ALLEN. Experience as a Source and Ground of Theory in Epicureanism

19
De Gruyter Experience as a Source and Ground of Theory in Epicureanism Author(s): James Allen Reviewed work(s): Source: Apeiron: A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science, Vol. 37, No. 4, RE- INVENTIONS: ESSAYS ON HELLENISTIC & EARLY ROMAN SCIENCE (December 2004), pp. 89-106 Published by: De Gruyter Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/40913983 . Accessed: 08/11/2012 13:02 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . De Gruyter is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Apeiron: A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science. http://www.jstor.org

description

ALLEN. Experience as a Source and Ground of Theory in Epicureanism

Transcript of ALLEN. Experience as a Source and Ground of Theory in Epicureanism

  • De Gruyter

    Experience as a Source and Ground of Theory in EpicureanismAuthor(s): James AllenReviewed work(s):Source: Apeiron: A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science, Vol. 37, No. 4, RE-INVENTIONS: ESSAYS ON HELLENISTIC & EARLY ROMAN SCIENCE (December 2004), pp. 89-106Published by: De GruyterStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/40913983 .Accessed: 08/11/2012 13:02

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    De Gruyter is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Apeiron: A Journal forAncient Philosophy and Science.

    http://www.jstor.org

  • Experience as a Source and Ground of Theory in Epicureanism James Allen

    As has often been noted, Epicurus and his followers were indebted to an ancient tradition of empiricism in epistemology. Thus there are many points of contact between Epicureanism and the position defended by the self-styled Empiricists (large as opposed to small e empiricists), a medical school which arose near Epicurus' lifetime but whose views are based on ideas that were already familiar to Plato and Aristotle. Both schools assign a place of fundamental importance in their accounts of knowledge to the observation of relations of sequence and conjunction among events, and later Epicureans used some of the same empirical terminology as the Empiricists. Most notably, the Epicureans used the term, ' epilogismos' , which was used by some Empiricists for the form of reasoning about matters falling under experience that they accept, though with differences that it has proved very hard to pin down.

    Yet in certain crucial respects, Epicurean epistemology is about as far removed from empiricism as it is possible to be. Medical Empiricism defined itself in opposition to rationalism. 'Rationalism' was in fact the Empiricists' polemical term for a mass of disparate views whose adher- ents were united only by the conviction that mere experience was insufficient to give rise to a body of knowledge that deserved to be called an art, whether in medicine or any other sphere. Its leading characteristic, according to the Empiricists, was a claimed ability to go beyond experi- ence and grasp nonevident entities and processes by means of a special faculty of reason. These are sometimes described as matters seen or discerned by reason ( ). The atoms about whose behavior the Epicureans had so much to say were a paradigm of this kind of entity.

  • 90 James Allen

    The Epicureans also defended theories about the nonevident causes of astronomical phenomena like eclipses and much else besides. And they achieved these results, or claimed to achieve them, by rationalist means: inference or demonstration from signs or evidence furnished by the phenomena. By these measures, Epicureanism is a form of rationalism.

    The aim of this paper is to compare Epicurean views about experience to other views available in the Hellenistic period, including those of the medical Empiricists. In this way I hope to throw light on the Epicureans' distinctive attitude towards experience, an attitude whose affinities with empiricism sets Epicureanism apart from more orthodox forms of ra- tionalism but permits the Epicureans to base on experience theories that orthodox empiricists would reject as unsupported by experience.

    I

    Talk of 'experience' involves a certain amount of unclarity . The word has several senses, whose history would make an interesting study in its own right. Present-day discussions of what is given in immediate experience, where this means something like bare sensation prior to interpretation or inference, or about the quality of conscious experience, use the term in a way that would, I think, have been new to ancient Greek and Latin speakers familiar with the words 'experientia' or empeiria.

    Clues that will help us understand the ancient conception of experi- ence are furnished by the medical Empiricists' reflections about their terminology. Galen's Outline of Empiricism (Subfiguratio emprica; hence- forward Subfig emp), which is meant to be a faithful presentation of the Empiricists' own views, makes a point about one term in the Empiricist vocabulary that is also true of others. Though the term autopsia, seeing or observing for oneself, ought strictly to be applied to an activity, he tells us, it was also used by the Empiricists for knowledge, namely the knowledge one has as a result of observing for oneself {Subfig emp 47, 14-26). The Empiricists used two terms that are traditionally translated as 'experience', peira and empeiria. The Outline of Empiricism defines them not as activities, but as psychic states or forms of knowledge (notitia: ). Peira is 'autoptic knowledge', i.e., the knowledge one has as a result of an episode of observation (44, 6 ff .). Empeiria, on the other hand, is knowledge or memory of what has been observed to happen many times in the same way {Subfig emp 45, 24; 50, 23). The mention of memory is significant because the Empiricists seem to have held that knowledge

  • Experience as a Source 91

    was a form of memory (Galen, On Therapeutic Method; henceforward Meth med X 36, 3 Khn = fr. 46 Deichgrber), but that is another story.1

    According to these definitions, then, empeiria is a kind of knowledge that arises on the basis of many episodes of observation, each of which gives rise to an instance of peira. One has empeiria as opposed to peira when one has observed something often enough for the knowledge that one now has as a result to be expressed in a theorem {Subfig emp 45, 24 ff.). And this is the case when one is in a position to say, e.g., that the administration of such and such a remedy in cases of such and such a kind is followed by recovery always, for the most part, roughly half the time or rarely. In this favored sense, empeiria applies to expert knowl- edge, many instances of which, when they form a cluster (), make up a complete expertise or art {On Sects for Beginners', henceforward Sect ingred SM III, 13-16 Helmreich). And in what is perhaps the most privileged sense of all, the term empeiria applies to the art as a whole {Subfig emp 47, 26; 54, 10-13). This means that the contrast between experience and reason is indirect. Experience as knowledge and the activities that give rise to it are opposed to the activities of the faculty of reason (or a special form of it) and the knowledge to which they give rise, and reason as a faculty is opposed to the faculty or faculties which are responsible for experience (cf. Subfig emp 86, 23-87, 12).

    In Empiricist usage, however, the words for experience are not re- stricted to these meanings any more than autopsia is restricted to its official meaning. Empeiria, in particular, is often used in place of peira, and both are frequently used for the activities of perception and obser- vation that give rise to peira and empeiria in the sense of knowledge, just as activity words like 'autopsy' and 'observation' () are some- times used of the knowledge to which the activities give rise {Subfig emp 47, 26-48, 4; 48, 11-21).2 Nevertheless, the distinctions that we have seen are available make it easier to characterize ancient empiricism. Art or expertise is experience {empeiria) and experience, both in the sense of empeiria and that of peira, has its source in the activities of perception and observation. This knowledge is confined to what can be perceived or observed, items which are called phenomena, evident matters or percep- tibles by the Empiricists. One can, however, supplement the experience

    1 On this point see Frede, 1990.

    2 for [Galen], On the best sect, 1 131, 8-9 Khn = fr. 51 Deichgrber.

  • 92 James Allen

    one has as a result of one's own observation with history () - what one learns by reading and evaluating the reports of other people, which is ultimately based on their own observations (Subfig emp 47, 14-26).

    II

    It should be plain that a rather generous conception of experience, both in the sense of the activities of perception and observation and in the sense of the knowledge they yield, is presupposed. The phenomena or evident matters that are perceived or observed are things like people, animals, mountains or trees as well as certain states, qualities and activities of theirs like being green or running or having a fever. Ques- tions about how observation conceived in this way is ultimately based on what modern philosophers call immediate experience or bare sensa- tion receive little attention. Instead the focus is on how expert knowledge complete and systematic enough to qualify as an art, e.g., of medicine, can arise out of observation or experience of people, their activities, habits, diets, environments, symptoms and the like. Nonetheless, gener- ous as this conception of experience is, it restricts experience to knowl- edge that certain patterns of sequence and correlation among phenomena obtain. The causes which would explain why the patterns occur and recur as they do can be grasped, if at all, only by means of faculties other than those responsible for experience.

    The idea that it is only facts that which are accessible to experience is behind a way in which we use the term 'empirical', e.g., when we speak of an 'empirical question'. Our point when speaking in this way is less that the question has been or is likely to be resolved by experience than that, because the truth at issue is not determined by laws of nature or laws of reason or relations of ideas or the like - and therefore cannot be known by grasping how it is determined in one of these privileged ways - it is a contingent matter of fact that can be known, if at all, by experience. But it is important to note that it is possible to grasp facts, which are not empirical questions in this sense, as empirical truths. Something that we grasp as a fact that on the basis of experience may be the necessary consequence of the inalterable nature of things; and some- one in a position to grasp it as the necessary consequence of first principles will grasp it as more than a fact that. Aristotle's theory of knowledge, for example, depends on a contrast between grasping a truth

  • Experience as a Source 93

    as a fact of experience and grasping that same truth as required and explained by first principles.

    The disagreement between rationalism and empiricism, as it is usu- ally understood, presupposes a framework of common assumptions that was widely if not universally shared. They emerge especially clearly, for instance, in the account of the different epistemic conditions at the beginning of Aristotle's Metaphysics (A 1, 980a27 ff., 981a27 ff .).

    (i) Experience grasps only facts that;

    (ii) The causes that supply the reasons why these facts obtain, if they can be known at all, are the object of a separate rational faculty;

    (iii) Experience is prior to this rational faculty, whose insights, if and when possible, are nonetheless somehow based on experience.

    This framework was treated as uncontroversial by many philoso- phers and scientists in antiquity, especially in the Hellenistic period, when just about everyone seems to have been committed to an episte- mology that was broadly empiricist in the sense of taking all knowledge to be based, ultimately and in the last analysis, on a grasp of the evident. The Epicureans seem to have subscribed to an especially strong form of this position. Pronouncements of theirs to the effect that all knowledge either consists in or arises out of a grasp of the evident are not hard to find (e.g., Letter to Herodotus, 38; Diogenes Laertius X, 32). Nonetheless I mean to argue that the use Epicureanism made of the common empirical tradition led them to take a position which the framework could not accommodate or could accommodate only with very significant qualifi- cations. One way of putting this - though this too will require qualifi- cation - is to say that the Epicureans were committed to a still more generous conception of experience.

    Ill

    We can see this, among other places, in the apparently exhaustive scheme for assessing opinions as true or false proposed by Epicurus (DL X 34; Ep Hdt 51-2; Sextus Empiricus, M VII 211-16). Attestation and non-attestation ( and ) apply to evident matters; contestation and non-contestation ( and ) to nonevident matters. Falsity arises when an opinion is either not attested or is contested by the evident, truth when it is either

  • 94 James Allen

    attested or not contested by the evident. The opinion that that is Plato over there, for instance, awaits attestation. It can legitimately be accepted as true if, upon closer inspection, it is attested or rejected as false if, under the same conditions, it is not attested. An opinion about nonevident matters is contested when it has an observable consequence that obser- vation shows to be false; not contested when its observable consequences are not shown to be false by observation. Why the mere absence of contestation should confirm the truth of an opinion about the nonevi- dent is a notorious puzzle to which we shall turn in a moment; the use of contestation to eliminate false opinions, on the other hand, seems not to present a problem. Thus the false opinion that there is no void, which is the contradictory of the true Epicurean doctrine, is contested by the evident fact that there is motion, as there would not be if there were no void for bodies to move into - or so the Epicureans maintained (Ep Hdt 40; Lucretius 1 334).

    But suppose we connect contestation and non-attestation in the way that seems most obvious. Then a false opinion about nonevident matters will be contested when one of its observable consequences is not attested (in the appropriate conditions). Sometimes, when the observable conse- quence of the thesis to be contested is a universal negative, e.g., that there is no motion, this can be achieved by the attestation of a single counter- instance, assuming that we grant the unobjectionable principle that if is attested then not-P is not attested. One observed episode of motion will banish the denial of void and vindicate its contradictory.

    Matters are not always so simple, however. Consider, for example, the Epicurean argument for the principle that nothing comes to be from nothing. If it did, then anything could come to be anywhere at any time without the proper seeds, which is contested because not attested by observation (Ep Hdt 38; Lucretius 1 159 ff.). Or the argument that atoms cannot be of any size because, if they were, there would have to be visible atomic bodies, which is likewise not attested (Ep Hdt 55-6; Lucretius II 496-9).3 Yet as we have seen, attestation and non-attestation appear to establish only contingent matters of fact or empirical truths. A classical

    3 To be sure, he adds other reasons, e.g., that it is not possible to conceive how an atom could become visible. This may refer to his theory of vision, according to which vision is caused by the flow of invisible atomic films from the object being seen to the eyes. The problem would then be how an atom of this size could interact with the organs of visual perception.

  • Experience as a Source 95

    empiricist, a Humean descendent of his, or indeed anyone who sub- scribes to the framework described above, will patiently explain that the fact that episodes of random spontaneous generation or absolutely unbreakable objects have not been attested in our experience, and that recorded history contains no traces of them, does not by itself entitle us to conclude that one has not been overlooked or will not occur or be found in ten seconds, or ten years or ten million years. According to this familiar way of looking at things, no amount of observation or experi- ence by itself can rule it out as a possibility.

    It appears that something more is required to establish opinions of the kind that are candidates for contestation and non-contestation. We must somehow be able to tell that what is implied by the false opinion to be contested, e.g., the manifest episodes of random spontaneous generation that are implied by the opinion that creation ex nihilo is possible or the visible atoms that are implied by the opinion that atoms can be of any size, are not the sort or type or kind of thing that can happen or exist. But attestation and non-attestation through or by means of the evident do not seem to be equal to this task.

    The same result appears to follow if we approach matters from a different angle. The principal candidates for contestation, which can be rejected as false if contested and accepted as true if not contested, are theories, for example, the theories about meteorological matters that are discussed in the Letter to Pythocles (Ep Pyth). And the main source of these is analogy with the phenomena with us ( ') or, as translators often put it, 'in our experience7 (Ep Hdt 80). Inevitably it often happens that more than one theory about the nonevident causation of a natural phenomenon suggested by analogy remains uncontested (cf. Lucretius VI 703 ff.). Yet it appears that the status of such a theory is not like that of an opinion about an evident matter awaiting attestation by remaining epistemically possible, i.e., possible for all we know or can say, as long as it is not falsified by observation. Rather, Epicurus seems to have regarded all the theories compatible with the phenomena as objectively possible. Indeed, he seems to have held that they are true in the sense of being realized either at some time in our world or in some other world in the infinite universe (Lucretius V 526-33).

    Now suppose that one could somehow be on the moon in the way imagined by Aristotle in the Posterior Analytics and see which accounts of eclipses or waxing and waning do not obtain there (I 31, 87b39; II 90a26). Apparently, on the Epicurean view, the fact that these theories are not directly attested in these conditions would not show that they are false as claims about what might be or what is true in some world.

  • 96 James Allen

    Yet this is not how Epicurus treated our failures to observe episodes of random spontaneous generation or to find atoms of observable size. These revealed that certain phenomena - or objects or events that would have to be phenomena if they were capable of existing - are not the kind of things that can exist at all, and thereby refute certain theories once and for all.4 Trips to the moon or efforts to determine whether that is, say, Plato over there, by establishing contingent matters of fact, serve only to show that an opinion is false here or a theory does not apply in this cosmos.

    The way in which the two pairs - attestation and non-attestation, on the one hand, and contestation and non-contestation, on the other - are both said to take place 'through the evident' appears to conceal a gap between two quite different ways of grasping the evident and to leave the relation between them in the dark (Sextus Empiricus M VII 216). At any rate, this is how someone in sympathy with the framework that I outlined above is likely to feel.

    IV

    This suspicion is well founded, and it receives additional support from the use Epicurus makes of analogies with the phenomena in establishing theories about the nonevident. This use makes the most sense if it rests on the assumption that a grasp of the evident puts us in possession of truths not only, as we have seen, about what cannot be, but also about what, in very robust sense, can be. Near the end of the Letter to Herodotus, Epicurus says: 'seeing in how many ways the like comes to be with us ( '), one must theorize about the causes () of astro-

    4 The discussion of the shapes of the cosmoi in the Letter to Pythodes 88 might seem to count against this. There it is said that many shapes are possible because this is contested by none of the phenomena in this cosmos, whose boundary it is not possible to grasp. This could be taken to mean that the many possible cosmic shapes are not contested since we cannot grasp the shape of our own cosmos, with the implication that, if we could, all of the shapes apart from the one that belongs to our cosmos would be contested. In this case, their non-attestation here would contest the possibility of their obtaining anywhere at all. I take the point rather to be that the many possible shapes are not contested by phenomena within this cosmos, whose own boundary, like the way in which eclipses and many other phenomena come about in it, are, as it happens, unknown.

  • Experience as a Source 97

    nomical phenomena () and everything nonevident' (80). And in the Letter to Pythocles, he offers multiple explanations for a host of meteorological phenomena based on analogies with the behavior of medium sized physical objects that we can observe from close up.

    If every possibility is realized somewhere or at some time in the infinite universe, analogies suggested by observation of the phenomena among us will suggest theories that stand a good chance of being true in the sense that they are true of some episodes of the phenomenon to be explained at some time or in some cosmos. But is being suggested by the phenomena sufficient to show that a theory is genuinely possible, and therefore true in this way? Perhaps, despite having a better chance of being true on Epicurean assumptions than it would on other assump- tions, a theory suggested by an analogy with the phenomena has, so far, only been shown to be epistemically possible. It could still happen, for all we know or can say, that it is not genuinely or objectively possible. And if this is so, we shall be entitled to accept it as a genuine possibility only after it has survived the test of contestation by the phenomena. If it does not survive, then it only seemed to be genuinely possible.

    Some of Epicurus' language suggests an interpretation along these lines or is compatible with it (Ep Pyth 92, 93, 98-9). But there is also evidence suggesting that likeness of the right kind to a phenomenal analogue is sufficient to establish a theory about nonevident causation as true. In parts of the Letter to Pythocles, where explanations based on analogies with the phenomena in our experience are discussed, these phenomena are four times said to bid or call for the analogous explana- tions (87, 94, 100, 113). This may be merely suggestive, but in the same work, after remarking that the waxing and waning of the moon can come about in all the ways in which we observe similar phenomena coming about in our experience, and noting that the same is true of the way in which the moon gets its light and presents a visage to us, Epicurus says that someone who accepts one of the explanations and rejects the others will be in conflict () with the evident (96). And, after reviewing the explanations for the varying lengths of nights and days over the course of the year that are suggested by analogous occurrences in our experi- ence, Epicurus insists that it is necessary to speak of meteorological matters in a manner that is consonant or in agreement () with the phenomena, before going on to say that those who accept only one explanation are, once again, in conflict with the phenomena (98).

    It seems very much as if a theory's similarity to the phenomena is sufficient to ensure that it is in agreement with them, and that being in agreement with the phenomena guarantees that a theory is true, in the

  • 98 James Allen

    sense of being possible and true somewhere or at some time, for it is implied that to reject one of the explanations based on analogy with a phenomenon is to deny the reality of the phenomenon that it resembles. Perhaps theories undergo a double test. When put forward as universal explanations, holding of all times and places, they qualify as true if they are merely not contested by the phenomena, but when reformulated as claims about possibility, each has a contradictory, viz., the proposition that it is not possible, which is in conflict with the phenomenon that it resembles and which was the basis of the analogy that is its source. This would mean that theories - conceived as claims about objective possi- bility - follow from the phenomena to which they are analogous. The grounds that the phenomenon on which an analogous theory is based furnish for accepting the theory would then complement the grounds furnished by the fact that the theory is not contested by the phenomena quite generally.

    Epicurus' use of the vocabulary of signs and sign-inference of signs that seem to signify how nonevident matters are by being similar to them lends additional support to this suggestion (Ep Pyth 97; cf. 104). To reject some possible explanations while giving arbitrary preference to one is, he maintains, to be unable to grasp the phenomena as signs and to be carried into inconceivability (97). My guess is that the inconceivability that he means is that of denying that one instance of a type of behavior is possible when other manifest instances of it show that behavior of that type is possible.

    V

    For our present purpose, what matters most is that Epicurus was able to assign such an important part to analogy because he did not share the assumptions about what can and cannot fall under a grasp of the evident that are incorporated in the framework set out above. According to these assumptions, on the basis of such a grasp we know only that things have behaved as we have observed they did. This knowledge will make an empiricist, who relies only on experience, expect that events will coin- cide, follow and precede one another as they have been observed to, without in any way justifying his expectation. But Epicurus seems to suppose that, in grasping the phenomena, we grasp how things can and must be. I am tempted to go further and say that, according to Epicurus to grasp the phenomena is, within limits and in part, to understand the causes at work by grasping the natures in virtue of which ordinary

  • Experience as a Source 99

    medium sized objects act and behave as they do. Understanding how and why they behave as they do, we thereby see how bigger objects further away that are relevantly like them by sharing the nature respon- sible for their behavior must behave. The same holds mutatis mutandis for smaller objects whose distance from us may be negligible, but which are too small for us to perceive.

    Grasping true theories about the nonevident extends and deepens our understanding of the causes which explain and necessitate the behavior we are able to observe, but the sharp line which the framework takes to separate knowledge of the phenomena from the grasp of truths about what can and must be of the kind that figure in causal explanations appears not to be a part of Epicureanism.5 For adherents of the frame- work, anything that smacks of knowledge of natures, the necessities they impose and the possibilities they open up, is knowledge of the nonevi- dent, to be had, if it can be had at all, by inference or by means of another exercise of a special rational faculty distinct from experience. But as we have seen, this is not so for Epicurus and the Epicureans: the grasp of the evident, which precedes and secures all knowledge of the nonevident, must itself already be a grasp, however partial, of how things can and must be.

    Should we then say that the Epicureans were committed to a concep- tion of experience still more generous and richer than the one enshrined in the framework - the suggestion that I put forward for consideration above?6 Perhaps, but there are reasons to hesitate, most notably the fact that this is not something any Epicurean ever says or, I suspect, ever would say. The framework takes experience to be coordinate with evident matters or phenomena. They are accessible to experience, and the knowledge one has of them is experience. A better way of describing the distinctive character of the Epicurean position, I shall suggest, would be to say that this coordination does not obtain in Epicureanism.

    5 Perhaps this is what Epicurus is saying in a passage of the Letter to Pythocles, where he notes that 'signs about celestial matters are furnished by certain phenomena in our experience concerning which it is seen how they are' - unlike celestial phenom- ena themselves (87; cf. Ep Hat 80). N.B., however, that this reading is based on an emendation.

    6 This is something I have said elsewhere. See Allen, 2001, 196, 236-9.

  • 100 James Allen

    This becomes clear when we try to see what Epicurus and his follow- ers thought about ancient forms of empiricism. To judge by the available evidence, it is not a subject that Epicurus himself took much of an interest in.7 Philodemus is a different matter, however. On Signs and Sign-infer- ences (henceforward On Signs) defends the so called method of similarity, which would allow us to infer, e.g., that all human beings everywhere are mortal from the fact that those among us are or that atoms behave mutatis mutandis in the way visible bodies do from the fact that visible bodies behave in that way. The work is full of terms and notions from empiricism, which retain the meanings they have in it, e.g., peira and historia. And Philodemus directly confronts the problem that arises already in Epicurus, namely how observation of a finite sample, however large, of, say, human beings, can entitle us to conclude that all human beings everywhere are mortal. The occasion for the work is the challenge presented by unnamed opponents who raise precisely this problem. Yet Philodemus does not credit peira, the activity, with any more powers, or take the knowledge we have as a result of it to extend any further or penetrate any more deeply than empiricism does.8

    7 Consider, however, Letter to Herodotus, 79, where Epicurus remarks that what comes under history () about the risings, settings, eclipses and like matters does not contribute to blessedness because it leaves untouched fears that can block the way to happiness. His point is that it is possible to have a great deal of astronomical knowledge of this kind while remaining vulnerable to superstition, which can be banished only by a grasp of the natures () and principal causes ( ) underlying the phenomena. ', though not the exclusive property of Empiricists, was a key term of theirs, and this passage reads very much like a rejection of merely empirical astronomy in favor of a version that satisfies the rationalists' demand for explanation by way of natures and causes, albeit for reasons peculiar to Epicureanism.

    8 And in his work On rhetoric, using language that would not have been out of place in a Platonist inspired by the Gorgias, he maintains that practices grounded in observation and history, and , which he calls , are not arts properly speaking (Rhet II XXX 19 ff.; but cf. XXXVIII 2 ff.).

  • Experience as a Source 101

    VI

    How, then, are we able to infer conclusions about the nonevident from the phenomena? A crucial part in the Epicurean account appears to be played by epilogismos, which, or at least the term for which, was, as we noted, also used by the medical Empiricists. They stressed two features: that epilogismos is concerned exclusively with evident matters, unlike analogismos, the form of reasoning that is employed by the Rationalists and which allows them to deduce nonevident conclusions; and that it is the kind of reasoning employed by ordinary human beings in everyday life. They use it, for instance, of inferring one evident matter, which is temporarily nonevident, from another, which they call commemorative signification elsewhere, e.g., 'since there is smoke, there is fire' (Sect ingred 10, 23-4; 11, 9-10).

    As I noted above, however, this is not how the Epicureans used the term. An earlier tendency to render it as 'empirical inference' has been much criticized. Though Philodemus speaks frequently of the epilogismos of the phenomena, and even, in one especially badly preserved passage, of the application of epilogismos to what has been grasped by experience (peira) (fr. 4), a survey of Epicurean usage shows that it is often applied to items that are not obviously empirical. Epicurus himself speaks of the epilogismos of the end or telos, and one of Philodemus' authorities, Demetrius of Laconia, speaks intriguingly of his opponents' failure to apply epilogismos to their own method of inference (XXVIII 13 ff.). What is more, it is not obvious that the rational activity designated by 'epilo- gismos' is a matter of inference. Viewed in isolation, a few passages seem to suggest that epilogismos is the inference of the nonevident conclusion from evident signs (XXII 37 ff .), but it is plain from a fuller survey of the evidence that epilogismos belongs to a preliminary phase prior to the inference of a nonevident conclusion, for which the terms 'sign-infer- ence' () or 'reasoning' () are reserved.9 Philode- mus speaks of advancing or making a transition to a nonevident conclusion through or by means of epilogismos because epilogismos is an indispensable precondition for the inference, not the inference proper.

    The noun and the verb occur in several different constructions. We find the verb used with a direct object and

    9 Cf. Barnes, 1988, 130-1, Sedley, 1978, 27-34, and especially Schofield, 1996.

  • 102 James Allen

    the noun taking an objective genitive, e.g., the epilogismos of the end or of the phenomena which have already been mentioned.10 The verb can be used to introduce a subordinate clause that, with which we seem to come closest to reasoning as inference or deduction.11 And there are constructions in which the verb takes a direct object and introduces a subordinate clause - the 'consider the lilies, how they grow' construc- tion especially familiar in Greek verbs 'to know', where the subordinate clause unpacks in propositional form what it is one knows o/an item in knowing it (Philodemus, On Signs XXVIII 15-25; cf. Epicurus, Men 133, where the construction is implicit).

    Though the last construction is rare, the fact that it is possible may help us. Suppose we distinguish between the materials to which reason- ing is applied and its upshot or result. I hesitate to say 'conclusion' because I do not want to prejudge the question of whether the reasoning at issue is a form of deduction or inference, though the premises of an inference may perhaps be viewed as one kind of material and its conclu- sion as one kind of upshot or result. The distinguishing feature of epilogistic reasoning, signaled by the prefix epi-, would then be that the materials to which one applies it and that about which one knows, or knows better, as a result are the same.12 Passages in which epilogismos/epi- logizesihai takes a direct object or objective genitive, signifying the mate- rial to which epilogistic reasoning is applied, and passages in which epilogismos/epilogizesthai introduces a subordinate clause, signifying the upshot or conclusion of the reasoning, would then be incomplete speci- fications of part of a whole instance of epilogistic reasoning.

    Whether every use of 'epilogismos' can be made to fit this pattern, I do not know. But if this is the basic idea, it might explain some things about both the Epicurean and Empiricist uses of the term. For instance, though it is far from clear that this distinction is marked in Epicureanism, according to the Empiricists, what distinguishes epilogismos from the analogismos of the rationalists is that it never departs from the phenom-

    10 With a direct object: Epicurus, Ep Hdt 72, Letter to Menoeceus 133, Principal Doctrines XXII; Philodemus, On Signs XIII 32. With an objective genitive: Epicurus, Principle Doctrines XX; Philodemus, On Signs XXII 37, XXVII 23.

    11 Epicurus, Vatican Sayings 35, Ep Hdt 73; Philodemus, On Signs XXVIII 16

    12 For these ideas about epilogismos and analogismos see Schofield, 1996, nn. 8 (which contains suggestions of David Sedley) and 12.

  • Experience as a Source 103

    ena, while analogismos, though it sets out from the phenomena, proceeds to the utterly different, namely the completely nonevident {Sect ingred 106, 4-7).13 Strictly speaking, the Empiricists maintain, nothing can be known on the basis of something else, but everything has need of knowledge from itself (105, 27).

    To be sure, if sign-inferences of the kind exemplified by the inference from smoke to fire are instances of epilogismos, it must in some way permit us to know one thing from another. Indeed in the part of his account of Empiricism from which these citations come, Galen tells us that the Empiricists say that epilogismos is useful for the discovery () of what they call temporarily nonevident matters (107, 34 ff.). But there is much talk of epilogismos as the logos of the phenomena (Subfig emp 62, 23-7; Sect ingred 11, 8; On Medical Experience, 133-5 Walzer), and one admittedly rather obscure passage describes it as the rational con- sideration of what follows on each thing ([Soranus], Medical Questions 50 = fr. 12 Deichgrber). Perhaps the gap can be closed to some extent by supposing that, in its primary sense, the Empiricists' epilogismos is the application of reason to the phenomena, and that sign-inference from one phenomenon to another, temporarily nonevident phenomenon con- joined with it in past experience can also be called 'epilogismos' because it is an application of epilogismos in this sense.

    Malcolm Schofield has proposed 'assessment' or 'comparative assess- ment' as a translation of 'epilogismos' as it is used by the Epicureans. But perhaps 'assessment' or 'rational assessment' would also cover Empirical epilogismos conceived in this way as well. The differences that remain between the two schools include the already noted fact that epilogismos is confined to the phenomena by the Empiricists, who seem to treat this as part of its meaning, but not by the Epicureans. But even so, both schools would agree that epilogismos, when of the phenomena, cannot by itself yield conclusions about matters other than phenomena. Something further is required to infer nonevident conclusions. The Epicureans are confident that we can make such inferences; the Empiri- cists are not. The critical difference between them concerns the knowl- edge that Epicurean epilogismos of the phenomena yields. The Empiricist knows that certain phenomena coincide, precede or follow

    13 Cf , to refer one thing to another, or , to reduce one thing to another.

  • 104 James Allen

    one another, in certain patterns and with certain relative frequencies. On the basis of this knowledge, he can, in a manner of speaking, reason about the phenomena and form reasonable expectations about unob- served observables or phenomena to be. As a result of his epilogismos, on the other hand, the Epicurean has a grasp, however incomplete and partial, of the natures and powers of the items he is studying. And on this basis he is able to infer that unobserved and even unobservable items must be the same or similar.

    VII

    If the Epicureans had, as I put it earlier, a still more generous conception of experience than that admitted by the framework, then it is not one they described in terms drawn from the standard empirical vocabulary. The activities that went under the head of 'experience' remained capable only of grasping facts that, devoid of necessity and explanatory power. If you will, Epicurean epistemology depends on a more than empirical grasp or comprehension of the phenomena or the evident. It is pretty clear that epilogismos, to which Epicurus had already appealed, was enlisted by Philodemus' Epicurean authorities to close a gap between the deliverances of experience and the grasp of the phenomena that is necessary if sign-inferences to the nonevident are to be possible. It is also a fair guess that their opponents responded by taking epilogistic reason- ing to be a matter of inference or deduction. Having elicited the admis- sion that experience by itself tells us nothing about how things must be, they could then proceed by demanding to know how an inference from the data of experience can yield a grasp of the phenomena which is at once the upshot or result of epilogismos and a sufficient basis for sign-in- ferences to the nonevident.

    Thus, if the framework cannot accommodate Epicurean views, it is not because the Epicureans explicitly disavow the assumptions that compose it. Indeed such evidence as we have suggests they might have been willing to endorse claims about the limits of experience strictly so called. Yet the fact that they do not take experience to be coordinate with the phenomena and, as I put it earlier, permit a more than empirical grasp or comprehension of the phenomena, means that this tells us less about Epicureanism than it otherwise might. This is not the comprehen- sion of the phenomena that we have when we view them in the light of first principles or as effects of their underlying causes because it is an essential precondition for aetiology. According to orthodox adherents to

  • Experience as a Source 105

    the framework, experience plays this part, whereas for Epicureans, experience merely prepares the way for the more than empirical grasp of the phenomena that in turn supports rational insights about nonevi- dent matters. If 'experience' were simply the name for the grasp or comprehension of the phenomena that precedes aetiology, then the Epicureans would disavow the restrictions on empirical knowledge imposed by the framework.

    I suggest that we look at matters in this way. Sometimes, when philosophers like Plato and Aristotle defended one position and op- posed another, they were not taking a familiar position in a dispute that was already being conducted along well defined lines so much as creating a new way of understanding the issues. When the medical Empiricists defend the claim that experience can by itself give rise to artistic knowledge, it is an impoverished form of experience, experience as conceived and marked off from reason by Plato and Aristotle. But it is doubtful that earlier figures who made large claims for experience drew the lines quite so sharply. Rather, from the point of view of Plato and Aristotle, it was probably fairer to say that they failed to see that knowledge of the kind which they assumed could be explained by experience and perception alone actually requires a separate rational faculty with distinctive powers of its own. In this respect, as in others, Epicurus is something of a throwback.14

    14 I am grateful for comments and criticism to the participants in the conference, to the speakers and audience at Philosophy in Assos, July 2004, where I delivered a paper related to this one, and to the participants in the Pittsburgh /Athens Symposium, October 2000, where I first presented some of these ideas as a commentator on Michael Frede's paper, 'Experience in the ancient "Empiricists'' '.

    Bibliography

    Allen, James. 2001. Inference from Signs: Ancient Debates about the Nature of Evidence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Annas, J. and Grimm, R.H., eds. 1988. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, suppl. vol. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Barnes, Jonathan. 1988. 'Epicurean Signs', in Annas and Grimm, eds. 91-134. De Lacy, P.H. and E.A., eds. 2nd edn. 1978. Philodemus: On Methods of Inference. Naples:

    Bibliopolis.

  • 106 James Allen

    Deichgrber, Karl, ed. 2nd edn. 1965. Die griechische Empirikerschule: Sammlung der Frag- mente und Darstellung der Lehre. Berlin: Weidmann.

    Everson, S. ed. 1990. Companions to Ancient Thought 1: Epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Frede, M. 1990. 'An empiricist view of knowledge: memorising in Everson, ed. 225-50. Frede, M. and Striker, G., eds. 1996. Rationality in Greek Thought. Oxford: Oxford University

    Press. Schofield, M. 1996. 'Epilogismos: An Appraisal', in Frede and Striker, eds. 221-37. Sedley, D. 1973. 'Epicurus on Nature Book XVIIF. Cronache ercolanesi 3: 5-83.

    Article Contentsp. [89]p. 90p. 91p. 92p. 93p. 94p. 95p. 96p. 97p. 98p. 99p. 100p. 101p. 102p. 103p. 104p. 105p. 106

    Issue Table of ContentsApeiron: A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science, Vol. 37, No. 4, RE-INVENTIONS: ESSAYS ON HELLENISTIC & EARLY ROMAN SCIENCE (December 2004), pp. 1-153Front MatterIntroduction [pp. 1-8]New Issues in the History of Ancient Science [pp. 9-27]Hero of Alexandria's Mechanical Geometry [pp. 29-56]Remarks on Physics and Mathematical Astronomy and Optics in Epicurus, Sextus Empiricus, and Some Stoics [pp. 57-87]Experience as a Source and Ground of Theory in Epicureanism [pp. 89-106]Medical and Ethnic Identities in Hellenistic Egypt [pp. 107-131]Back Matter