Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

24
Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to Creative Receptivity (British Journal of Aesthetics / DOI: 10.1093/aesthj/ayaa041 ) Eli I. Lichtenstein Abstract: While t he idea of art as self-expression can sound old-fashioned, it remains widespread—especially if the relevant ‘selves’ can be social collectives, not just individual artists. But self-expression can collapse into individualistic or anthropocentric self-involvement. And compelling successor ideals for artists are not obvious. In this light, I develop a counter-ideal of creative receptivity to basic features of the external world, or artistic objectivity . Objective artists are not trying to express themselves or reach collective self-knowledge. However, they are also not disinterested or emotionless. They can be unmoved by personal feelings and human concerns, but they are still receptive—just attuned to the more elemental forces that creatively inspire them. I elaborate this ideal in dialogue with John Ruskin’s influential critique of the pathetic fallacy. By contextualizing Ruskin’s view vis-à-vis Romantic and Modernist poetics, post-Kantian aesthetics, modern environmental art, and contemporary theories of expressiveness, I show how it indirectly motivates my account. 1. Beyond Self-Expression? The idea of art as self-expression can seem old-fashioned, if not justifiably obsolete. At the very least, it no longer has the explicit pride of place that it did for the Romantic tradition which rose to prominence in the early 19 th century, giving new priority to the ‘expressive’ artist. 1 For us now, rather, the idea of self-expression has apparently been “collecting dust for some decades,” as one recent commentator puts it— in art and aesthetics, as elsewhere. 2 Still, it may have been right to say, forty years ago, that “the assumption that art is an important mode of self-expression and that it is justified on this account” is “ubiquitous” in the art literature of the 20 th century. 3 But this assumption has arguably been steadily losing steam ever since. On the other hand, the idea of art as creative self-expression clearly still has a firm hold on many parts of the public imagination. To begin with, it is still ubiquitous outside the cutting edge of aesthetics and art criticism. In pedagogical contexts, for instance, it remains common to view arts and crafts education as cultivating a capacity for “self- University of Michigan, Department of Philosophy; [email protected] 1 See e.g. Abrams 1953. 2 Green 2007, 3. 3 Osborne 1977, 296–297. 1

Transcript of Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

Page 1: Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

Artistic Objectivity:From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to Creative Receptivity

(British Journal of Aesthetics / DOI: 10.1093/aesthj/ayaa041 )

Eli I. Lichtenstein †

Abstract: While the idea of art as self-expression can sound old-fashioned,it remains widespread—especially if the relevant ‘selves’ can be socialcollectives, not just individual artists. But self-expression can collapse intoindividualistic or anthropocentric self-involvement. And compellingsuccessor ideals for artists are not obvious. In this light, I develop acounter-ideal of creative receptivity to basic features of the external world,or artistic objectivity. Objective artists are not trying to express themselvesor reach collective self-knowledge. However, they are also not disinterestedor emotionless. They can be unmoved by personal feelings and humanconcerns, but they are still receptive—just attuned to the more elementalforces that creatively inspire them. I elaborate this ideal in dialogue withJohn Ruskin’s influential critique of the pathetic fallacy. By contextualizingRuskin’s view vis-à-vis Romantic and Modernist poetics, post-Kantianaesthetics, modern environmental art, and contemporary theories ofexpressiveness, I show how it indirectly motivates my account.

1. Beyond Self-Expression?The idea of art as self-expression can seem old-fashioned, if not justifiably

obsolete. At the very least, it no longer has the explicit pride of place that it did for theRomantic tradition which rose to prominence in the early 19th century, giving newpriority to the ‘expressive’ artist.1 For us now, rather, the idea of self-expression hasapparently been “collecting dust for some decades,” as one recent commentator puts it—in art and aesthetics, as elsewhere.2 Still, it may have been right to say, forty years ago,that “the assumption that art is an important mode of self-expression and that it isjustified on this account” is “ubiquitous” in the art literature of the 20 th century.3 But thisassumption has arguably been steadily losing steam ever since.

On the other hand, the idea of art as creative self-expression clearly still has a firmhold on many parts of the public imagination. To begin with, it is still ubiquitous outsidethe cutting edge of aesthetics and art criticism. In pedagogical contexts, for instance, itremains common to view arts and crafts education as cultivating a capacity for “self-

† University of Michigan, Department of Philosophy; [email protected] See e.g. Abrams 1953.2 Green 2007, 3.3 Osborne 1977, 296–297.

1

Page 2: Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

expression” in children, and to value it as such.4 But the idea still exerts a stronginfluence within recent aesthetics and art criticism, too. Here there are still some self-conscious defenses of “the Romantic idea of artistic expression,” albeit fewer than inearlier eras.5 But ideals of self-expression are often invoked more casually, as well, as inNick Riggle’s recent account of street art: “The street facilitates self-expression andpublic interaction in a relatively constraint-free way[...]It is a place where we can expressourselves in public, present our style, declare our commitments, allegiances, and values—where we can be seen for who we are or aspire to be.”6

The idea of art as self-expression has even broader scope if one allows that the‘self’ in question can be a collective, not just an individual artist. In this broader sense,for instance, the paradigm of self-expression plausibly underlies focus on ‘relatability’ inpopular art and its reception: a social collective may value ‘expressing itself’ in mass art,by recapitulating common feelings or experiences. In historical context, the basic visionof art as collective self-expression can likewise encompass more nuanced Hegelianaccounts of art as distilling shared values or ideological tensions distinctive of a givenculture or epoch—such that art is a ‘sensuous expression’ of historically-evolving‘Spiritual’ freedom.7 Finally, the same basic idea can also extend to broadly Kantianaccounts of aesthetic experience as involving a more trans-historical expression ofuniversal human capacities—as in Schiller’s claim that aesthetic ‘play’ is the “dispositionwhich comprises in itself the wholeness of humanity,” wherein we are “masters in equaldegree” of our sense and reason.8 Art can thus be the “most complete possible expression”of “mankind” or shared humanity, by the artist acting on behalf of us all.9 So, while theidea of art as self-expression is old hat, in a sense, it may still be central to the currentcultural fabric.

But even if the idea of art as individual or collective self-expression is justoutdated, what—if anything—has replaced it? Or, to the extent that this idea is actuallystill widespread and apparently compelling, even within aesthetic theory and art criticism,why seek to replace it? What should an artist now aspire towards, if not expressingherself or human ‘Spirit’? Back to beauty or truth, as in still-older views?10 To politicalconsciousness-raising and social change?11 To keep “question[ing] the nature of art”itself, as the conceptual artist Joseph Kosuth claimed was the only remaining role of the

4 E.g. Pöllänen, 2011; Lynch, 2012; Karppinen, 2008, p. 87; cf. Meeson, 1991.5 Robinson, 2015, 250. Robinson’s focus is on how the world appears “to the artist or his/her persona”

when in emotional states, not on other kinds of individual or collective self-expression. See also Robinson 2005.

6 Riggle 2016, 192. Likewise, Baldini (2016, 188) argues that street art “reclaim[s] a right for individuals to express themselves visually in public space.”

7 Hegel 1975.8 Schiller 2014, 81–82.9 Schiller 1966, 111.10 On challenges to beauty as an ideal in modern art, see e.g. Steiner 2002; Pippin 2013. For a

representative sample of ongoing debates about the role of beauty in contemporary art, see Charlesworth and Harbison 2016.

11 On the famously controversial Whitney 1993 Biennial Exhibition, e.g., see Danto 2003, 103–124.

2

Page 3: Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

artist, in 1969?12 Or maybe just to create work that is “intentionally, but playfully,repellent”—as a bemused New York Times critic described a 2018 exhibition by theVienna-based art collective Gelitin, featuring ‘un-monumental’ massive realisticsculptures of “giant turds,” placed on Persian rugs “like welcome-home gifts left by ahuge, vengeful dog”?13

Here I will develop a different alternative to the idea of art as self-expression: anideal of creative receptivity to basic features of the external world, which I will callartistic objectivity. This differs from traditional notions of scientific objectivity, in crucialways.14 And it also differs from standard accounts of the objectivity (or subjectivity) ofaesthetic judgments, as in judging a given painting beautiful, insofar as these accountsoften prioritize the standpoint of the artistic audience or spectator of natural beauty.15

Artistic objectivity is instead an ideal for artistic practice itself, which thus prioritizes thestandpoint of the artist or creator. This shift in focus, from audience to artist, is arguably abroadly warranted corrective. For instance, Nietzsche claims that Kant deeplymisunderstands beauty precisely because he (“like all philosophers”) unduly privilegesthe aesthetic experience of the “spectator” over “the point of view of the artist (thecreator).”16 Regardless, inquiry into the point of view of the artist is a worthy subject inits own right, both for artists developing their own practice and for critical audiencesinterested in artistic creativity and its relation to artworks.

Artistic objectivity can provide a fruitful contrast to broadly Romantic artisticideals of individual or collective self-expression, which are arguably still pervasive, andat least lack clearly compelling successors. Elaborating a counter-ideal of receptivity canalso productively interrelate certain historical and ongoing artistic movements and artcritical approaches. In particular, here I will examine how it informs John Ruskin’sinfluential critique of the ‘pathetic fallacy’—that is, “false” perception induced by“violent feeling,”17 as in a mourning poet’s vision of inhuman objects silenced by grief—and his praise of the “feeling” that instead “loves a stone for a stone’s sake.”18 Ruskin’sview is related to broader anti-Romantic currents within Victorian and Modernist art,including Imagist poets’ stress on “exteriority” or depicting “things as they really are.”19

And it also arguably illuminates certain more recent work across a range of media,including Ansel Adams’s landscape photography and Andy Goldsworthy’s site-specificsculpture, alongside other modern environmental and abstract art, as I will elaborate later

12 Kosuth 1991, 18; see also Danto 1997, 13–14.13 Siegal 201814 Cf. Best’s claim that aesthetic and scientific judgments are objective “in precisely the same way” (Best

1980, 126).15 E.g. see Aldrich and Slatter 1978; Winterbourne 1981; Bonzon 1999; Parsons 2006.16 Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morals, Essay III, §6.17 Ruskin 2004, 71. Ruskin was “the most influential mid-Victorian aesthetician” (Garratt 2009, 53). On

his ongoing relevance to aesthetics, see e.g. Morris 1955; Landow 1971; cf. Bell 1963, 21. See also Logan 1940; Miles 1965; Hewison 1976; Wihl 1985; Teukolsky 2009.

18 Ruskin 1891, 183.19 Miles 1944. E.g. on ‘exteriority’, see Lowell 1920; on ‘things as they really are’, see Hulme 1960.

3

Page 4: Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

below. Finally, it helps to show why self-expression can be worth criticizing, even if notrejecting wholesale: it can easily become individualistic or anthropocentric—i.e. self-involved, whether individually or collectively. This is a general vice, but it can alsoproduce bad art. Receptivity is a general virtue, but also an artistic one that can yieldgood work, at least in one valuable style.20

As both a guide and foil, Ruskin’s view will help to motivate my own account ofartistic objectivity. Objective artists avoid both broadly Romantic drives to self-expression and scientific drives to represent things as they are ‘in themselves’, apart fromall ‘poetic license’ or ‘merely figurative’ description. Rather, for objective artists,receptivity to the broader world often manifests itself precisely in impassioned figurativedescription, along with other kinds of artistic creation. Imagine, for instance, that amusician hears a thunderstorm, that a certain quality of sound or rhythm within thethunder and rain catches her ear, and that she then composes a new song using this sonicform, abstracted from nature, as an artistically purified creative foundation. In so doing,she may disregard or exclude those parts of the original storm that had less impact on her.And she may even modify the central sounds or rhythmic forms that she does emphasize.But the artist’s “tremendous drive to bring out the main features so that the othersdisappear in the process,” as Nietzsche puts it,21 can still give her real artisticunderstanding of the storm, grounded in genuine creative receptivity to it. Likewise, anartist like Goldsworthy might gather red autumn leaves and shape them into an intenselysaturated monochromatic sculptural form, concentrating or intensifying the leaves’ redcolor beyond its naturally-given state, and in this sense falsifying it—yet in a way thatcan still reflect receptivity to the leaves’ aesthetic force.22

Objective artists are not trying to express themselves or reach self-knowledgethrough their creative acts. But they are also not disinterested or free of emotion. Theycan often be calm or unsentimental, however, in the way that mountains are calm andhurricanes are unsentimental: unmoved by personal feelings, if not all human concerns.Still, objective artists are receptive, not insensitive—just attuned to the more elementalforces by which they are impassioned and inspired.

2. Ruskin on Looking Outward to Strong Causes for True FeelingI will elaborate, contextualize, and motivate this ideal of artistic objectivity in

dialogue with Ruskin, by way of several basic questions. First, how can receptivity to thebroader world manifest itself precisely in artistic creation, which can seem soidiosyncratic to specific artists or cultures, or at least bound more by human perspectivethan science, for instance, appears to be? Second, how can artists actually go about beingreceptive, in practice, or avoid making work that is unintentionally self-expressive?

20 Here one might productively compare recent work in ‘virtue aesthetics’—see e.g. Woodruff, 2001.21 Twilight of the Idols, ‘Skirmishes of an Untimely Man’, §8. Note that Nietzsche’s emphasis is on

“idealization,” and arguably on artistic expression, directly by contrast to the kind of objectivity I stress.22 E.g. compare Red cherry leaf patch, Brough, Cumbria, 4 November 1984 (Goldsworthy 1990, 176).

4

Page 5: Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

Third, which parts of the broader world are truly worth being receptive to? Finally, whyidealize receptivity, or criticize self-expression, in the first place?

On each issue, Ruskin’s critique of the pathetic fallacy offers valuable food forthought—even though his view is unacceptable or demands refinement, in importantrespects, as it stands. It will thus prove helpful to first review some basic features of hisaccount. I will then approach the first two of the above questions, in this light, beforereturning to the last two, in later sections.

The term ‘pathetic fallacy’ is now often taken to refer to any case ofpersonification used as a poetic technique, regardless of its cause.23 But Ruskin insteaduses the term to refer to any misperception of the world induced by overwhelmingfeeling. ‘Feeling’ here includes not only ‘emotion’, but also ‘contemplative fancy.’24 Inturn, this sort of misperception can take the specific form of anthropomorphicdescriptions, as when poets personify natural objects under the influence of strongpassions—so that even a stream can seem ‘silenced by grief’. But Ruskin’s patheticfallacy is not restricted to this one kind of misperception, at least in principle.25

For Ruskin, in this light, a bad writer’s overreliance on pseudo-poetic expressionneed not simply be an affectation, as it can also indicate authentic sensitivity topassionate feelings and their falsifying effect (he suggests) on perception. This kind ofsensitive writer may be further inclined to project feelings onto nature under the influenceof a broadly Romantic ethos, like the one that Wordsworth articulates in describing hisown poem, ‘The White Doe of Rylstone’:

Throughout, objects[...]derive their influence not from properties inherent in them,not from what they are actually in themselves, but from such as are bestowed uponthem by the minds of those who are conversant with or affected by those objects.Thus the Poetry, if there be any in the work, proceeds whence it ought to do, fromthe soul of man, communicating its creative energies to the images of the externalworld.26

Ruskin prefers accurate poetic description of objects to this putative ‘communication’ ofthe poet’s own ‘energy’. Thus, recall his praise of “feeling” that “loves a stone for astone’s sake.”27

But deeper than Ruskin’s basic criticism of the pathetic fallacy is his further claimthat it can be justified, in a way, when ‘false’ perceptions reflect ‘true’ feelings with

23 This usage is apparent in (if not also derived from) common interpretations of Ruskin, as in Josephine Miles’s claim that he views the pathetic fallacy as “the attribution of human aspects and emotions to natural objects” (Miles 1944, 210; see also Miles 1965, 1).

24 Ruskin 2004, 70.25 Ruskin explicitly defines the ‘pathetic fallacy’ as the “falseness in all our impressions of external

things” that “violent feelings” induce (Ruskin, 2004, p. 71). But many of his examples do involve personification.

26 Wordsworth 1854, 395.27 Ruskin 1891, 183.

5

Page 6: Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

‘strong’ causes:

An inspired writer, in full impetuosity of passion, may speak wisely and truly of‘raging waves of the sea, foaming out their own shame’ [Jude 1:13]; but it is onlythe basest writer who cannot speak of the sea without talking of ‘raging waves’,‘remorseless floods’, ‘ravenous billows’ etc.; and it is one of the signs of thehighest power in a writer to check all such habits of thought, and to keep his eyesfixed firmly on the pure fact, out of which if any feeling comes to him or hisreader, he knows it must be a true one.28

Hence, Ruskin outlines a hierarchical order of “four classes.”29 First and lowest, there aretotally unpoetic people who “feel nothing, and therefore see truly.” Next, a “second orderof poets” comprises those who “feel strongly, think weakly, and see untruly.” In turn,“first order” poets “feel strongly, think strongly, and see truly.” Last and highest, thereare people “who, strong as human creatures can be, are yet submitted to influencesstronger than they, and see in a sort untruly, because what they see is inconceivablyabove them”—as in “prophetic inspiration.” But even accounting for this kind ofinspiration, Ruskin insists that “so far as it is a fallacy,” the pathetic fallacy is “always thesign of a morbid state of mind, and comparatively of a weak one.”30 “Even in the mostinspired prophet,” the pathetic fallacy is “a sign of the incapacity of his human sight orthought to bear what has been revealed to it.”31

Ruskin is wrong to claim that pathetic fallacies must reflect ‘morbidity’ or‘incapacity’. And it is fair to be critical of the stark opposition between reason andemotion that underlies his distinction between ‘true sight’ and ‘true feeling’. Emotionscan plausibly aid understanding, if not even be necessary for grasping certain truths.32 Butone can isolate a deeper ideal of artistic objectivity by reflecting on the link betweengreat poets like Homer who ‘see truly’ and inspired prophets who declaim with ‘falsesight’ but ‘true feeling’ under the sway of ‘higher’ powers.

Namely, both Ruskin’s ‘first order poets’ and inspired ‘prophets’ evidently lookoutward to strong external causes for true inspiration. This is one way to take his adviceto ‘keep eyes fixed firmly on the pure fact.’ Admittedly, another interpretation moreclosely tracks certain of his remarks: ‘Err on the side of purely literal description.’33 Butthis is a far less compelling creative ideal. The contrast between figurative and literal usesof language is less artistically salient, and narrower in scope, than is the contrast betweenideals of individual or collective self-expression and an outwardly-oriented ideal ofcreative receptivity to basic features of the world.

28 Ruskin 2004, 75.29 Ruskin 2004, 73–74.30 Ruskin 2004, 79.31 Ruskin 2004, 79.32 For extended discussion and defense of this basic idea, see e.g. Furtak 2018; Nussbaum 1990. I am

grateful to an anonymous referee for pressing me to stress this point, and for these references.33 Some commentators seem to read Ruskin this way—e.g. compare Miles 1944, 216.

6

Page 7: Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

To begin to delve deeper into this ideal, we may first examine why Ruskin thinksthat poetic acts like anthropomorphic description are misperceptions or fallacies, in thefirst place. In anachronistic terms, of course, one might instead distinguish between literaland figurative truth, or between truth and something like aptness.34 But Ruskin’s ownanalysis is more illuminating, with respect to my aim of motivating an ideal of artisticobjectivity and a correlative critique of self-expression. Namely, he characterizes “falseappearances” as those which are “entirely unconnected with any real power or characterin the object, and only imputed to it by us.”35 For example, when the poet CharlesKingsley writes of the sea’s “cruel, crawling foam,” Ruskin objects that “the foam is notcruel, neither does it crawl.”36 Presumably, then, he would deny that Kingsley’s metaphorreflects any ‘real power or character’ located ‘in’ the ocean.37 By contrast, he observesthat a gentian flower “has always the power” to produce sensations of blueness, andconcludes that “the gentian and the sky are always verily blue, whatever philosophy maysay to the contrary.”38 He thus spurns focus on the “objective” properties of things “inthemselves,” and de-emphasizes Lockean distinctions between primary and secondaryqualities.39 Notably, Locke would agree that blueness is ‘in’ the gentian, even in theabsence of perceiving subjects.40 But Ruskin still treats the distinction between primaryand secondary qualities as aesthetically irrelevant. Color may be neither ‘objective’ nor a‘primary’ quality, but for Ruskin this does not preclude a color’s ‘true’ description by‘first order’ poets.

This relates directly to my focus on the contrast between receptivity and self-expression. Ruskin’s hostility to figurative descriptions which are ‘only imputed to thingsby us’ is by direct contrast to Wordsworth’s aforementioned praise of ‘the soul of man,communicating its creative energies to the images of the external world.’ And Ruskin’spreference for focus on ‘powers’ that are instead truly located ‘in’ objects is related to hispraise of ‘loving a stone for a stone’s sake’. For Ruskin, evidently, an artist’s genuineopenness to the broader world must be matched by real powers in the broader world.Artistic objectivity requires both, not just one-sided receptivity.

Ruskin’s advice to err on the side of literal description can be more charitably

34 On these distinctions, more broadly, see Hills 1997.35 Ruskin 2004, 70.36 Ruskin 2004, 71.37 Cf. Arsić’s claim that Ruskin divides things into “doers and nondoers” rather than subjects and objects,

and takes a gentian’s ‘power’ to produce blueness sensations as paradigmatic of ‘doers’, or “generative forces,” which are thus neither ‘subjects’ nor ‘objects’ (Arsić 2017, 125). But if Ruskin believed in ‘generative forces’ and inert ‘nondoers’ instead of ‘people’ and ‘things’, as Arsić claims, then he would not think that any attribution of active forces like cruelty to impersonal natural objects is “false”—which is precisely his view, however. Arsić plausibly conflates Ruskin’s commitment to a broadly Lockean account of secondary qualities as real powers located in objects with a more radical rejection of the basic distinction between subjects and objects.

38 Ruskin 2004, 69.39 Ruskin naturally read Locke at Oxford (Collingwood 1971, 4). Note that Ruskin’s sense of ‘objective’

is distinct from mine, and closer to traditional notions.40 See Ch. VIII, Section 10 in An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Compare Ruskin 2004, 69.

7

Page 8: Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

recast in this light, as a concrete strategy for avoiding projection of one’s own feelingsonto nature. The feelings that one ‘finds’ in nature are all too often just one’s own, eitheras an individual or the bearer of a social collective—whether it be a specific culture orhumanity quite generally. For those like Wordsworth, this may be a virtue. But forRuskin, it is a vice. And he proposes avoiding this vice, fairly intuitively, by adopting aposture of defaulting to purely literal poetic descriptions. However, this does not precludethe possibility of some effective poetic use of the pathetic fallacy, on Ruskin’s view. Hejust takes truly inspired or prophetic uses of the pathetic fallacy to be earned, by strongcauses overcoming one’s real resistance to indulge in it. So, then, if one rejects Ruskin’sadvice to err on the side of literal truth, what might replace it, for those still compelled byhis basic call to look outward to strong causes for true feeling? And why in fact reject hisadvice to err on the side of narrowly literal truth—as I claim one should?

I have already raised one reason to reject Ruskin’s advice to err of the side ofliteral truth, earlier above: the contrast between figurative and literal uses of language isnarrower in scope than is the contrast between self-expression and creative receptivity tobasic features of the world. It is unclear, for example, how (if at all) Ruskin’s point aboutliteral truth might extend to the case of Goldsworthy creating an abstract sculptural formout of red leaves. To achieve a wider scope and broader utility for creative practice, then,an artist might instead defer to a slightly more abstract piece of advice, like ‘Focus on thebroader world, not on yourself.’

3. Expressive Qualities in Nature: Anthropomorphism vs. Anthropocentrism A second basic problem with Ruskin’s advice to err on the side of literal truth isthat artists’ invocation of expressive qualities in impersonal natural objects plausibly canreflect real powers that are genuinely located in these objects. Of course, the sea is anunfeeling object—not an anthropomorphic subject of cruelty, grief, or any other feeling.But why couldn’t the inhuman ocean still have a perfectly real power to elicit a figurativedescription of ‘cruel foam’, in poets like Kingsley? More broadly, could it not be that atleast some ‘pathetic fallacies’ in fact reflect the impact of real causal powers, located ‘in’objects just as much as their colors are ‘in’ them? In other words, one might distinguish(in a way that Ruskin does not) between feelings merely projected onto nature andfeelings that are immanent in nature in some truer sense—i.e. more objective feelings.Ruskin’s advice to err on the side of literal description is thus oversimplified.

Analyses of expressiveness in more recent aesthetic theory seem to provide anatural way to motivate this basic idea of expressive qualities truly located in impersonalnatural objects. Many modern aesthetic theorists who emphasize the expressive characterof art now disassociate it from self-expressive acts by artists, in a way that moretraditional expression theories of art did not.41 For instance, according to an ‘arousal’

41 E.g. Tolstoy 1995; Dewey 1934; Collingwood 1938. For defenses of Collingwood’s theory of expression, see e.g. Ridley 1998; Robinson 2005, 244–250; Hopkins 2017. Cf. Hospers 1955; Tormey 1971.

8

Page 9: Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

theory of musical expressiveness, the emotional expressiveness of a musical work orpassage consists in its power to induce corresponding emotions in a receptive listener.42

Hence an arousal theorist could, in principle, agree with Ruskin’s claim that great poets“watch” their feelings as if “from afar off,” even if their audiences do not.43 Likewise, anadvocate of a modern ‘resemblance’ or ‘contour’ theory, who claims that music’sexpressiveness consists in relations of resemblance between the contour of a givenmelody and the contour of typical behavioral manifestations or phenomenologicalfeatures of a corresponding emotion, could allow that even the most highly expressivemusical works are created by apparently “impassive” artists.44 In this light, then, eveninhuman natural objects can genuinely possess expressive qualities. That is, even ifSusanne Langer is right that works of art are “expressive forms,”45 or “images of feeling”which “mak[e] it visible or audible or in some way perceivable,”46 this alone would notdistinguish art from all natural beauty or sublimity. Of course, howling winds are not“created for our perception,” in the way that Langer takes art to be.47 But the wind neednot be made by or for us, let alone be able to feel, in order to be able to make feelingsperceivable or sensibly apparent to a receptive listener. For example, the ocean foammight have a contour truly resembling that of cruelty, despite Ruskin’s claim thatKingsley’s ‘cruel foam’ is a fallacy.

But modern aesthetic theories of expressiveness still cannot fully capture thedistinction between receptivity and self-expression. If one just invokes similarity incontour, for instance, then there is an overabundance of expressive qualities in nature—the sad weeping willow, the playful burbling brook, and so on ad infintum. It is thusnecessary to invoke a further distinction, between objective and subjective principles forartistically highlighting (or exaggerating) certain expressive qualities in nature and notothers. In other words, even granting that there are many expressive qualities in naturalobjects, e.g. in the sense of contour theories of expressiveness, we can ask: why does anartist notice the expressive qualities in nature that she does? In turn, some reasons fornoticing expressive qualities are self-expressive. For instance, a mourning poet mightnotice a relation of genuine resemblance between the contour of a willow and that of hisgrief because he is grieving. The identification of real expressive qualities in nature canthus still be a way of expressing one’s own feelings. Nor is this point restricted toindividual rather than collective self-expression. In a society that has suffered a civil war,for example, a poet might give expression to shared feelings of anger or loss, evenwithout viscerally experiencing them herself, by noticing just those contours in naturewhich correspond to these shared feelings.

42 See e.g. Matravers 1998.43 Compare Ruskin 2004, 75.44 For defenses of a ‘contour’ theory, see e.g. Kivy 1989; cf. e.g. Levinson 1996, 90–125. See also Budd

1985; Budd 2011; Davies 2011; Levinson 1982; Robinson 2005.45 Langer 1957, 15; compare Langer 1953.46 Langer 1957, 25.47 Langer 1957, 15.

9

Page 10: Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

Similarly, identifying expressive qualities in nature can be a collective expressionof human feeling more broadly—hence, a more abstract joint projection of ourselves ontonature. In this light, recall Langer’s view that artworks are ‘expressive forms,’ or ‘imagesof feeling.’ Notably, she here takes ‘feeling’ to include “everything that can be felt, fromphysical sensation, pain and comfort, excitement and repose, to the most complexemotions, intellectual tensions, or the steady feeling-tones of a conscious human life.”48

This broad notion of feeling is helpfully compared to Kant’s claim that taste is “a facultyfor the judging of the sensible rendering of moral ideas.”49 While moral ideas are notemotions, perhaps we can nevertheless feel and not merely think them, at least inaesthetic experience. Indeed, the sensuous presentation of ideas, whether in artworks orin beautiful natural phenomena, is perhaps precisely a way of allowing us to feel ideas, inthis sense. Hegel’s claim that “the sensuous in the work of art is itself something ideal,but which, not being ideal as thought is ideal, is still at the same time there externally as athing”50 is productively interpreted in this light, as broadly Kantian. So too, one shouldinterpret Schiller’s less famous but earlier suggestion that “in our pleasure inBeauty[...]reflection is so completely intermingled with feeling that we believe ourselvesto perceive form immediately.”51 Of course, not just any concrete particular counts as thesuccessful ‘sensuous presentation’ of a corresponding universal or idea, in the relevantsense. Good art makes it seem as if the universal or idea itself, not just a mere instance orpartial reflection thereof, is fully and viscerally present.

But why take the artistic creation of ‘images of feeling’ to be valuable? Again, wemay distinguish objective and subjective motivations. Subjectively, creating images offeeling can be a way to value our own capacity for the range of emotion, sensation, andintellectual activity which Langer outlines. As a “symbolic presentation of subjectivereality for contemplation,”52 art can thus be a way of valuing generic human subjectivity.In this light, recall Schiller’s claim that art is “the most complete possible expression ofmankind,” which induces states of ‘play’ or ‘freedom’ involving full reciprocal activationof our powers of sensibility and rational form.53 For Hegel, similarly, art is the sensuouspresentation of freedom. In art, material forms somehow still breathe with our shared‘spiritual’ essence—freedom, ideas, feeling. And this encapsulates the human condition:our nature is to be ‘embodied spirit’, conditioned as sensible beings and yet still free. Inshort, then, artistic images of feeling can be a collective self-expression of humanity.

For Hegel, however, collective self-expression through art also has a culturallyspecific dimension. On his account of classical Greek tragedy, for example, the chorus is“the actual substance of the moral life and action” of heroic individuals, or “the people as

48 Langer 1957, 15.49 Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment §60.50 Hegel 1975, 38.51 Schiller 2014, 96–97.52 Langer 1957, 24.53 Schiller 1966, 111.

10

Page 11: Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

the fruitful soil” out of which these heroes grow.54 This is particularly “appropriate,” headds, for an ancient Greek culture in which “moral complications cannot yet be met byspecific valid and just laws and firm religious dogmas,” but instead “the ethical orderappears only in its direct and living actuality.”55 The “essence of tragedy” then consists inan “opposition” of heroic individuals, each of whom is “justified in their action,” but whonevertheless encapsulate “the battle between the essential powers that rule human life andbetween the gods that dominate the human heart.”56 For instance, Antigone “ought to payobedience to the royal command,” on Hegel’s view, but “Creon too, as father andhusband, should have respected the sacred tie of blood” and observed proper burial ritesfor Polynices.57 Hence, Sophocles’s drama is a kind of sensuous expression of ancientGreek culture, which focalizes its institutionally-unresolved ethical tensions betweenfamilial love and patriotic duty.58 Art can thus be a collective expression, not just ofuniversal humanity, but also of specific historical cultures or subcultures.59 This is notobjectionable, in itself. But when it descends into ethnocentric myopia, it is. So too,insofar as human self-expression stems from our reactive desire to display our moralstatus as essentially free or autonomous beings, ultimately above and beyond any ‘mere’natural forces—a kind of anthropocentric interiority that closes us off to realdetermination by basic sources of value in the broader natural world—it is criticizable.

But more objective modes of identifying expressive qualities are possible. AndRuskin’s basic invocation of ‘powers’ is illuminating, here, although his specific accountof the kind of powers that are ‘in’ natural objects is overly restrictive. An identification ofexpressive qualities is objective insofar as it reflects the artist having been genuinelyimpacted and determined from without, not just external contours being occasions forindividual or collective self-expression. For instance, whereas a subjective poet might seethe rising sun as ‘joyous’ because he has recently fallen in love, a more objective poetmight feel or contemplate joy because he is moved by the sun’s awesome force. The suncan thus more truly inspire his poetry—whether about joy or human sorrow by contrast tothe sun’s joy. The crucial point is the sun’s power to elicit his art.

When I invoke real powers in natural objects to elicit creative acts by artists, notethat I am not associating this artistic receptivity with any conceptually-determinatefeatures of external things. That is, broadly like Kant claims that one cannot prove that agiven thing is beautiful simply by describing it in generic terms—rather, one always hasto “submit the object to his own eyes”60—I claim that artistic objectivity does not involve

54 Hegel 1975, 1211.55 Hegel 1975, 1211.56 Hegel 1975, 1206 and 1210.57 Hegel 1975, 1217.58 For a modern ‘structuralist’ account of myth, with similar focus on laying bare culturally-specific

tensions, see Lévi-Strauss 1955.59 For a structuralist-inspired account of genre film, including the “conflict between civilization and

savagery” in Western genre film, vis-à-vis a distinctively American frontier mythos, see also Schatz 1981.

60 Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, §8.

11

Page 12: Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

receptivity to the kind of empirical fact that is amenable to objective scientificdescription. What the objective musician hears in the thunder, or what the objectivesculptor sees in the red leaves, eludes non-artistic or non-aesthetic perception. Aselaborated below, this view is not mystical or supernatural, just anti-scientistic. Note alsothat this is not a description of Ruskin’s view. It is a view that I am advancing, indialogue with Ruskin—who, again, explicitly denies that the ocean has this kind of realpower.

In this light, then, we may tease apart several threads of Ruskin’s appeal to “theordinary, proper, and true appearances of things to us.”61 In particular, it will provehelpful to reflect on why he takes the ‘ordinary, proper, and true’ to exclude phenomenalike Kingsley’s ‘cruel foam.’ First, Ruskin could deny that the ocean has any real powerto produce feelings (ideas, etc.) of cruelness in Kingsley, as the sky produces sensationsof blueness in us. But this is questionable. For instance, recall my earlier example of amusician composing a song, inspired by a certain sound or rhythm in a thunderstorm thatshe hears: why deny the storm its real power, here? Moreover, in cases of propheticinspiration, Ruskin62 himself acknowledges that pathetic fallacies can stem fromoverwhelming religious feeling—and hence, presumably, from the real power of God.Ruskin’s emphasis on creative inspiration by God helps to intuitively motivate my ownwider notion of creative receptivity to real powers located in external things, even thoughRuskin himself evidently rejects this extension of ‘real powers’ to things like the ocean.

Second, Ruskin could distinguish the intersubjective validity of sensations ofblueness when looking at the sky from the personal or idiosyncratic quality of Kingsley’spoetic response to the ocean. A serious problem with invoking intersubjective validity inthis context, however, is that the highest poetic experiences of expressive qualities innature are not ‘ordinary’. And they arguably are not available—even in principle—to allnormally-functioning people, in the way that the sky’s blueness is. Not everyone is agreat poet, after all. One might object that a poetic description of expressive qualities innature is as intersubjectively valid (or not) as any aesthetic judgment, or at least anyclaim about the aptness of a given metaphor. And people can evidently evaluate theaptness of a given metaphor without having the creative capacity to produce it. But here itis helpful to distinguish between real powers in natural objects to elicit figurativedescriptions in poets and (on the other hand) real powers in these figurative descriptionsto elicit aesthetic experiences in audiences who read or hear them. Even supposing thataesthetic judgments are intersubjectively valid, this validity is presumably related to thesecond kind of power, not the first. But one should focus on the first kind of power, toelicit creative responses in artists, when assessing whether or not a given pathetic fallacyconstitutes a ‘true appearance’.

Finally, Ruskin elsewhere distinguishes between fire itself being “ravenous andpitiless” and “something in this fire” that “rages,” before relating this ‘something’ to the

61 Ruskin 2004, 70.62 Ruskin 2004, 79.

12

Page 13: Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

Greek gods:

It seems to me that the Greek had exactly the same instinctive feeling aboutthe elements that we have ourselves; that to Homer, as much as to Casimir dela Vigne, fire seemed ravenous and pitiless; to Homer, as much as to Keats,the sea-wave appeared wayward or idle, or whatever else it may be to thepoetical passion. But then the Greek reasoned upon this sensation, saying tohimself: “I can light the fire, and put it out; I can dry this water up, or drink it.It cannot be the fire or the water that rages, or that is wayward. But it must besomething i n this fire and i n the water, which I cannot destroy byextinguishing the one, or evaporating the other, any more than I destroymyself by cutting off my finger[...]So there may be a power in the waterwhich is not water, but to which the water is as a body[...]This something, thisGreat Water Spirit, I must not confuse with the waves, which are only itsbody. They may flow hither and thither, increase or diminish. That must beindivisible—imperishable—a god.63

Paganism is blasphemous, for Ruskin, as a devout Christian. However, it is “not thematerialism, but the vice, which degrades the [Greek] conception [of deities].” Because“there is always some sense of exaltation in the spiritual and immortal body” here, “thematerialism itself is never positive, or complete.”64 Ruskin therefore sees Greek myths asdeeply, albeit only partly, true. Namely, for Ruskin, the basic truth underlying thepagan’s appeal to a Great Water Spirit, located in the sea as a “spirit” occupies its“body,”65 is the reality of a higher spiritual domain.

Ruskin’s view is not narrowly scientistic, then, even though he sees descriptionsrooted in prophetic inspiration as ‘fallacies’. A Biblical invocation of mountains singingand trees clapping before God still involves a pathetic fallacy, for instance, albeit a“noble” one grounded in “true” feeling.66 Ruskin sees it as literally true that there aredivine powers, which he relates without fail to the singular God of his Christian faith.The Greeks thus avoided the pathetic fallacy by attributing powers to gods, rather than toobjects like the sea. This is why there is no ‘real power’ in the sea, on Ruskin’s view, andhence why he always takes figurative descriptions like Kingsley’s to be ‘false’. I willreturn to this point shortly below, with an eye towards modifying Ruskin’s view so as toreach a more secularized and naturalistic position.

But before doing so, we may first review some central results of the abovediscussion. First, how can receptivity to the broader world manifest itself precisely inartistic creation? Here the crucial point is that the personal, cultural, or human quality of

63 Ruskin 1859, 175–176.64 Ruskin 1859, 176.65 Ruskin 1859, 176.66 Ruskin 2004, 77.

13

Page 14: Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

artistic response is not a barrier, in itself, to receptivity. The presumption that receptivitymust track external things’ intersubjectively available or conceptually-determineproperties is a scientistic misconception. Ruskin’s notion of ‘true’ appearances isbeholden to this traditional epistemological framework. But more satisfactory accounts ofcreative receptivity should allow that the relevant kind of ‘real power’ interactsspecifically with artists, not with their audiences, let alone all human beings.

Second, how can artists actually go about being receptive, in practice, or avoidmaking unintentionally self-expressive work? Ruskin’s concrete advice to err on the sideof purely literal description should be refined, both because it is narrow in scope andbecause there plausibly can be expressive qualities genuinely located in impersonalnatural objects. But modern theories of expressiveness are still incapable, in themselves,of adequately capturing the distinction which is relevant here, between subjective andobjective expressive qualities in nature. Invoking real powers in objects to elicit creativeacts by artists is more directly to the point. Anthropomorphic descriptions of nature neednot be anthropocentric, insofar as they can be genuinely elicited by real powers in naturalobjects, more so than emanating from within artists. Still, both artist and nature can playactive roles, even if their interaction is thus hierarchical. What practical advice remains,then, for artists aspiring to objectivity? First, focus on the broader world, not yourself.Second, be open to genuine inspiration from without, but do not try to be inspired. Thiscaptures the kernel of truth in Ruskin’s advice to not try to be moved to use poeticlanguage. Finally, be skeptical if you find yourself ‘inspired’ by too many things. Thescientistic person is not open to artistic inspiration; but the Romantic is insteadhypersensitive—that is, receptive to too much, in a way that can often reflect anunderlying anthropocentric preoccupation with human feeling.

4. Objectivity contra Individualism, Anthropocentrism, and HypersensitivityIn this light, finally, we may return to the two other questions that I raised earlier

above: Which parts of the broader world are worth being receptive to? And why idealizereceptivity, or reject self-expression, in the first place? These are interrelated and so bestapproached at once.

One reason to value receptivity and not self-expression is that we can overlookimportant features of our surroundings, like aesthetically impactful formal details ofnatural environments, if we are inwardly rather than outwardly focused. Artists projectingtheir feelings onto nature can thus be criticizable in broadly the way that spectators arewhen they misinterpret an artwork by seeing it as more about their own lives than it reallyis. We often cannot appreciate all that nature or art has to offer, aesthetically andotherwise, without allowing it to draw us out of ourselves.

To reach deeper than this crucial but basic point, however, we must distinguishdifferent senses of the ‘broader world’ to which an objective artist could be attuned.Depending on what one takes it to be, a stance of creative receptivity can have further

14

Page 15: Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

value in different ways. One might view the ‘broader world’ as comprising everythingbeyond the horizons of one’s own individual experience or personal concerns. But onemight also view it from a more collective standpoint, as comprising everything beyondthe human or artificial. Finally, following Ruskin, one might instead view the ‘broaderworld’ as comprising only its ‘strongest’ forces, like God.67

If one focuses on a contrast between the (subjective) individual and (objective)collective, then stressing an ideal of objectivity in art can be part of a broader critique ofhyper-individualistic tendencies in contemporary liberal societies. By contrast, one mightvalue artistic self-expression in line with a broader praise of individuality and self-determination in liberal political philosophy and ethics. This is one way to contextualizeRiggle’s implicit view that it is valuable to “express ourselves in public” and “be seen forwho we are or aspire to be,” as he takes street art to allow.68

But my own focus here has been more on the contrast between the human orartificial and the inhuman or natural. One reason for this is that I take ideals of collectiveself-expression, like broadly Hegelian views of art as the sensuous self-representation ofSpirit or historical cultural feeling, to now be more common in aesthetics and artcriticism than are individualistic ideals. A major problem with the paradigm of art ascollective human or cultural self-expression, however, is that it runs the risk ofanthropocentrism. By contrast, then, objectivity can be valuable insofar as it is part of abroader anti-anthropocentric ethos. This might be connected, for instance, to the traditionof ‘deep ecology’ in environmental ethics, which treats ecological systems as inherentlyvaluable.69 Regardless, it is worth envisioning forms of art which respect nature, withoutsentimentalizing it.

One might object to this, of course. Is it not also bad to be self-effacing, forinstance? And why not value ourselves, either as individuals or collectively as human?First, however, note that an ideal of receptivity need not be self-effacing. Indeed, abroadly Ruskin-style appeal to ‘strong’ causes is one way to ensure that it is not: if weonly idealize receptivity to certain especially important features of the world beyondourselves, then the result is not self-effacing in any pejorative sense. Moreover, as Iacknowledged earlier, both an artist and any external powers to which he is receptivehave active (not just passive) roles to play, in the interactions that yield objective art. It isjust that the artist’s highest creative activity is rooted in his ability to respond to powersbeyond himself. One also need not treat a given power in the natural world—say, athunderstorm or the ocean—as ‘above’ oneself in all contexts, in order to do so in certain

67 Compare especially Ruskin 2004, 74–75. However, Ruskin does also sometimes intimate the first or second notions—e.g. he says that a “great” man is not “in any wise shaken” by “that which immediatelyaffects him,” but attuned to “the past and future, and[...]all things beside and around” (Ruskin 2004, 74). This suggests a quite traditional notion of objectivity—as a ‘view from nowhere’ or universally-valid standpoint, independent of subjects’ idiosyncratic capacities or personal experiences (Nagel 1986).

68 Ruskin 2016, 192.69 See e.g. Naess, 1973; Naess, 1984; cf. Watson, 1983; see also Lynch, 1996.

15

Page 16: Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

acts of artistic creation. Finally, note that it is possible to value ourselves, either asindividuals or jointly as human, without treating ourselves as the center of reality, or themost valuable thing. We can value ourselves appropriately without treating humanity as akind of secularized God.

But even if we should not deify humanity, why place any part of nature aboveourselves? One reason is just that this offers another rich source of artistic inspiration; so,why close oneself off to it unnecessarily? More deeply, however, it helps to frame thisissue in somewhat broader context. For Ruskin, as a pious Christian, the paradigmatic‘strong’ cause of ‘true’ feeling is clearly God. Hence, his notion of ‘strength’ evidentlycombines moral and physical senses, although his dominant emphasis is arguably on theformer, moralized sense.70 In turn, Ruskin’s talent for close description should be viewedin this light. He values only “detail referred to a great end,” not “detail sought for its ownsake”71—where again ‘greatness’ is religiously inflected. He thus takes the painter JohnConstable’s “morbid preference of subjects of a low order” to reflect “want ofveneration.”72 (One can only imagine what he might say about Gelitin.)

For current adherents of Christianity and similar religions, this may all seemappropriate. After all, as Feuerbach observes, “religious sentiment” evidently “looks at allthings through the medium of religion, it sees all in God,[…]sees all in images and as animage.”73 But in light of long-standing processes of secularization within modernWestern societies, it is also productive to think about where ‘divine’ strength has beenculturally reinvested since Ruskin wrote on the pathetic fallacy in 1856, to the extent thatthe ‘death of God’ has not just left behind a nihilistic void. Some traits previouslyattributed to God have arguably been displaced onto humanity—or, as Feuerbach andMarx would say, reclaimed for humanity after a period of religious alienation in whichwe mistook human self-consciousness for consciousness of God. The ultimate result ofthis process, according to Marx, is thus “the doctrine that man is the supreme being forman.”74 But secularization might also (or instead) involve reinvesting ‘divine’ strengthinto nature. Basic natural entities like the ocean, or primal phenomena like time, cycles ofseasonal change, or life and death, are fair candidates for powers beyond and strongerthan ourselves, in certain ways that merit deep respect. In turn, this basic respect can begiven distinctively artistic modes of outlet.

Modern or contemporary examples of art that is informed by this sort ofsecularized but profound respect for nature plausibly include Ansel Adams’s large-scalelandscape photography and Andy Goldsworthy’s site-specific sculptures constructed

70 E.g. compare Ruskin’s discussion of pathetic fallacies in two Biblical passages (Ruskin, 2004, p. 77), aswell as his subsequent discussion of a pathetic fallacy from the poet Edward Young, describing (in Ruskin's words) “the character of a truly good and holy man” (Ruskin, 2004, p. 78).

71 Ruskin 1858, xxx.72 Ruskin 1858, 92.73 Feuerbach 1957, 95.74 Tucker 1978, 60.

16

Page 17: Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

from natural materials and without tools.75 Notably, in this light, Goldsworthy is oftenself-consciously working to “understand” natural materials like a certain kind of stone oryellow shade in autumn leaves.76 Or consider the California poet Robinson Jeffers’sdepiction of a devastating wildfire, in a 1932 poem: “The deer were bounding like blownleaves/ Under the smoke in front of the roaring wave of the brush-fire;/ I thought of thesmaller lives that were caught./ Beauty is not always lovely; the fire was beautiful, theterror/ Of the deer was beautiful.”77 Jeffers’s description is clearly respectful, even as it isalso strikingly unsentimental. This differs from Ruskin’s more moralized view of God’sstrength, but also from moralized notions of the sublime in Romantic landscape painting.Like Adams’s epic wilderness and Goldsworthy’s primal colors and biomorphic forms,Jeffers’s nature—from “roaring” fire to the “merciless black” and “merciless blue” of theburnt hills and bright sky in its aftermath78—is a far cry from the ‘heavenly’ glowingclouds and gentle herd animals in Albert Bierstadt’s Among the Sierra NevadaMountains, California (1868).

An anti-anthropocentric form of creative receptivity to the broader natural worldneed not manifest itself in art that is so overtly concerned with nature, though.79 In close,high-contrast depictions of human body parts like interlocking fingers or crooked elbowsresting on crossed legs, for instance, the German-British photographer Bill Brandtachieves a similar effect. Human bodies are reframed as centers of natural form andmotion, in their own right—not ‘objectified’, in any standard sense, but rather naturalizedor made impersonal, like stones and flooding ocean tides (compare Brandt, 1977). In thislight, moreover, note that the relevant sense of the ‘natural world’ beyond the human orartificial may well be quite abstract. Hence, for example, it may even encompass visceralsensory qualities, like the glowing fields of textured color in a Mark Rothko painting; orthe ethereal wash of ambient frequencies in Alvin Lucier’s I Am Sitting in a Room(1969/70), a multi-media work in which Lucier records himself narrating a brief text,plays the recording back into a room, and re-records this output, repeatedly, until theoriginal sound of his voice has been transformed into a cadenced ebb and flow of theresonant frequencies of the room itself.80

While each of these examples merits further examination, here they functionadequately even as suggestive illustrations. Rather than elaborating these cases, then, itwill prove more illuminating to conclude by partly spanning the art historical gapbetween them and Ruskin’s mid-19th-century critique. Ruskin is broadly critical of BritishRomantic poetry—and of what he sees as the more disingenuous sentimentality of 18th-century poets like Pope.81 More positively, though, Josephine Miles has argued

75 Compare Adams 1992, Goldsworthy 1990.76 Riedelsheimer 2003.77 Jeffers 1938, 359.78 Jeffers 1938, 359.79 I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for pressing me to emphasize this point.80 Lucier 1990.81 Ruskin 2004, 78.

17

Page 18: Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

compellingly that Ruskin’s view fits into a broader shift in Victorian poetic use of thepathetic fallacy, away from simple appeal to emotions shared between people and genericnatural objects, and towards a “new emphasis on color, atmosphere, texture, ‘the thing initself’ with its adjectival discriminations.”82 (On Miles’s telling, this shift was alsomediated by younger Romantics like Keats and Shelley, for whom the “world feels apartfrom man”—e.g. Keats writes of the shore, “Full of calm joy it was, as I of grief”—andsensory qualities like “shape, hue, odour, and sweet sound” become the “new agents offeeling.”83 In turn, this new Victorian emphasis on “objectivity” construed as closeattention to the individual “thing in itself,” using “the qualifying and discriminatingadjective,” positively influenced currents within Modernist poetics stressing “[t]hequality of the thing, not our feeling about it.”.84

In particular, Miles highlights Imagism’s call to “interest in the object ‘for its ownsake,’” or “stress on the object’s own perceivable qualities and textures.”85 Here theImagist poet Amy Lowell’s own account of the distinctively “modern” poetic virtue of“Externality” is noteworthy:

I do not call it “objectivity” advisedly. I do not mean that this [modern] poetryis objective rather than subjective. I mean that it concerns itself with man in hisproper relation to the universe, rather than as the lord and master of it. It is thisattitude which leads to so many poems on nature, on effects of trees and skyand water, by themselves, with no hint of the “pathetic fallacy” to heighteninterest.86

“By ‘externality’,” Lowell elaborates elsewhere, “I mean the attitude of being interestedin things for themselves and not because of the effect they have upon oneself.”87 Thisnotion is helpfully compared to Lowell’s description of “exteriority” as “thecharacteristic modern touch”:

“Interiority” was the fashion; a poet examined his mental processes under amicroscope.[...]Somehow, that fashion worked itself out, and “exteriority,” as Ihave called the characteristic modern touch, came in. By this extremelyawkward word, “exteriority,” I mean an interest in the world apart fromoneself, a contemplation of nature unencumbered by the “pathetic fallacy.” It isthe reason of the picture-making of the modern poet. Picture-making theseother men gave us, but the Modern gives us picture-making without

82 Miles 1944, 214. Compare Miles 1965, 32–44. See also Prettejohn 2007.83 Miles 1965, 29; see also Miles 1965, 100.84 Miles 1944, 210. See also Cianci and Nicholls 2001; Feldman 2002; Teukolsky,2009.85 Miles 1944, 210.86 Lowell 1917, 106.87 Lowell 1916, 124.

18

Page 19: Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

comment.88

Lowell only meant to be “labeling” and “not condemning” the “internality” or“subjectivity” of “the poets of the late Victorian epoch”89—as she saw them, contraMiles’s more subtle analysis. For Lowell, that is, “in the world of the arts [egoism] isperfectly permissible,” and indeed “makes very good and very interesting poetry.” It isjust “not the manner of to-day [1916].”

Lowell’s notion of ‘Externality’ is closely related both to my own account ofartistic objectivity and to Ruskin’s criticism of the pathetic fallacy. This is no accident: Imean to be refining and creatively extending a long-standing counter-Romantic tradition.As I suggested above, this tradition also arguably extends to some modern environmentaland abstract art. Part of my original contribution to this counter-Romantic traditionconcerns my analysis of the relevant notion of the ‘universe’ to which man should, asLowell suggests, stand in ‘proper relation.’ Does this universe comprise everything? Oreverything holy, or natural, or powerful?

Receptivity to everything beyond one’s immediate environment is indiscriminate,if not also unduly self-effacing. Qua indiscriminate, receptivity to everything beyondone’s immediate environment is also ironically similar to the Romantic poet’shypersensitivity to any and all features of his natural surroundings—such that everyflower, insect, and cloud becomes a sign of God or a pantheistic ‘World Soul’. Consider,in this light, the “physical consciousness of a universally infused emotion” in both Blakeand Erasmus Darwin,90 echoed and even intensified in second-generation Romantics likeKeats or Shelley.91 But this Romantic enthusiasm also has a less sentimental correlate inindiscriminate applications of the kind of close attention to the individual “thing in itself”which Miles92 associates with both Victorian poets’ shifting use of the pathetic fallacyand Imagists’ subsequent emphasis on ‘Externality’.

Ruskin instead views the broader world to which the best artists are mostreceptive as being centered on especially ‘strong’ powers, paradigmatically like God. Hisnotion of strength is thus moralized. But an amoral notion of strength is more plausible,in application to nature.

Nature can be kind—but nature is not kind, as a rule. The ‘divine’ powers locatedin the ocean or the flame are neither moral nor immoral. They are amoral. Ruskin himselfseems close to acknowledging this, when he describes the Greek gods. But he thenappears to lose clarity on this point in moments where his Christianity reasserts itself. Totruly love a stone for a stone’s sake, as Ruskin claims to advocate, should in part be tofrankly acknowledge that a stone’s values are not human values. To value morally is to

88 Lowell 1920, 215.89 Lowell 1916 ,124.90 Miles 1965, 17.91 Miles 1965, 27–28.92 Miles 1944, 216.

19

Page 20: Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

treat humanity as an end in itself—to be what Marx called a ‘universal’ or ‘speciesbeing’. Hence, to read moral values into nature, even as its purely transcendent cause orground, is arguably to project ourselves onto it. Or, as Marx says more approvingly, tomake man the supreme being for man is ultimately to treat nature as no more than ourown “inorganic body.”93

This is anathema to artistic objectivity, construed as creative receptivity to basicfeatures of the external world. Humanity is not the center of reality, and artists who treatus as if we were inevitably fail to present the world ‘as it really is’ or nature ‘for its ownsake’. Instead, they only ever present us back to ourselves. Like Wordsworth, that is, theyonly ever show us ‘the soul of man, communicating its creative energies to the images ofthe external world.’

5. ConclusionIdeals of art as self-expression remain more prevalent than they might seem,

especially if one allows that the ‘self’ in question can be a human collective, not just anindividual artist. These self-expressive ideals run the risk of self-involvement, however—whether it be in the form of individualism or anthropocentrism. In this light, I haveworked to develop a counter-ideal of artistic objectivity, or creative receptivity to basicfeatures of the external world. I focused primarily on a version of this ideal whichemphasizes the contrast between human beings and the broader natural world‚ although Ipointed out that anti-individualistic and anti-ethnocentric versions are also salient. Ratherthan deifying human freedom or self-determining ‘Spirit’, an anti-anthropocentric versionof the basic ideal of artistic objectivity instead fundamentally values our dynamic relationto the broader natural world—including the possibility of creative determination byimpersonal forces.

In this light, I argued that Ruskin’s specific advice to err on the side of literaldescription is flawed, while defending his basic appeal to look outward to ‘strong’ causesfor ‘true’ feeling. Contra Ruskin, there plausibly can be expressive qualities truly locatedin impersonal natural objects. But modern aesthetic theories of expressiveness areincapable, in themselves, of adequately capturing the distinction between subjective andobjective artistic creation. Invoking objects’ real powers to elicit creative acts by artists ismore to the point. Anthropomorphic descriptions need not be anthropocentric, then,insofar as they can be elicited by real powers in natural objects, more so than emanatingfrom within artists. Unlike the blueness of the sky, though, the powers that elicitobjective art may affect artists but not ‘typical’ people. To accept the existence of powersof this kind, and their real interactions with artists, is not mysticism or supernaturalism. Itis to reject scientism, and to see art as a natural phenomenon in its own right.

I used this framework to motivate several pieces of practical advice: focus on thebroader world, not yourself; be open to genuine inspiration from without, but do not try

93 Tucker 1978, 75.

20

Page 21: Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

to be inspired; and be skeptical if you find yourself ‘inspired’ by too many things.Finally, I suggested that a broad notion of artistic objectivity can illuminate not onlyVictorian poetry and certain currents within Modernism, like Amy Lowell’s emphasis on‘exteriority’, but also recent movements in land and environmental art. Ruskin’smoralized notions of ‘strong’ cause and ‘true’ feeling are especially inappropriate in thiscontext, because the natural world is largely inhuman and amoral.

Ruskin is closer to correct when he keeps his own eye fixed firmly on the purefact. Not the pure empirical fact, but the pure poetic fact—the fact that includes‘something in this fire and in the water’ which may rage or be wayward. Ruskin says thatit is ‘not the materialism, but the vice,’ which ‘degrades’ the Greek conception of thegods. But the reality of the Greek gods, such as it is, is tied precisely to this ‘vice’. Theravenousness and pitilessness of the wildfire are not just ideas. Nor is the gentleness ofthe breeze, though, or the life-giving power of the earth—of course.

Objective artists look outward to strong external causes for true inspiration. Theyare not trying to express themselves or reach collective self-knowledge through their art.But they are also not disinterested or devoid of emotion. They can be broadly calm orunsentimental, in the way that mountains are calm and hurricanes are unsentimental:unmoved by personal feelings, if not all human concerns. Still, objective artists arereceptive, not insensitive—just attuned to the more elemental forces by which they areimpassioned and creatively inspired.94

WORKS CITED

Abrams, M. H. (1953). The Mirror and the Lamp: Romantic Theory and the Critical Tradition. Oxford: OUP.

Adams, A. (1992). Our National Parks. Edited by A. G. Stillman and W. A. Turnage. Boston: Little, Brown.

Aldrich, V. C. and Slatter, P. E. (1978). ‘Aesthetic Perception and Objectivity’. The British Journal of Aesthetics, 18, pp. 209–216.

Arsić, B. (2017). ‘Materialist Vitalism or Pathetic Fallacy: The Case of the House of Usher’. Representations, 140(1), pp. 121–136.

Baldini, A. (2016). ‘Street Art: A Reply to Riggle’. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 74, pp. 187–191.

Bell, Q. (1963). Ruskin. Edinburgh: Oliver and Boyd.Best, D. (1980). ‘The Objectivity of Artistic Appreciation’. The British Journal of Aesthetics, 20,

pp. 115–127.Bonzon, R. (1999). ‘Aesthetic Objectivity and the Ideal Observer Theory’. The British Journal of

Aesthetics, 39, pp. 230–240.Brandt, B. (1977). Shadow of Light: Photographs. New York: Da Capo Press.Budd, M. (1985). Music and the Emotions: The Philosophical Theories. London: Routledge &

94 Thanks to Pavel Godfrey, Daniel Herwitz, Ross Martin, Filipa Melo Lopes, and Peter Railton for valuable feedback on earlier versions. I am also grateful to two reviewers for very helpful comments.

21

Page 22: Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

Kegan Paul.Budd, M. (2011). ‘Music’s Arousal of Emotions’, in Gracyk, T. and Kania, A. (eds), The

Routledge Companion to Philosophy and Music. New York: Routledge, pp. 233–42.Charlesworth, J. J. and Harbison, I. (2016). ‘Head to Head: Does Beauty Still Matter in Art?’.

Tate Etc., 36, pp. 24–25.Cianci, G. and Nicholls, P. (2001). Ruskin and Modernism. London: Palgrave Macmillan.Collingwood, R. G. (1938). The Principles of Art. Oxford: OUP.Collingwood, R. G. (1971). Ruskin’s Philosophy. Chichester, Sussex: Quentin Nelson.Danto, A. C. (1997). After the End of Art: Contemporary Art and the Pale of History. Princeton,

NJ: Princeton University Press.Danto, A. C. (2003). ‘Beauty and Politics’, in his The Abuse of Beauty: Aesthetics and the

Concept of Art. Chicago: Open Court, pp. 103–124.Davies, S. (2011). ‘Emotional Contagion from Music to Listener’, in his Musical Understandings

and Other Essays on the Philosophy of Music. Oxford, pp. 47–65.Dewey, J. (1934). Art as Experience. New York: Minton, Balch & Co.Feldman, J. R. (2002). Victorian Modernism: Pragmatism and the Varieties of Aesthetic

Experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Feuerbach, L. (1957). The Essence of Christianity. Translated by G. Elliot. New York: Harper.Furtak, R. A. (2018). Knowing Emotions: Truthfulness and Recognition in Affective Experience.

Oxford: OUP.Garratt, P. (2009). ‘Ruskin's Modern Painters and the Visual Language of Reality’. Journal of

Victorian Culture, 14, pp. 53–71.Green, M. S. (2007). Self-Expression. Oxford: OUP.Goldsworthy, A. (1990). Hand to Earth: Andy Goldsworthy Sculpture 1976–1990. Edited by

Friedman, T. and Goldsworthy, A. Leeds: The Henry Moore Centre for the Study of Sculpture.

Hegel, G. W. F. (1975). Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Arts. Translated by T. M. Knox. Oxford: Clarendon.

Hewison, R. (1976). John Ruskin: The Argument of the Eye. London: Thames & Hudson.Hills, D. (1997). ‘Aptness and Truth in Verbal Metaphor’. Philosophical Topics, 25, pp. 117–153.Hopkins, R. (2017). ‘Imaginative Understanding, Affective Profiles, and the Expression of

Emotion in Art’. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 75, pp. 363–374.Hospers, J. (1955). ‘The Concept of Artistic Expression’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society,

55, pp. 313–344Hulme, T. E. (1960). Speculations. Edited by H. Read. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Jeffers, R. (1938). The Selected Poetry of Robinson Jeffers. New York: Random House.Kant, I. (2000). Critique of the Power of Judgment. Translated by P. Guyer and E. Matthews.

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Karppinen, S. (2008). ‘Craft-Art as a Basis for Human Activity’. The International Journal of Art

& Design Education, 27, pp. 83–90.Kivy, P. (1989). Sound Sentiment: An Essay on the Musical Emotions, including the complete

text of ‘The Corded Shell’. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.Kosuth, J. (1991). ‘Art after Philosophy’, in his Art After Philosophy and After: Collected

Writings, 1966–1990. Edited by G. Guercio. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, pp. 13–32.Landow, G. P. (1971). The Aesthetic and Critical Theories of John Ruskin. Princeton, NJ:

Princeton University Press.

22

Page 23: Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

Langer, S. K. (1953). Feeling and Form: A Theory of Art. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.Langer, S. K. (1957). ‘Expressiveness’, in her Problems of Art: Ten Philosophical Lectures. New

York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, pp. 13–26.Lévi-Strauss, C. (1955). ‘The Structural Study of Myth’. The Journal of American Folklore, 68,

pp. 428–444.Levinson, J. (1982). ‘Music and Negative Emotion’. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 63, pp.

327–346.Levinson, J. (1996). The Pleasures of Aesthetics. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Locke, J. (1998). An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Edited by P. H. Nidditch. Oxford:

OUP.Logan, J. V. (1940). ‘Wordsworth and the Pathetic Fallacy’. Modern Language Notes, 55, pp.

187–191.Lowell, A. (1916). ‘The New Manner in Modern Poetry’. The New Republic, 6, pp. 124–125.Lowell, A. (1917). ‘A Consideration of Modern Poetry’. The North American Review, 205, pp.

103–117.Lowell, A. (1920). Six French Poets: Studies in Contemporary Literature. New York: Macmillan.Lucier, A. (1990). I Am Sitting in a Room [Sound recording]. New York: Lovely Music, Ltd.Lynch, T. (1996). ‘Deep Ecology as an Aesthetic Movement’. Environmental Values. 5, pp. 147–

160.Lynch, G. H. (2012). ‘Encouraging Self-Expression Through Art’. Available at

https://www.pbs.org/parents/thrive/encouraging-self-expression-through-art (Accessed 10 August 2020).

Matravers, D. (1998). Art and Emotion. Oxford: Clarendon.Meeson, P. (1991). ‘The Influence of Modernism on Art Education’. British Journal of

Aesthetics, 31, pp. 103–110.Miles, J. (1944). ‘The Pathetic Fallacy and the Thing in Itself’. Poetry, 63, pp. 210–218. Miles, J. (1965). Pathetic Fallacy in the Nineteenth Century: A Study of a Changing Relation

Between Object and Emotion. New York: Octagon.Morris, B. (1955). ‘Ruskin on the Pathetic Fallacy, or on How a Moral Theory of Art May Fail’.

The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 14, pp. 248–266.Naess, A. (1973). ‘The shallow and the deep, long-range ecology movement. A summary’.

Inquiry, 16, pp. 95–100.Naess, A. (1984). ‘A Defence of the Deep Ecology Movement’. Environmental Ethics, 6, pp.

265–270.Nagel, T. (1986). The View from Nowhere. Oxford: OUP.Nietzsche, F. (1976). Twilight of the Idols, in Kaufmann, W. (ed and trans), The Portable

Nietzsche. New York: Penguin, pp. 463–564.Nietzsche, F. (1989). On the Genealogy of Morals and Ecce Homo. Translated by W. Kaufmann

and R. J. Hollingdale. New York: Vintage.Nussbaum, M. C. (1990). Love’s Knowledge: Essays on Philosophy and Literature. Oxford:

OUP.Osborne, H. (1977). ‘Aesthetic Relevance’. The British Journal of Aesthetics, 17, pp. 291–304.Parsons, G. (2006). ‘Freedom and Objectivity in the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature’. The

British Journal of Aesthetics, 46, pp. 17–37.Prettejohn, E. (2007). Art for Art’s Sake: Aestheticism in Victorian Painting. New Haven, CT:

Yale University Press.

23

Page 24: Artistic Objectivity: From Ruskin’s ‘Pathetic Fallacy’ to ...

Pippin, R. B. (2013). After the Beautiful: Hegel and the Philosophy of Pictorial Modernism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Pöllänen, S. H. (2011). ‘Beyond craft and art: A pedagogical model for craft as self-expression’. International Journal of Education through Art, 7, pp. 111–125.

Ridley, A. (1998). R. G. Collingwood: A Philosophy of Art. London: Orion Press.Riedelsheimer, T. (2003). Rivers and Tides: Andy Goldsworthy Working with Time [video

recording]. Burlington, VT: Docurama.Riggle, N. (2016). ‘Using the Street for Art: A Reply to Baldini’. The Journal of Aesthetics and

Art Criticism, 74, pp. 191–195.Robinson, J. (2005). Deeper than Reason: Emotion and Its Role in Literature, Music, and Art.

Oxford: OUP.Robinson, J. (2017). ‘The Missing Person Found I: Expressing Emotions in Pictures’. The British

Journal of Aesthetics, 57, pp. 249–267.Ruskin, J. (1858). Modern Painters. Vol. 1. New York: Wiley & Halsted.Ruskin, J. (1859). Modern Painters. Vol. 3. New York: Wiley & Halsted.Ruskin, J. (1891). The Complete Works of John Ruskin. Vol. 26. Philadelphia: Reuwee, Wattley

& Walsh.Ruskin, J. (2004). ‘Of the Pathetic Fallacy’, in Birch, D. (ed), John Ruskin: Selected Writings.

Oxford: OUP, pp. 68–81.Schatz, T. (1981). Hollywood Genres: Formulas, Filmmaking, and the Studio System.

Philadelphia: Temple University Press.Schiller, F. (1966). Naive and Sentimental Poetry, and On the Sublime; Two Essays. Translated

by J. A. Elias. New York: Frederick Ungar Publishing Co.Schiller, F. (2014). On the Aesthetic Education of Man. Translated by R. Snell. Brooklyn, NY:

Angelico Press.Siegal, N. (2018). ‘In This Exhibition, You Walk Through Excrement’. The New York Times.

Available at https://www.nytimes.com/2018/06/07/arts/design/gelatin-excrement-sculptures.html (Accessed 10 August 2020).

Steiner, W. (2002). Venus in Exile: The Rejection of Beauty in Twentieth-Century Art. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Teukolsky, R. (2009). The Literate Eye: Victorian Art Writing and Modernist Aesthetics. Oxford: OUP.

Tolstoy, L. (1995). What is Art? Translated by R. Pevear and L. Volokhonsky. London: Penguin.Tormey, A. (1971). The Concept of Expression: A Study of Philosophical Psychology and

Aesthetic. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Tucker, H. C. (1978). The Marx-Engels Reader. 2nd edition. New York: W. W. Norton &

Company.Watson, R. A. (1983). ‘A Critique of Anti-Anthropocentric Biocentrism’. Environmental Ethics,

5, pp. 245–256.Wihl, G. (1985). Ruskin and the Rhetoric of Infallibility. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Winterbourne, A. T. (1981). ‘Objectivity in Science and Aesthetics’. The British Journal of

Aesthetics, 21, pp. 253–260.Woodruff, D. M. (2001). ‘A Virtue Theory of Aesthetics’. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art

Criticism, 35, pp. 23–36.Wordsworth, W. (1854). The Poetical Works of William Wordsworth. Vol. 7. Boston: Little,

Brown & Company.

24