Blasphemy and Leo Strauss Machiavelli.pdf

12
Cambridge University Press and University of Notre Dame du lac on behalf of Review of Politics are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Review of Politics. http://www.jstor.org Blasphemy and Leo Strauss's Machiavelli Author(s): Dante Germino Source: The Review of Politics, Vol. 53, No. 1, Special Issue on the Thought of Leo Strauss ( Winter, 1991), pp. 146-156 Published by: for the Cambridge University Press University of Notre Dame du lac on behalf of Review of Politics Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1407555 Accessed: 03-05-2015 19:15 UTC Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/ info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. This content downloaded from 186.18.172.79 on Sun, 03 May 2015 19:15:56 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Transcript of Blasphemy and Leo Strauss Machiavelli.pdf

Page 1: Blasphemy and Leo Strauss Machiavelli.pdf

Cambridge University Press and University of Notre Dame du lac on behalf of Review of Politics are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Review of Politics.

http://www.jstor.org

Blasphemy and Leo Strauss's Machiavelli Author(s): Dante Germino Source: The Review of Politics, Vol. 53, No. 1, Special Issue on the Thought of Leo Strauss (

Winter, 1991), pp. 146-156Published by: for the Cambridge University Press University of Notre Dame du lac on behalf of

Review of PoliticsStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1407555Accessed: 03-05-2015 19:15 UTC

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/ info/about/policies/terms.jsp

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

This content downloaded from 186.18.172.79 on Sun, 03 May 2015 19:15:56 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 2: Blasphemy and Leo Strauss Machiavelli.pdf

Blasphemy and Leo Strauss's Machiavelli

Dante Germitno

In 1966, I published a review article hailing Leo Strauss's Thoughts on Machiavelli as an instant classic. I also expressed some reserva- tions or "second thoughts" about its conclusions.' In the intervening years my appreciation for the profundity and originality of Strauss's interpretation has only increased, but many of my doubts have also remained. Here I wish to restate both my admiration and reserva- tions with particular attention to parts of Strauss's chapter on Machiavelli published in the 1972 edition of his History of Political Philosophy, co-edited with Joseph Cropsey.2

Let me at the outset state the obvious: Strauss's interpretation of Machiavelli is well- indeed overwhelmingly- supported by tex- tual evidence, given Strauss's manner of reading between the lines. No interpreter, therefore, is entitled to dismiss it out of hand, even if he or she disagrees with Strauss's methodology, in whole or in part. In this respect, Claude Lefort has provided a model for scholars whose philosophical orientation differs widely from that of Strauss.3 Strauss has given us a truly fresh look at the great Florentine.

I do not choose here to enter into a debate with what might be called Strauss's strict constructionist interpretation of the great texts in political theory. For a variety of reasons, I do not agree with Strauss that it is possible to understand a thinker "as he understood him- self," any more than I agree with Ranke that history can be written wie sie eigentlich gewesen ist. "Nevertheless" (as Machiavelli would say), I agree that the attempt to grasp and portray a great political the- orist's achievement empathetically from the inside is entirely laud-

1. "Second Thoughts on Leo Strauss's Machiavelli," Journal of Pblitics 37 (1966): 794-817. Without in any way implying his assent to my arguments, I would like to express my gratitude to my friend Prof. Harvey Mansfield for his comments on an earlier version of this article.

2. Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey, eds., History of Political Philosophy, 2nd ed. (Chicago: Rand McNally, 1972), pp. 271-92.

3. Claude Lefort, Le travail de l'oeuvre: Machiavel (Paris: Gallimard, 1972), pp. 259-309. By contrast, Gennaro Sasso, one of Italy's premier Machiavelli scholars, refused even to discuss Strauss's conclusions because he did not want to spend the time necessary to understand Strauss's teaching. Machiavelli e gli antichi, 2 vols. (Milan - Naples: Riccardo Ricciardi, 1987), 1: 4-5.

146

This content downloaded from 186.18.172.79 on Sun, 03 May 2015 19:15:56 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 3: Blasphemy and Leo Strauss Machiavelli.pdf

Strauss's Machiavelli 147

able. With respect to Machiavelli, Strauss has made one of the great attempts at such a portrayal.

I wish here also to look at Strauss himself empathetically and from the inside, especially as it concerns his conclusion that Ma- chiavelli was a deliberate (religious) blasphemer, whose blasphemy is all the more serious because it was covert. This matter is of cru- cial importance to Strauss's understanding of Machiavelli's entire teaching and its relationship to modernity. Only the uncritical ac- ceptance of a convention of modernity itself, that is, that religion is a "private affair" and should have nothing to do with politics, can prevent a scholar in political theory from taking the blasphemy ques- tion with the utmost seriousness.4

Strauss identifies Machiavelli as a blasphemer on the basis of an apparent mistake in Discourses I, 26, where David rather than God appears to be the referent and author of certain words in the Magnificat (Luke 1:53). For Strauss, every blunder by Machiavelli-and espe- cially every "manifest blunder"-- is deliberate and hides a deception. Inasmuch as the passage in question is the only New Testament quo- tation in the Discourses, and inasmuch as it occurs in the twenty- sixth chapter, Machiavelli's "mistake" with regard to it conceals a deception of mammoth proportions, Strauss alleges.

Strauss's reason for attributing crucial importance to Discourses I, 26 deserves to be quoted at some length:

We have seen [because the Discourses has 142 chapters to correspond to Livy's 142 books] that the number of chapters of the Discourses is meaningful and has been deliberately chosen. We may thus..,. wonder whether the number of chapters of the Prince is not also meaningful. The Prince consist of 26 chapters. Twenty-six is the numerical value of the sacred name of God in Hebrew, of the Tetragrammaton. But did Machiavelli know of this? I do not know. Twenty-six equals 2 times 13. Thirteen... for quite sometime has been considered an unlucky number, but in former times it was also and even primarily consid- ered a lucky number. So "twice thirteen" might mean both good luck and bad luck, and hence altogether: luck,fortuna. A case can be made for the view that [for Machiavelli] ... God is fortuna [and] ... sub- ject to human influence (imprecation).5

Having established, to his satisfaction, the importance of the number 26 for Machiavelli's theology, Strauss turns to consider the 26th chapter of the Discourses, whose heading declares that "a new

4. See Leo Strauss, Thoughts on Machiavelli (Glencoe, IL: The Free Press, 1958), p. 231.

5. Strauss and Cropsey, Political Philosophy, p. 286.

This content downloaded from 186.18.172.79 on Sun, 03 May 2015 19:15:56 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 4: Blasphemy and Leo Strauss Machiavelli.pdf

148 Dante Germino

prince..,. must make everything new." This means that the subject of the chapter is tyranny, he says, because at the end of chapter 25 Machiavelli had written that he who wants absolute power must make everything new (offices, names, authorities, leaders).6 Although Machiavelli avoids using the term tyranny in both the Prince and in Discourses I, 26, tyranny is the actual subject of the one and the other, Strauss concludes.

According to Strauss, Machiavelli's inference that the New Testa- ment verse "He hath filled the hungry with good things and the rich he hath sent empty away" applies to King David must be interpreted as follows:

The quotation forms part of the Magnificat, the Virgin Mary's prayer of thanks after she heard from the angel Gabriel that she would bring forth a son called Jesus; he that "hath filled the hungry with good things and sent the rich empty away" is none other than God himself. In the context of this chapter [Discourses I, 26] this means that God is a tyrant, and that King David, who made the rich poor and the poor rich, was a Godly king, a king who walked in the ways of the Lord because he proceeded in a tyrannical way. We must note that this is the sole New Testament quotation occurring in the Discourses or in the Prince. And that sole New Testament quotation is used for expressing a most horrible blasphemy. Someone might say..,. that the blasphemy is not expressly uttered but only implied. But this defense, far from helping Machiavelli, make his case worse, and for this reason: when a man openly utters or vomits a blasphemy, all good men shudder and turn away from him, or punish him according to his just deserts; the sin is entirely his. But a concealed blasphemy is so insidious... because it ... compels the hearer or reader to think the blasphemy by himself and so to become an accomplice of the blasphemer. Ma- chiavelli thus establishes a kind of intimacy with his readers..,. whom he calls "young," by inducing them to think forbidden or criminal thoughts .... This is an important part of his education of the young, or to use a time honored expression, of the corruption of the young.7

The most striking phrase in the above passage is "vomits a blasphemy." By using it, Strauss clearly means to align himself on the side of the phrase's author, the sixteenth-century French Cal- vinist Innocent Gentillet, one of the principal founders of the tradi-

6. Niccolo's Machiavelli, Tutte le opere (Florence: Sansoni, 1971), pp.25-26. The conclusion of Discourses I, 25 reads: "ma quello che vuole fare una potesti assoluta, la quale dagli autori & chiamata tirannide, debbe rinnovare ogni cosa, come nel seguente capitolo si dir&" (but he who desires an absolute power, which the authors call tyranny, must make everything new, as is explained in the following chapter).

7. Strauss and Cropsey, Pblitical Philosophy, pp. 287-88.

This content downloaded from 186.18.172.79 on Sun, 03 May 2015 19:15:56 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 5: Blasphemy and Leo Strauss Machiavelli.pdf

Strauss's Machiavelli 149

tion which associates Machiavelli's name with scandalous and im- moral "Machiavellianism."8 Although Strauss thinks that the tra- ditional version of Machiavelli as a diabolical figure forgets that the devil himself was a fallen angel, he thinks that one can "ascend" from that version to a more adequate understanding. On the other hand, the revised version (Machiavelli as humanist, republican, friend of the people, politically secular but not antireligious) represents the triumph of Machiavellianism itself. Those scholars who hail the "good," "progressive, "democratic" Machiavelli have been unknow- ingly corrupted by Machiavelli's evil message, hidden under a cover of good thoughts and good works.9

Let me now begin my criticism of Strauss on Machiavelli as blasphemer by comparing what Machiavelli has to say about David and about blasphemy in his "Exhortation to Penitence." (The Ex- hortation is a sermon believed to have been delivered by Machiavelli to a religious confraternity of which he was a member. Some scholars of note now place the date of the composition between 1525 and 1527, that is, during the last two years of Machiavelli's life.) I shall next proceed to a critique of Strauss's interpretation of Discourses I, 26. In conclusion, I will consider Strauss's closing words to his 1972 textbook chapter on Machiavelli as they appear to me to bear on the question of philosophy versus revelation, or Athens versus Jerusalem.

Regrettably, Strauss himself referred only fleetingly (once in the text and twice in the footnotes) to Machiavelli's lay sermon on peni- tence, so that it will be necessary to flesh out his view as to why this seemingly pious work does not challenge his interpretation of Discourses I, 26 and in general of Machiavelli as arch-atheist and blasphemer. 10

8. See Le A. Burd, II Principe (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1895), p. 55, which is Strauss's source for the following remark by Gentillet. "C'est atheiste ... a bien os& vomir ce blasph6me .. ." (Strauss, Thoughts on Machiavelli, p. 334, n. 72).

9. Strauss, Thoughts on Machiavelli p. 13. 10. Ibid., pp. 322, n. 133 and 332, n. 47. Strauss's first footnote refers to the

Exhortation as comparable to the three "sermons"- or discourses on a Latin text - found in the Discourses (ibid., p. 138) The second footnote begins with a reference to Discourses I, 30, which demonstrates that the vice of ingratitude (in a prince, toward his victorious general, for example) is "the effect of a natural necessity" (ibid., p. 194). Strauss continues: "As for the significance of the subject of grati- tude, see Machiavelli's Esortazione alla penitenza" (ibid, p. 332). These cryptic re- marks seem to me to suggest that Machiavelli views any profession of gratitude, especially toward one's "Lord" (signore), as feigned, and that therefore his counsel

This content downloaded from 186.18.172.79 on Sun, 03 May 2015 19:15:56 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 6: Blasphemy and Leo Strauss Machiavelli.pdf

150 Dante Germino

In the "Exhortation," Machiavelli refers to David as the author of the Psalms, as "reader [lectore] of the Holy Spirit" and as "prophet."11 Inasmuch as the Magnficat itself is redolent with phrases from the Psalms, it would appear that an obvious justification for Machiavelli's linkage in Discourses I, 26 of the words "He filled the poor with good things and the rich he sent empty away" to David was that he be- lieved him to have been author of the Psalms, interpreter of the Holy Spirit, and prophet. Indeed, Machiavelli begins the "Exhortation" by quoting the opening verse to Psalm 130 in the Vulgate: "Out of the depths have I cried unto thee, O Lord. Lord hear my prayer." He could have proceeded to quote the next verse: "If Thou, Lord, shouldest mark our iniquities . . . who shall stand?"

As defined by the Oxford English Dictionary, blasphemy is the "pro- fane speaking of God or sacred things" as well as "impious irrever- ence." Another dictionary gives this definition of blasphemy: "In Jewish law, cursing or reviling God or the king, who is God's repre- sentative; in later usage, pronouncing the forbidden name of God, the Tetragrammaton" (or the four Hebrew letters, written without vowel points, and transliterated YHVH).12 If in Discourses I, 26 Machiavelli in fact declared or even implied God to be a tyrant, he would certainly have been guilty of blasphemy. But did he? My own reading of the chapter reveals only that Machiavelli says of David

of contrition for ingratitude toward God and one's neighbor in the Exhortation is also feigned. Strauss's only textual reference to the Exhortation-and his only direct quotation from it - occurs in Thoughts on Machiavelli, p. 201, toward the end of his discussion of Discourses III, 6 on conspiracies. Noting Machiavelli's observa- tion that the dangers of conspiracies "surpass by far every other kind of danger," Strauss interprets this phrase as intended to include "the danger of damnation." He continues with the following qualification: "Or did Machiavelli believe that the danger of damnation can be averted by repentance, and perhaps even repen- tance on the death bed? 'Penitence" he says in his Exhortation to Penitence, 'is the sole remedy which can wipe out all evils, all errors of men.'" Neither David nor Saints Peter, Jerome, or Francis (all mentioned in the Exhortation) repented on their deathbeds.

11. All references to the "Exhortation to Penitence"- entitled "Exortatione alla penitenza"- rather than "Esortazione alla penitenza" as used by Strauss and many others-are from Mario Martelli, ed., Niccld Machiavelli: Tutte le opere (Florence: Sansoni, 1971), pp. 932-34. The title was not Machiavelli's own; his autograph manuscript left it untitled. An English translation is in Alan Gilbert, Machiavelli: The Chief Works, 3 vols. (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1965), 1: 170-75. I have used my own translation, however.

12. The Shorter Oxford English Dictionary, 2 vols. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1985), 1: 200; Webster's Dictionary of the English Language (New York, 1952), pp. 90, 879.

This content downloaded from 186.18.172.79 on Sun, 03 May 2015 19:15:56 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 7: Blasphemy and Leo Strauss Machiavelli.pdf

Strauss's Machiavelli 151

that "when he became King he made the rich poor and the poor rich." He does not say that David was the addressee of the precise words of the Magnificat. Nor does he say of David that he made every- thing new with new governments, new names, new authorities and new men. It was Philip of Macedonia, not King David, who "built new cities, destroyed buildings, and transferred inhabitants from place to place." These "very cruel means, inimical to every way of living, not only Christian but human" were employed by Philip, father of Alexander the Great, and not by David.'3

What Machiavelli says about David in the "Exhortation to Peni- tence" is that he deeply repented of having committed adultery and indirect murder in the affair with Bathsheba. In this one grievous instance, David abused his power as king by taking Bathsheba for his mistress and arranging to have her soldier husband killed on the front line of battle. This one instance, growing out of his lust of the flesh, hardly makes David a tyrant. Furthermore, wrote Machiavelli, in David "no greater penitence can be found in a man, nor in God can there be discovered any greater generosity to forgive."4

Is there "profane speaking of God" or "impious irreverence" to be found in this? It is true that Machiavelli's sermon presents God as most merciful, "as mindful of human weakness," and as opposed to "the rigors of the vendetta." How is this "profane speaking of God," however? How is Machiavelli guilty of "impious irreverence" when in the "Exhortation" he declares God to have devised "the most pious remedy for human weakness," namely penitence? How do these words square with an alleged vomiter of blasphemies?

In his recent intellectual biography of Machiavelli, Sebastian de Grazia has sifted through every scrap of writing left by the great Florentine. De Grazia concludes, somewhat surprisingly, that Machiavelli "discourses about God always in the conventional reverent attitude." Far from being an atheist or a blasphemer, Machiavelli emerges in de Grazia's reconstruction as a man with a sincere belief in God. Here is de Grazia's summation:

Scattered about his writings..,. like poppies in a field of chick peas, are many references to God. Together they form an unmistakable like- ness. Niccolo's God is the creator, master deity, providential, real,

13. Machiavelli, Discorsi sopra la prinma deca di Tito Livio, in Martelli, Machiavelli: Tutte le opere, p. 109.

14. Machiavelli, [Exortatione alla penitenza] in Martelli, Tutte le opere, 933.

This content downloaded from 186.18.172.79 on Sun, 03 May 2015 19:15:56 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 8: Blasphemy and Leo Strauss Machiavelli.pdf

152 Dante Germino

universal, one of many names, personal, invocable, thankable, to be revered, a judge, just and forgiving, rewarding and punishing, awe- some, a force transcendent, separate from but operative in the world.'15

In the "Exhortation to Penitence" Machiavelli appears to take sin - defined ultimately as ingratitude to God and enmity toward one's neighbor - seriously. Yet it is not sin "but the perseverance in sin" which God judges to be punishable with "eternal hellfire." God opens up "the way of penitence" as the path to eternal salvation, human beings having lost "the other way" of a sinless life, as a result of the Fall.

"Everything is created [by God] for the honor and good of man, and only man is created for the good and honor of God," declares Machiavelli in the "Exhortation." Man is given speech with which to praise God, hands with which to build temples and make sacrifices in His honor, and "reason and intellect with which he is able to spec- ulate about and understand" His greatness. See, however, continues Machiavelli, with what ingratitude man rebels against God's gifts! The tongue, given for speech so that man might honor God, is used "to blaspheme" Him.

Surely it is noteworthy that in the "Exhortation" Machiavelli the alleged blasphemer explicitly condemns blasphemy. He also con- demns converting our intellect from an instrument for understanding God's greatness into a means for speculating about the world. Not insignificantly, Machiavelli the alleged philosopher of supreme world- liness concludes the Exhortation with these lines from Petrarch:

to repent and to know clearly that everything which pleases the world is but a brief dream.16

Strauss's case against Machiavelli for blasphemy in Discourses I, 26 relies heavily on the conviction that the number twenty-six had a special theological significance for Machiavelli.'7 Yet Strauss himself

15. Machiavelli in Hell (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1989), p. 58. 16. Machiavelli, [Exortatione alla penitenza], p. 934. 17. Cf. Thoughts on Machiavelli, pp. 48-53. After observing that "in taking seri-

ously the number 26, we are on the right path" to understanding Machiavelli's intention, Strauss compares Prince 26, Discourses I, 26, and Discourses II, 26. (Dis- courses III, 26 is not mentioned, however). He then notes that Machiavelli "speaks of twenty-six emperors from Caesar to Maximinus, and adds: "This is not the place to give further examples of Machiavelli's use of the number 26 or, more precisely of 13 and multiples of 13" (p. 52). Apparently the proper "place" for Strauss to

This content downloaded from 186.18.172.79 on Sun, 03 May 2015 19:15:56 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 9: Blasphemy and Leo Strauss Machiavelli.pdf

Strauss's Machiavelli 153

admits that he "does not know" whether Machiavelli was aware that 26 is the numerical value of the Tetragrammaton.'8 Could not Machiavelli also have been ignorant that thirteen was both a lucky and an unlucky number and hence stood forfortuna, a blasphemous substitute for the God of revelation? There is no more evidence for the latter supposition than the former.

The difference between Sebastian de Grazia's and Strauss's at- tempts at empathetically grasping Machiavelli's teaching from within is that de Grazia allows that teaching to emerge from its author's own words - and from all of those words - placed in biographical context. By comparison, and despite his intention, Strauss gives the appearance of forcing Machiavelli to conform to a pattern imposed by him from without. Machiavelli to de Grazia is very much the citizen-activist and master of irony that one encounters in the letters. Strauss's Machiavelli, on the other hand, resembles a reclusive phi- losopher or perhaps a gnostic sage who pores over ancient texts- especially Plato, Aristotle, Xenophon, and the Bible -and who with truly diabolical cleverness hides a subversive message between the lines, a message that by the nineteenth century had succeeded in turning two thousand years of western philosophy and religion up- side down, almost single-handedly.

To such criticisms as I have offered, Leo Strauss might well have responded regretfully that I am just one more modern scholar who has been corrupted in his thinking by the very success of the Machiavellian doctrine.'9 We moderns are said no longer to know what blasphemy is because our "enlightened" minds are closed to revealed truth.20 Strauss would presumably have responded to de

mention these further examples is in his chapter in Strauss and Cropsey. See foot- note 5 above. This is not to say that Strauss did not give numerous examples of multiples of 13 in Thoughts on Machiavelli. None of these places seems to qualify as "the place" when he discusses the significance of the number 26, however.

18. Strauss and Cropsey, Political Philosophy, p. 286. So far as I know, in Thoughts on Machiavelli Strauss does not mention that the numerical value of the Tetragram- maton in Jewish law is 26.

19. "To do justice to Machiavelli requires one to look forward from a pre-modern point of view toward an altogether unexpected and surprising Machiavelli who is new and strange, rather than to look backward from today towards Machiavelli who has become old and our own, and therewith almost good" (Thoughts on Machiavelli, p. 12).

20. Ibid., pp. 49-52, Strauss defends his use of the term blasphemy not only with regard to Discourses I, 26 but to Machiavelli's entire teaching. The blasphemy of I, 26 is said to be "only the spearhead of a large column" (p. 49). Indeed, Machiavelli of necessity, so to speak, had to commit blasphemies and had to commit them covertly, because in his time the authority of the Bible was "generally recog-

This content downloaded from 186.18.172.79 on Sun, 03 May 2015 19:15:56 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 10: Blasphemy and Leo Strauss Machiavelli.pdf

154 Dante Germino

Grazia's reconstruction of a Machiavellian theology with the obser- vation that, under fear of persecution, Machiavelli of course masked his atheism in conventional references to the deity. In order to be effective, Machiavelli's blasphemy had to be subtle, so as not to bring the wrath of the authorities, including the papacy which had com- missioned him to write the History of Florence, down on his head, or to frighten and anger his readers, who were to be brought little by little to consider worldly humanism as a substitute for biblical revelation.

My response to such a conceivable rejoinder by Strauss is as follows. For all his brilliance, ingenuity, and formidable knowledge, Strauss has imposed on Machiavelli the consistency of a system- builder. My own sense of Machiavelli is that he was a man in love with the tangible, the concrete, and the comical. The Florentine Secretary was a man who dismissed his book the Prince as a "whim" or "fantasy."21 The Discourses on Livy seem to have only the most general kind of plan, and it is not clear to me that he ever finished the work.

In effect, Strauss argues that anyone who dissents from his overall interpretation of Machiavelli has to be, even if unknowingly, in the service of Machiavelli's antireligious modernism.22 Strauss contends that each wave of modernity has been more radical than the last, so that to the extent that we ourselves are moderns, Machiavelli has to seem "moderate" in comparison with Hobbes, Hegel, and Nietzsche.23

nized and supported by law." To bring forth what moderns call his innerworldly humanism, he had to challenge that authority by impugning its alleged source - i.e., God-and for fear of persecution he had to do it covertly (p. 52).

21. Machiavelli, letter to Francesco Vettori, 10 December 1513 in Tutte le opere, p. 1160. "Et se vi piacque mai alcuno mio ghiribizoy. ..

22. "The kinds of unbelief with which we are most familiar today are respectful indifference and such a nostalgia for lost faith as goes with an inability to distin- guish between theological truth and myth" (Thoughts on Machiavelli, p. 51). This is not one of Strauss's better "thoughts" See Dante Germino, Political Philosophy and the Open Society (Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press, 1982), for a discussion of myth, philosophy, revelation, and mysticism as modes of openness toward transcendent Being, the Being that revealed itself to Moses in Exodus 3 as "I AM THAT I AM." I shall reserve exploration of this complicated matter for another place. See the forthcoming Strauss-Voegelin Correspondence edited by Barry Cooper, University of Calgary, for Eric Voegelin's alternative understanding of philosophy and revelation.

23. Given Strauss's splendid mastery of Italian, it is appropriate that the best book I have read on Strauss on modernity is in Italian: Raimondo Cubeddu, Leo

This content downloaded from 186.18.172.79 on Sun, 03 May 2015 19:15:56 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 11: Blasphemy and Leo Strauss Machiavelli.pdf

Strauss's Machiavelli 155

I do not think that there exists a Rosetta stone to decipher the Machiavellian hieroglyph, and therefore, I do not think that Strauss has found it. I do not think that I personally am under the spell of modernity, against whose premises I have argued in print over the years. I do think that Strauss is a great interpreter of Machiavelli, precisely because he is greater than either his method (counting words, numbers of chapters, sentences, noting first and last words, etc.) or his conclusions about Machiavelli as a philosopher with a metaphysical system. Where Strauss is greatest is in his eye for tex- tual detail, his insistence on taking seriously every apparently idle word.

Let me conclude with a consideration of Strauss's notion of what it means to philosophize. Not accidentally, he refers to Machiavelli as a "corrupter of the young"- for these words of course were origi- nally part of the indictment returned by the jury against Socrates, as reported in Plato's Apology. Socrates was said to have corrupted the youth because he did not worship the gods worshipped by the polis and because he introduced "new divinities." In other words, Socrates corrupted the young because he was allegedly blasphemous.

The last words of Strauss's 1972 chapter on Machiavelli are: " ... Machiavelli and Socrates make a common front against the Sophists."24 Is Strauss deliberately silent about the "common front" Machiavelli and Socrates also make against revelation?

In his famous Jerusalem lecture, Leo Strauss refused to decide

Strauss e lafilosofia politica moderna (Naples: Edizioni Scientifiche Italiane, 1983). See the whole part II: "La modernith: Storia di una decadenza," pp. 165-315.

24. Strauss and Cropsey, Political Philosophy, p. 292. See also Thoughts on Machiavelli: "Machiavelli's claim that he has taken a road not yet trodden by anyone implied that in breaking with the Socratic tradition he did not return to an anti- Socratic position. . . (p. 291).

25. See Strauss'sJerusalem lecture on "The Mutual Influence of Theology and Philosophy; in V Ivyun-Hebrew Political Quarterly, no. 1 (Jerusalem. 1954) and "Jerusalem and Athens" in The City College, no. 6 (New York, 1967). In "Mutual Influence" he declares the Bible and philosophy to be "alternatives and antagonists in the drama of the human soul" (pp. 113-14). Strauss's overall conclusion is that philosophy can never refute revelation nor can revelation ever refute philosophy. Philosophy as the search for the just way of life is incompatible with the biblical teaching which claims to possess the truth about the just way of life. "Strauss's teaching does not lead to a subordination of philosophy to revelation. As a Jew, although distanced from the Synagogue, he does not refuse to speak of faith in an atheist world" or as a philosopher "to indicate to the believer those rational conclusions of philosophy which are antithetical to the faith. The tertium non datur . .. remains his secret position" (Cubeddu, Leo Strauss, pp. 44-45).

This content downloaded from 186.18.172.79 on Sun, 03 May 2015 19:15:56 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 12: Blasphemy and Leo Strauss Machiavelli.pdf

156 Dante Germino

whether philosophy or biblical revelation has the ultimate hold on our allegiance."25 Does this refusal bring him closer to Machiavelli and suggest that Strauss himself recognized that there was some- thing to be said in favor of Machiavelli, thereby mitigating the charge of blasphemy? Was the charge of blasphemy a deliberate exaggera- tion by Strauss to bring the entire dilemma of Athens versus Jerusalem back into public view? However one answers these ques- tions, one should never lose sight of the fact that the title of Strauss's Machiavellian masterpiece is Thoughts on [and not Certainties about] Machiavelli. In the end, we are indeed left with the thoughts of Leo Strauss as inspired by an original reading of the Florentine Secretary with the enigmatic smile.

The Vital Nexus Vol. 1 Number 1 May 1990

Conscience - Justice - Freedom

A Leo Strauss Symposium Contributors:

George Anastaplo - Shadia Drury Peter Emberley - Ernest Fortin John Gunnell - Clifford Orwin

- Robert Stone -

Published by The Institute of Human Values

Saint Mary's University Halifax, Nova Scotia

Canada B3H 3C3

Subscription $5.00

Institute Membership (includes Journal) $25.00

Next Issue:

Natural Law Symposium

This content downloaded from 186.18.172.79 on Sun, 03 May 2015 19:15:56 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions