling, however, is shown to moderate the violation of hierarchy in terms of

    facilitating design efforts. This finding regarding the role of hierarchy and loose-coupling is

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    38/58

    38

    generally robust to both variations in the size of the organization and its complexity (i.e., number

    of departments and the nature of interaction between them). The principle of hierarchy (i.e.,

    asymmetry in between-department interdependence) facilitates the process by which boundedly

    rational search on the space of organizational forms helps designers evolve toward and stabilize

    on appropriate forms. In contrast, in the absence of hierarchy (i.e., between-department

    interactions are reciprocal), the local search process never ceases searching for the appropriate

    assignment of decision choices to departments. Reciprocal interdependence triggers a cycling

    behavior wherein the reciprocally interdependent decisions are continually re-assigned from one

    department to another. The locally rational designers have no way of stopping this incessant

    searching. Thus, the appropriate design of non-hierarchic structures requires actors to have a

    sophisticated, perhaps implausibly so, global sense of the interdependencies. An empirical

    implication of this finding is that instances in which one observes an on-going pattern of

    organizational restructuring (see Eccles and Nohria, 1992) may stem from reciprocal

    interdependence among activities. In such settings, stability in organizational form can only

    result if the organization is willing to accept some degree of apparent mis-specification of the

    organizational structure.

    Thus, in terms of the chicken-and-egg dilemma that Simon posed, our analysis suggests

    that the underlying structure of complexity is an important arbiter of the success of human design

    efforts. Structures that are non-hierarchical and tightly-coupled do not easily lend themselves to

    effective analysis and design efforts; however, structures that are hierarchical (or if not

    hierarchical, loosely-coupled), are amenable to boundedly rational design efforts. Even in the

    case of non-hierarchical and tightly-coupled structures, the product of design efforts is still better

    than random designs. Though this is not observed in the reduction in diversity of organizational

  • 8/6/2019 Bounded Rationality and the Search for Organizational Architecture

    39/58

    39

    forms, the usefulness of design efforts to first-order adaptation is clear from the results of

    experiment 3. Thus, we infer that the usefulness of boundedly rational design efforts is not

    limited to just hierarchical and loosely-coupled structures. It broadly extends to other structures

    that violate the two properties. The benefits, however, of design efforts differ both qualitatively

    and quantitatively across the four different structures. In this regard, our analysis helps formalize

    and extend Simons intuitions and provide some boundary conditions around the direction of

    causality between the architecture of complex systems and bounded rationality16

    .

    The second research question sought to examine how environmental change hampers the

    usefulness of design efforts. We find that the relative efficacy of adaptive efforts in hierarchical

    structures persists with moderate levels of environmental change. However, as the rate of

    environmental change increases or organizations get larger, the capacity to adapt effectively

    recedes. Our results, thus, provide a potential r