An Examination Of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-being

download An Examination Of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-being

of 18

Transcript of An Examination Of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-being

  • 7/31/2019 An Examination Of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-being

    1/18

    PREFACE

    My professional career has ended and I am now happily

    retired. However, there are a few unpublished papers that

    I would like to make available. While research on the

    hedonic view of happiness and well-being has flourished

    very little has focused on Aristotles eudaimonic theory.

    These might add something to the existing literature. To

    see our other studies on eudaimonia and our scale of moral

    virtue please go to :csufresno.academia.edu/SamuelFranklin

    I believe that virtue is the most important, but greatly

    misunderstood, idea in Aristotles theory. I have

    included several chapters on the topic of virtue in a

    recent book entitled THE PSYCHOLOGY OF HAPPINESS: A GOOD

    HUMAN LIFE, published by Cambridge University Press.

    I have also included a study on crowding that may be of

    interest. It suggests that crowding and scarcity of

    resources may lead to both political and social upheaval.

    Although the study was conducted in the 1970s it may

    portend the future for some.

  • 7/31/2019 An Examination Of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-being

    2/18

    AN EMPIRICAL EXAMINATION OF

    ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPT OF VIRTUE

    AND ITS RELATIONSHIP TO

    WELLBEING

    Samuel S. Franklin California State University, Fresno

    PAPER PRESENTED AT THE MEETING OF THE WESTERN PSYCHOLOGICALASSOCIATION

    LOS ANGELES

    APRIL, 1994

  • 7/31/2019 An Examination Of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-being

    3/18

    AN EMPIRICAL EXAMINATION OF ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPT OF VIRTUE AND ITS

    RELATIONSHIP TO WELL-BEING

    SAMUEL S. FRANKLIN

    CALIFORNIA STATE UNIVERSITY, FRESNO

    Aristotle's Nichomachean Ethics (NE) contains a well developed and

    elaborate theory of the good life which he called 'eudaimonia.' Although

    the eudaimonic theory has been largely overlooked by contemporary

    researchers of well-being and happiness, we believe it has much to offer.

    The theory is based upon the assumption that a good life is achieved to

    the extent that one actualizes or fulfills potentials. Aristotle would

    probably very much agree with Ryff's observation that "Central emphasis

    has been given to short-term affective well-being (i.e. happiness), at the

    expense of more enduring life challenges such as having a sense of purpose

    and direction, and achieving a sense of self-realization" (Ryff, 1989).

    Actualization requires the satisfaction of certain needs. According to

    Aristotle we have both physical and psychological needs, or 'needs of the

    soul', as he called them, such as the need for friends, art, learning,

    etc. In eudaimonic theory, how we fulfill our needs is crucial.

    Aristotle emphasizes the necessity of acquiring the things we need at the

    right time, in the right amount and in the way. Most of the things we

    need, or 'real goods' as Aristotle called them, are 'limited'; we need

    them for actualization, but only in certain amounts and only at certain

    times, and they may be good only if obtained in certain ways. Food, for

    example, is a real good but it is not beneficial in unlimited quantities,

    at any time and under all circumstances. Too little food is damaging and

    too much food is equally harmful. The same may be said for most all the

    things we need. In most things we are well advised to seek the 'golden

    mean'.

    To correctly obtain what we need, virtue is required.

    ...if virtue , like nature, requires more accuracy and is better

    than any art, then it will aim at the mean.... In feeling fear,confidence, desire, anger, pity, and in general pleasure and pain,one can feel too much or too little; and both extremes are wrong.The mean and the good is feeling at the right time, about the rightthings, in relation to the right people, and for the right reason;and the mean and the good are the task of virtue. Similarly, inregard to actions there are excess, deficiency, and the mean.(Nichomachean Ethics [NE] II, 5. Bambrough, 1963, p. 309)

    While Aristotle may appear to be uncompromising about what is 'right', he

    is not. Right is always defined relative to the person. Aristotle says "We

    may now define virtue as a disposition of the soul in which, when it has

    to choose among actions and feelings, it observes the mean relative to

    us..." (NE II, 5. Bambrough, 1963, p. 309)

    Virtue is a complex idea that became terribly misunderstood when it fell

    into the company of words like sin and chastity during the middle ages

    (Maclntyre, 1981). As the ancient Greeks used the term, however, virtue

    is an extremely meaningful concept and I think translatable into the

    language of contemporary psychology. It is the purpose of this paper to

  • 7/31/2019 An Examination Of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-being

    4/18

    attempt such a translation and to empirically examine the relationship

    between virtue and well-being. First, I will attempt to show that

    Aristotle's concept of virtue is composed of several measurable

    psychological processes.

    VIRTUE AND REASON

    The first component of virtue is reason. For the Greeks, only humans

    have the capacity to think. Reason is our ergon, our highest and most

    unique function. "The function of man is activity of soul in accordance

    with reason..." (NE I. 7. Bambrough, p. 293). According to Aristotle

    there are two related but distinguishable types of reason. Intellectual

    virtue refers to something like our general intelligence, abstract

    reasoning, theory, and the understanding of general principle. It

    appears to be somewhat similar to what we now call fluid intelligence.

    Moral virtue, on the other hand, refers to the ability to apply general

    principles to specific instances. It is sometimes called practical

    intelligence. Moral virtue must be learned by doing, by practice.

    "Moral virtue is a product of habit" (NE II, 1. Bambrough, p. 303).

    And, it is important to acquire moral virtue early in life: "It makes no

    small difference, then, whether we form habits of one kind or another from

    our very youth; it makes a very great difference, or rather all the

    difference." (NE II, 1. Ross, p.29)

    VIRTUE AND DESIRE

    A second component of virtue is desire. Today we might call

    desire motivation. Action alone cannot be virtuous; the

    motivation which propels the behavior must also be considered.

    Wanting to do what is right and best (relative to your life) is

    as important as the act itself. Urmson notes that the virtuous

    person wants to be virtuous and enjoys virtuous action.

    "..whether one has excellent character (virtue) ... depends notmerely on what one does but also on what one likes doing."Virtue is a..."settled disposition to want to act and to act in away appropriate to the situation." (Urmson, 1988. p.26 ff)

    VIRTUE AND CHOICE

    Reason and desire combine to produce the third component of virtue:

    choice. "Choice, therefore, is thought along with desire, or desire

    along with thought." (NE VI. 2. Bambrough p. 345.) Adler (1980) notes

    "... moral virtues are habits of making the right choices..." (p.94).

    Once we know the appropriate action, and desire it, we must choose to

    behave appropriately. Choice mediates between knowing - wanting and

    acting.

    VIRTUE AND SELF-CONTROL

    A fourth component of virtue is self-control or restraint. Aristotle

    acknowledges that desires may compete with each other and that restraint

    is often required. We may know the best thing to do, and desire it too,

    but we may also know and desire a contrary action. Self control

  • 7/31/2019 An Examination Of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-being

    5/18

    influences our choice. "Virtue is within our power, and so, too is vice.

    The point is that where we can act, we can also refrain, and vice versa"

    (NE III. 5. Bambrough p. 323). To act one way frequently requires that

    we inhibit an alternative response.

    VIRTUE AND ACTION/FEELING

    Finally, there is the virtuous action itself. Virtuous action includes

    behavior and emotion appropriately chosen; at the correct time, in the

    right amount, for the right reason. For Aristotle, action and feeling go

    together, feeling 'supervenes upon acts'. That is why punishment can be

    effective; pain and act go together. "...to feel delight and pain rightly

    or wrongly has no small effect on our actions." "...virtue then, is

    concerned with pleasures and pains, and ....the acts from which [they

    arise]" (NE II, 3. Ross, p. 33).

    Virtue then, includes several psychological functions all of which serve

    to guide us toward the goods we need for actualization. Virtue "...is

    concerned with passions and actions, in which excess is a form of failure,

    and so is defect, while the intermediate is praised and is a form of

    success..." (NE II, 6. Ross p. 38).

    Summarizing what we have said above, the concept of virtue includes the

    following psychological functions:

    KNOWING the appropriate thing to do and feel, both

    theoretically and practically, by application of correct

    principle to the current circumstance.

    DESIRING/WANTING to act and feel appropriately.

    CHOOSING the appropriate action and feeling.

    SELFCONTROL, or the inhibition of competing behaviors and

    emotions.

    ACTING and FEELING appropriately.

    The present investigation was an attempt to examine this theoretical

    structure of virtue and its relationship to well-being.

    PROCEDURES

    Subjects were 68 advanced undergraduate psychology students, 16 males, 48

    females and 4 subjects who did not declare their gender. Their mean age

    was 25.55 years. The disproportionate number of females was the result

    of our psychology department's student population in which females are

    strongly over represented. This is not particularly disconcerting to the

    author since in this study, and in earlier investigations of the

    problem, age and sex have not been important to the study of well-being

    and its causes. (Costa, et. al., 1987; Franklin, LaMarca, & Barton 1991;

  • 7/31/2019 An Examination Of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-being

    6/18

    Franklin and Torzynski, 1993).

    The subjects were given three different packets of psychological scales

    over the course of a semester. The scales were completed both in class

    and out of class. The rate of return was 86%. Not all subjects

    completed all scales or all items of each scale so the N's for different

    variables and analyses vary slightly.

    SCALES

    REASON/THINKING

    Three scales were used to measure virtuous thinking. Moral virtue or

    practical thinking, was measured by the Decision Making Scale (DMS)

    consisting of 12 items. The items identified 12 different domains of

    life; family, education, friends, work, etc., and Ss rated their

    'decision making ability' and 'the quality of the solutions they usually

    find' for the day to day problems in each domain. A Likert type scale

    was used where 1 was bad and 5 described excellent decision making.

    This was the first time the DMS has been used and the correlation alpha of

    .72 seems quite reasonable. Because the 12 items of the scale refer to

    different life domains we might expect a less than perfect inter-item

    correlation.

    A second measure of moral virtue consisted of the four 'ways' items from

    the Will And Ways Scale ( ). A similar

    Likert type scale was used here to rate statements like "I can think of

    many ways to get out of a jam" and "Even when others get discouraged, I

    know I can find a way to solve the problem." The alpha obtained in the

    present study was .69, not especially impressive, but since the scale had

    only 4 items and since it correlated reasonably well (r = .55, p < .00)

    with the DMS measure it was decided to combine the two to derive our

    measure of moral virtue.

    The third measure of reason was an attempt to tap the more generalized,

    theoretical thinking that Aristotle called intellectual virtue. For this

    purpose four subscales from the Constructive Thinking Inventory (Epstein

    & Meier, 1989) were used. The subscales are designed to measure

    categorical thinking, superstitious thinking, esoteric thinking, and naive

    optimism. All these subscales are potential impediments and blocks to

    good generalized thinking. A person high in 'categorical thinking',

    ('making... undifferentiated judgments'), for example, would be likely to

    exhibit poor intellectual virtue because of a prevailing tendency to

    overgeneralize. A person high in superstitious thinking, e.g.

    one who agrees with the statement 'When something bad happens to

    me, I feel that more bad things are likely to follow' would also

    seem to reason poorly. Of the four intellectual virtue measures, only

    two; the Superstitious Thinking and the Categorical Thinking scales were

    shown to be statistically tied to the variables of the present study.

  • 7/31/2019 An Examination Of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-being

    7/18

    Therefore, early in the data analyses a new measure consisting of the 8

    item Superstitious Thinking scale and the 12 item Categorical Thinking

    scale was created and used in all analyses involving intellectual virtue.

    In the present study, the inter-item alpha's of the two measures were .80

    and .74 for the superstitious and categorical thinking scales,

    respectively. Since intellectual virtue was measured by scales designed

    to tap the opposite of good generalized thinking, the label 'Contra-

    Intellectual Virtue' is used throughout the paper to refer to performance

    on this scale.

    DESIRE AND CHOICE

    Aristotle claims that the truly virtuous persons wants to feel and act

    appropriately. Some like and enjoy doing the right thing while others do

    not. The present study does not include the data on desire and choice but

    leaves them for examination in later papers.

    SELF-CONTROL

    Several measures of self-control were employed. The Deferred Gratification

    Scale (Ray and Najman, 1986), the NEO Impulsiveness subscale (Costa and

    McRae, 1985), The Procrastination Scale (Tuckman, 1991), and two subscales

    from Epstein and Meier's (1989) Constructive Thinking Inventory: The

    Emotional Coping (CTIEC) and the Behavioral Coping (CTIBC) subscales.

    These two subscales consisted in a combined total of 37 items all of which

    refer to the subjects capacity to moderate his or her feelings and

    actions. Sample guestions from the emotional coping subscale read as

    follows: "The slightest indication of disapproval gets me upset" and "I

    don't worry about things I can do nothing about." Sample behavioral coping

    items are: "When I realize I have made a mistake, I usually take

    immediate action to correct it" and " When I have a lot of work to do by a

    deadline, I waste a lot of time worrying about it instead of just doing

    it." All self-control measures correlated significantly with each other

    but a hierarchical regression analysis to virtuous behavior (see below)

    led us to restrict our attention to only the two coping scales from the

    Constructive Thinking inventory. Their correlation alpha's reached

    respectable levels; .89 and .85 for the Emotional Coping and Behavioral

    Coping scales respectively.

    VIRTUOUS BEHAVIOR

    The present investigation did not measure virtuous behavior directly but

    did examine the disposition to respond appropriately. The Self Appraisal

    Scale (SAS) was constructed to assess ones ability to attain the right

    amount, at the right time, and in the right way. From Urmson's list

    (1988, p.34) of the ancient Greek virtues several of the most commonly

    recognized (including temperance, courage, liberality, justice, and

    pride) were selected and used to construct 48 True / False items regarding

    the tendency to engage in virtuous behavior. For example, the first

    item "I give too freely of myself" is intended to tap ones ability to give

    the right amount (liberality) of himself to others. Another item, "I

    tend to seek the easy way out in most situations" concerns ones 'courage',

  • 7/31/2019 An Examination Of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-being

    8/18

    the ability to endure temporary discomfort for future gains. "I always

    want to win" was used to measure the virtue Aristotle calls justice. The

    SAS, designed as a measure of the disposition for virtuous behavior, has

    been successfully used in previous investigations (Franklin, LaMarca &

    Barton, 1992, Franklin & Torzynski, 1993). It's alpha in the present

    investigation was .88.

    NEED SATISFACTION

    The Satisfaction Index (SI) was developed to assess the acquisition of

    real goods. The scale consisted of the same 12 life domains appearing in

    the Decision Making Scale (family, work, money, love, etc.) and subjects

    rated each on a 1 (terrible) to 5 (Great) Likert scale regarding "...

    the quality of each area of your life over the last few years?" It was

    assumed that a qualitative judgment regarding a particular domain would

    reflect the level of need satisfaction in that area. The domain items

    were presented in a different order than they assumed on the DMS.

    WELL-BEING

    The recent literature on happiness and well-being seems to be in general

    agreement regarding two fundamental components a good life: life

    satisfaction and a favorable balance of positive and negative affect

    (Diener, 1984). This modern view seems quite consistent with Aristotle's

    notion of eudaimonia. Surely, he would agree that happy people, people

    who fulfill their potentials, would find their lives both satisfying and

    pleasurable. Thus, well-being, the major dependent variable in this

    study, was operationalized in this way. Life satisfaction was measured

    by the Satisfaction with Life Scale (Diener, Emmons, Larsen and Griffen

    1983). Affect was assessed by the Affect Balance Scale (Bradburn, 1969).

    Both measures are widely used by researchers in the area of happiness and

    well- being and both have much to recommend them. In the present study

    the alpha for the Satisfaction with Life Scale (SWLS) was .87. Separate

    correlation alpha's for the positive and negative affect sub-scales of the

    Affect Balance Scale (ABS) were .91 and .50, respectively.

  • 7/31/2019 An Examination Of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-being

    9/18

    RESULTS

    The purpose of this investigation was to empirically examine the

    theoretical structure of Aristotle's concept of virtue and to further

    assess his claim that virtue is essential to well-being. The scales used

    are presented in Table 1, along with their means, standard deviations, and

    alpha's. Table 2 presents a correlation matrix of the variables. It

    may be noted from Table 2 that most of the scales, although structured

    very differently and intended to measure very different psychological

    processes, are quite highly correlated. While alternative explanations

    for these correlations may be possible, (e.g. all measures may reflect

    the same psychological construct), we believe the relationships shown in

    Table 2 lend strong support to the eudaimonic theory.

    The model presented in Figure I will serve as a guide for our discussion

    of the results.

    It should be noted at the outset that neither age nor sex was

    significantly correlated with any of the measures used in the study.

    VIRTUOUS THINKING AND MORAL ACTION

    In the eudaimonic model the most important determinant of virtuous

    behavior is good thinking. One can not do the appropriate thing unless he

    or she knows what is appropriate. Such knowledge consists of two distinct

    but related forms of reason. First, intellectual virtue requires that we

    understand certain principles which can be used to guide our actions. For

    example, to be just, we must understand the idea of fairness. But an

    intellectual understanding is not enough. We must also know how to use

    this knowledge. We must be able to select the right amount of fairness

    for the situation at hand. We need both intellectual virtue and moral

    virtue. From Table 2 it can be seen that while contra-intellectual and

    moral virtue are significantly correlated (r = -.29, p = .03) the

    correlation is not especially high. This finding is consistent with

    Aristotle's dichotomous treatment of virtuous thinking.

    Table 2 also reveals that both contra-intellectual and moral virtue are

    significantly related to moral action. Poor general thinking, assessed

    by the categorical and superstitious thinking subscales of the CTI,

    correlated -.53 (p

  • 7/31/2019 An Examination Of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-being

    10/18

    the others, our operational definition collapsed to the combined CTIEC

    (emotional coping) and CTIBC (behavioral coping) scores which we labeled

    Self-Control. Table 2 shows that Self-Control is strongly related to all

    variables of the model but especially to SAS (virtuous action), r =.72 (p< .000). Once again, Aristotle's model appears to be supported.

    Restraint as well as reason is integral to moral action.

    It is also interesting to note in Table 2 that virtuous thinking and self-

    control are far from independent. The strong relationships between these

    measures are quite consistent with the confusion in Aristotle's writings

    over the importance of will (self-control) in eudaimonic theory, and

    whether will can be explained entirely in terms of reason and thinking

    (Dahl, 1984). This is not an issue, however that can be addressed in the

    present paper.

    VIRTUE AS A MEANS

    Another confusion in Aristotle's writings concerns the issue of whether

    virtue, that is, the interaction of reason, restraint, choice, desire, and

    action, is a means to happiness, or is happiness itself. Aristotelian

    scholars differ on the question but some suggest both views are correct.

    The position taken in this paper is that virtuous thinking and self-

    control permit virtuous action, which in turn enables the acquisition of

    the goods we need for fulfillment. That is, virtue is a means. While not

    explicitly proposed by Aristotle, we predicted that virtuous behavior

    would be highly correlated with need satisfaction. Table 2 supports this

    prediction. The correlation between the SAS (virtuous behavior) and the

    SI (Satisfaction Index) is .47 (p

  • 7/31/2019 An Examination Of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-being

    11/18

    action scores, contra-intellectual virtue (CTICT + CTIST) accounted for

    another 14%, and self-control (CTIEC & CTIBC subscales) explained an

    additional 12 %. Altogether then, the three independent variables

    comprising virtuous thinking and self-control explain 56% of the variance

    in moral action. It appears from the Beta weights shown in Table 4 that

    the three independent variables (contra-intellectual and moral virtue and

    self-control) are relatively independent at this level in the model.

    In the second step of the hierarchical regression analysis need

    satisfaction (SI) served as the dependent variable while moral action

    (SAS) was added to the predictors used in step 1. By this procedure the

    contribution of all four variables to need satisfaction can be assessed.

    The independence of the predictors is reflected in their Beta weights.

    Taking Figure 1 and Table 4 together then, reveals that the four variables

    above need satisfaction (SI) explain 59% of its variance. As might be

    expected from the model, contra-intellectual and moral virtue still retain

    some of their individual contributions to SI but moral action (SAS),

    being strongly influenced by the predictors above it, looses its unique

    predictive power.

    The third and fourth steps of the hierarchical analysis regressed all

    predictor variables of the Model to the constructs that define well-being;

    Life Satisfaction and Affect Balance. From Table 4 we note that all

    variables of the model explained 49% of life satisfaction, and 26% of the

    affective dimension of well-being.

    Table 4 also reveals that none of the Beta weights remain significant in

    the final steps of the hierarchical analysis. This finding seems to make

    good sense in the context of the model. Reason and restraint are the

    basis of moral action, moral action enables the acquisition of the goods

    we need, and the latter is the basis of well-being. All variables of

    the model are interrelated. Thus, while it is clear that reason and

    restraint are the basis for about half the variance in life satisfaction,

    their effects are disbursed over the mediating variables of moral action

    and need satisfaction, thus dissipating most of their individual

    contribution.

  • 7/31/2019 An Examination Of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-being

    12/18

    DISCUSSION

    Virtue plays a cardinal role in Aristotle's theory of the good life.

    Actualization requires that needs be met correctly; in the right amount,

    at the right time, in the right way, and for the right reason. Virtue

    enables us to 'hit the target.' One of the goals of this investigation

    was to examine the theoretical structure of virtue. To this end, we

    looked at the relationships between the two types of reason, self

    control, and moral action/feeling.

    VIRTUE AND REASON

    Intellectual virtue may be characterized as "understanding" or "reasoning

    cogently and validly", or by the "grasp of what is most fundamental-first

    principles", or by "the powers of the mind." (Adler, 1990, p.175 ff).

    Moral virtue applies reasoning and understanding to the practical matters

    of living. Moral virtue depends, in part, on intellectual virtue but

    the two are by no means, uniformly aligned. For a variety of reasons,

    theoretical knowledge may not be used or may be applied incorrectly.

    The less than perfect union of the two kinds of reasoning seems to be

    supported by the data. The correlation between our contra-intellectual

    and moral virtue measures was only -.29 (p = .03). To do the right thing

    requires that we understand certain principles and apply them correctly;

    but variables, like desire, choice, self-control and the habits

    developed over a life time also play a role in the practical world.

    Theoretically then, the modest correlation between intellectual and moral

    virtue seems consistent with eudaimonic theory. The failure of previous

    investigations to find a connection between general or fluid

    intelligence, (which cannot be too far removed from what Aristotle called

    intellectual virtue) and well-being (Diener, 1984; Epstein & Meier, 1989,

    Valiant, 1977) might be explained by the neglect of moral virtue and all

    the variables which affect it. In eudaimonic theory, both are required.

    VIRTUE AND SELFCONTROL

    There is controversy in the philosophical literature regarding the role

    of will in Aristotle's ethics (Dahl, 1984). On the one hand he seems to

    recognize the importance of restraint and self-control, and on the other

    he suggests that restraint is ultimately explained by reason, or its

    deficiencies. It can be argued that the person who fails to act rightly

    does so because of ignorance not because of weakness. "No man chooses

    evil because it is evil; he only mistakes it for happiness, the good he

    seeks." (Mary Wollstonecraft). Dahl (1984) believes Aristotle does

    provide a place for will or self-control and emphasizes Aristotle's

    concept of Akrasia, or the 'weakness of will'.

    The findings concerning the relationship between reason and self-control

    appear to mirror the confusion in the philosophical literature. A

    hierarchical regression analysis showed that contra-intellectual virtue

    explained 31% of the variance in self-control and moral virtue accounted

    for another 16%. Poorly managed behavior may well be caused by poor

    thinking, both theoretical and practical. It is also possible that

  • 7/31/2019 An Examination Of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-being

    13/18

    thinking and self-control are bi-directionally related. In any case, the

    link between self-control and cognition is we11-documented. Lazarus

    (1991) suggests that emotional and behavioral reactions are regulated by

    our cognitive appraisal. There is still much to learn about the

    relationship of self-control and virtuous thinking.

    VIRTUE AND ACTION/FEEING

    The coupling of action and feeling has a long tradition in psychology

    (James, 1890; Klinger, 1977), but Aristotle antedates them all. Virtue

    includes both, in concert; two aspects of the same thing. And, maybe

    this is the essence of the good life. If we think, desire, control and

    choose correctly we will act/feel correctly. And, maybe that's what

    happiness is. "..happiness is activity of the soul in conformity with

    virtue" - period! Our examination of the relationship between virtue

    and well-being might stop here. Virtue culminates in virtuous

    action/feeling. Virtue and happiness may be two aspects of the same

    thing. There is much to be said for this position and Aristotle does

    not hesitate to embrace it. The data also seem to support it. Reason and

    self-control account for 56% of the variance in virtuous behavior (SAS)

    and virtuous behavior is strongly correlated with well-being. Table 2

    clearly shows that the correlations of contra-intellectual virtue, moral

    virtue and virtuous behavior with the two well-being measures are all

    highly significant. Virtue alone may bring happiness.

    However, Aristotle takes the other side too. We also need goods. "It is

    impossible to do fine acts without a supply of 'goods' "...happiness does

    seem to requires this external bounty." (NE I, 8. Brambough, p. 296).

    Aristotle seems comfortable with both sides: virtue is an end, and virtue

    is a means.

    Virtuous action/feeling is a means to the goods we need for growth; for

    fulfillment and actualization. Table 2 indicates a significant

    relationship between our SAS measure of virtuous action and the SI

    measure of need satisfaction (r = .47, p < .00). Figure 1 tells us

    that almost 60% of the variance in need satisfaction comes from virtue.

    As the eudaimonic theory claims, virtue pays off, both intrinsically, and

    by moving us toward the perfection that Aristotle believed was in the

    reach of everyone. (NE I, 9, Brambrough, p.296)

    Figure 1 reveals that virtue, by its intrinsic value, and by the goods it

    delivers, predicts about 50 percent of the variance in life satisfaction

    and about 25 percent of our affect. Good thinking and self-control

    appear to be much more important to our lives than most of the extrinsic

    goods we usually dream about. Fortune, youth, education, occupation, and

    the like, the things we usually equate with the good life, are far less

    important to our well-being. (Andrews and Withey, 1974; Campbell,

    1976; Myers, 1992). Virtue is an old idea, but it's still a good one.

  • 7/31/2019 An Examination Of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-being

    14/18

    REFERENCES

    Adler, M.J. (1980) Aristotle for everybody. New York: Bantam.

    Andrews, F. M., & Witney, S. B. (1976). Social indicators of

    well-being: Americans perception of life quality. New York: Plenum Press.

    Bambrough, R. (Ed.) (1963). The philosophy of Aristotle (trans. A.E. Wardman & J.L. Creed). NewYork American Library/Mentor.

    Bradburn, N.M. (1969). The structure of psychological well-being. Chicago: Aldine.

    Campbell, A. (1976). Subjective measures of well-being. American Psychologist,31, 117-124.

    Costa, P.T. Jr., & McCrae, R. R. (1980). Influence of

    extraversion and neuroticism on subjective well-being: happy and unhappy people. Journalof Personality and Social Psychology, 38

    f668 -678.

    Costa. P. T. Jr., & McCrae, R. R. (1985). The NEO personality inventory manual. Odessa,Fl: Psycholgical Assessment Resources, Inc.

    Costa, P.T., Jr., Zonderman, A.B., McCrae, R.R., Cornoni-Huntley, J., Locke, B.Z., & Barbano,H.E. (1987) Longitudinal analyses of psychological well-being in a national sample:Stability of mean levels. Journal of Gerontology, 42, 50-55.

    Dahl, N.O. (1984). Practical reason, Aristotle, and weakness of the will. Minneapollis:Univ. Minnesota Press.

    Diener, E. (1984). Subjective will-being. Psychological Bulletin, 95, 542-575.

    Diener, E., Emmons, R., Larsen, R. & Griffin, S. (1985). The satisfaction with lifescale. Journal of Personality Assessment, 49, 71-75.

    Epstein, S., & Meier, P. (1989). Constructive thinking: a broad coping variable with specificcomponesnts. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 57, 332-350.

    Franklin, S. LaMarca P., & Barton, L. (1991). An examination of

    Aristotle's eudaimonic theory of happiness. Paper presented at the Western PsychologicalAssociation, April 1991, San Francisco.

    Franklin, S. & Torzynski, R. (1993). Virtue and well-being: evidence for Aristotle'seudaimonic theory of happiness. Paper presented at the Western Psychological Association,

    April 1993, Phoenix, AZ.

    James, William (1969). Psychology: Briefer course. London:Col1i er-Macmi1i an.

    Klinger, E. Meaning and void: inner experience and the incentives in peeople's lives.

    Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Lazarus, R.S. (1991). Emotion & adaptation. New York. Oxford University Press.

    Maclntyre, A. (1981). After virtue: a study in moral theory. Notre Dame: University of NotreDame Press.

    Meyers, D-G. (1992). The pursuit of happiness. New York: Avon.

    Ray, J. L.,& Najman, J. M. (1986). The generalizability of deferment of gratification. TheJournal of Social Psychology, 126, 117-119.

    Ross, D. (1986). Aristotle: The nicomachean ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Ryff, C . (1989). Happiness is everything, or is it?Exploration of the meaning of psychological well-being.

    Jouranal of Personality and Social Psychology, 57, 1069 - 1081.

    Tuckman, B. W. (1991). The development and concurrent validityof the procrastination scale. Educational and Psychological Measurement, 51, 473-480.

    Urmson, J.O. (1988) Aristotle's ethics. Great Britain: Basil Blackwell.

    Vaillant, G. E. (1977). Adaptation to life. Boston: Little, Brown.

  • 7/31/2019 An Examination Of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-being

    15/18

  • 7/31/2019 An Examination Of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-being

    16/18

  • 7/31/2019 An Examination Of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-being

    17/18

  • 7/31/2019 An Examination Of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-being

    18/18