Aok ethics

49

description

 

Transcript of Aok ethics

Page 1: Aok   ethics
Page 2: Aok   ethics
Page 3: Aok   ethics
Page 4: Aok   ethics
Page 5: Aok   ethics

1- Strongly Agree2 – Agree3 – Strongly Disagree4. DisagreeGo to the part of the room that best

reflects your opinion on the matter.

Page 6: Aok   ethics

What should I do?

Page 7: Aok   ethics
Page 8: Aok   ethics

Skeptics of moral knowledge claim that moral values and judgements are simply ‘matters of taste’.

Saying ‘abortion is wrong’ is no different to saying ‘I like spinach’.

Emotivist’s argue all moral debate is nothing more than a set of boos and cheers.

Do you agree with this?

Page 9: Aok   ethics

According to moral relativism our values are determined by the society we grow up in, and there are no universal values.

Moral values are simply customs that vary from one culture to another.

Page 10: Aok   ethics
Page 11: Aok   ethics

The Diversity Argument – The sheer variety of moral practices suggests that there are no objective moral values.

The Lack of Foundations Argument – Moral values appear to be ungrounded or lacking in foundation.

Page 12: Aok   ethics

To highlight the lack of foundation to moral arguments consider this example:

Some people in the world are starving. Therefore, I ought to give some of my

food to the starving. It can be seen that there is no logical link

between what is the case, to what ought to be the case.

The argument is emotive but it is not rational/logical.

Page 13: Aok   ethics

One of the attractive features of moral relativism is that it seems to encourage a tolerant ‘live and let live’ attitude to other cultures.

Each and every culture’s values and beliefs are to be respected as no one cultures values are better or more important than another.

Tolerance therefore avoids – Cultural Imperialism.

Page 14: Aok   ethics

The belief in universal tolerance is not consistent with moral relativism.

Consider the following example…..

Page 15: Aok   ethics
Page 16: Aok   ethics

Punishing adultery by stoning to death. Punishing murder by lethal injection. Female genital mutilation. Infanticide. Imprisoning suspected terrorists

without trial. Discriminating against minority groups

Page 17: Aok   ethics

There appears to be shared moral values amongst all nations, people’s, culture’s and religions such as limiting violence, protecting property, promoting honesty etc.

The moral systems of the major world faiths contain very similar moral codes.

Some values can be justified as intuitively obvious. For example the vast majority of people would think ‘random torture is wrong’.

Admittedly it cant be proved but it can be argued that ‘random torture is wrong’ is as obvious as 2+2=4

Page 18: Aok   ethics

The theory that human beings are always and everywhere selfish

There are 4 arguments in support of this theory.

Page 19: Aok   ethics

It is necessarily true that everyone is selfish.

You are being selfish when you do what you want to do and you always end up doing what you most want to do – otherwise you wouldn’t do it.

Peter Stringfellow is comparable to Mother Theresa because there is no such thing as ‘genuine altruism’.

Page 20: Aok   ethics

Human beings are naturally selfish creatures who are programmed to pursue their own interests.

Looking after number 1 is intrinsic to the struggle for survival.

Page 21: Aok   ethics

We get various hidden benefits such as gratitude, praise, and a positive image of ourselves from being kind to other people.

If we help people when they’re in trouble then we can ask for help when we’re in trouble.

Page 22: Aok   ethics

Fear of punishment keeps us in line and prevents us from wrong doing.

The fear of a fine, imprisonment or even death is enough to deter most people from acting immorally.

Consider what it is like living in places where law and order has broken down. What do you think takes place?

Page 23: Aok   ethics
Page 24: Aok   ethics

While it may be that some values are relative and that people are often selfish, we do not need to conclude that all values are relative and that people are always selfish.

It follows that there is room for the idea that there is such a thing as moral knowledge.

We are now going to have a look at a more systematic and coherent approach to ethics which enables us to make sense of our moral beliefs and intuitions.

Page 25: Aok   ethics

Often reduced to slavish obedience to religious codes of conduct laid out in holy writings eg The Bible, Torah, Old Testament, Quran.

However, this raises serious questions. Should we really put people to death for

working on the Sabbath? It was Plato who first introduced us to the

problem of attempting derive ethics from Religion.

Page 26: Aok   ethics

Is something good because God says it’s good, or does God say it’s good because it is good?

On the one hand, if something is good simply because God says it’s good , then if God suddenly decided that murder was good, it would be good.

Most people would reject this conclusion. On the other hand if God says something is

good because it is good then it seems values are independent of God. Goodness exists outside and beyond of God. We therefore do not need to appeal to Him in order to justify our values.

This is a very convincing argument against religious ethics.

Page 27: Aok   ethics

The failure of religious ethics to counter Plato’s argument as well as religious ethics not appealing to atheists has led to the idea of ‘duty ethics’.

Ethics is a matter of doing your duty.The problem is finding out what

exactly it is we need to be dutifully performing.

Page 28: Aok   ethics

People have different views on dutySome people believe it their duty to

remain faithful – others do not.Some people believe it is their duty to not take life – others do not.

Page 29: Aok   ethics

Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) Argued that all duties can be known through

reason. Something is your duty if you can consistently

generalise it. For example – if you wanted to jump the dinner queue because you can’t be bothered to wait – you should ask yourself what would happen if everyone did that. The answer of course would be chaos. If everyone jumped the queue there would be no more queue to jump.

So if you were to generalise the rule ‘jump the queue whenever you feel like it’. You end up with a contradiction.

Therefore it is your duty to stand in line and not jump the queue whenever you feel like it.

The same reasoning is applied to every moral decision

Consider Kant’s response to the following…..

Page 30: Aok   ethics
Page 31: Aok   ethics
Page 32: Aok   ethics
Page 33: Aok   ethics
Page 34: Aok   ethics

This another key area in Kant’s thinking. It is sincere motives behind our actions

that are important and not the consequences our actions produce.

If you genuinely try to help a blind man cross the road but he gets knocked over, you should not be blamed.

If however, you intended to murder someone but they escaped unharmed you are still considered a bad person.

Page 35: Aok   ethics

Kant also insisted that truly moral behaviour should be motivated by reason and not feeling.

He felt feelings are unreliable and cannot justify values.

If you feel like helping someone today there is no guarantee you will feel like helping them tomorrow.

Page 36: Aok   ethics

Who were the rational students?Who were the more emotional

students?What would Kant think?Do you agree with him?What would an emotivist think?

Page 37: Aok   ethics

Kant believed there were 3 different motives for doing good.

1. You expect something in return2. Sympathy3. Duty Kant believed the only moral actions are

ones performed out of duty with sincere motives behind them and without regard for consequences.

Page 38: Aok   ethics

Kant has been instrumental in shaping modern approaches to ethics however, it can be seen that Kant’s theory suffers from very serious difficulties.

Consider…

Page 39: Aok   ethics

A madman asks you where he can find the person he’s trying to kill and you know where they are hiding. What should you do? According to Kant you have a duty to tell the truth, and not lie regardless of the murderous consequences that are likely to happen. This seems clearly counter intuitive.

Page 40: Aok   ethics

Simple theory of ethics. There is only one supreme moral principle

– that we should seek the greatest happiness for the greatest number.

Basically maximise happiness. Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832) and John

Stuart Mill (1806-73) Wanted to give a scientific foundation for

ethics in the same way science was discovering natural laws Bentham and Mill were looking for moral laws.

Page 41: Aok   ethics

The only thing that is good in itself is happiness and actions are right if they increase happiness and wrong if they decrease happiness.

You may ask ‘what is happiness?’ Bentham would reply ‘the sum of

pleasures and a happy life one that maximises feelings of pleasure and minimises feelings of pain.

According to this theory apply the principle of utility to the following examples…

Page 42: Aok   ethics
Page 43: Aok   ethics
Page 44: Aok   ethics
Page 45: Aok   ethics
Page 46: Aok   ethics

It is a simple and coherent theory. It is based on human nature which would

seem to suggest we all seek pleasure and avoid pain.

It is based on reason and seesm to suit the egoistic, hedonistic, individualism of the 21st Century

It’s based on the premise that desirable consequences are more important than motives or duties.

It avoids criticisms like that held against Kant.

Page 47: Aok   ethics

How do we measure happiness?How do we accurately predict the

outcomes or consequences of our actions?

Also consider the following horrific example which would be considered morally justifiable by Utilitarians…

Page 48: Aok   ethics
Page 49: Aok   ethics

Ethics is inescapable and a part of all our lives. In the case of a girl on holiday about to cheat on

her unknowing boyfriend back home – What would a Utilitarian think? What would a Kantian think?

How much use are theories in practice? Perhaps they offer a sense of support when we

make decisions and justify them on the basis of others.

The fact that we can never be sure that we have done the right thing, or that we are painfully aware that we could have done better, is perhaps part of the tragedy of the human condition.