A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

37
Presenting Analysis, Context, and Criticism on Nonfiction Works An Offprint from Nonfiction Classics for Students

Transcript of A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

Page 1: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

Presenting Analysis, Context, and Criticism onNonfiction Works

An Offprint from

NonfictionClassics

for Students

Page 2: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

Nonfiction Classics for Students

Project EditorDavid Galens

EditorialSara Constantakis, Elizabeth A. Cranston,Kristen A. Dorsch, Anne Marie Hacht,Madeline S. Harris, Arlene Johnson, MichelleKazensky, Ira Mark Milne, Polly Rapp, PamRevitzer, Mary Ruby, Kathy Sauer, JenniferSmith, Daniel Toronto, Carol Ullmann

ResearchMichelle Campbell, Nicodemus Ford, SarahGenik, Tamara C. Nott, Tracie Richardson

Data CaptureBeverly Jendrowski

PermissionsMary Ann Bahr, Margaret Chamberlain, KimDavis, Debra Freitas, Lori Hines, Jackie Jones,Jacqueline Key, Shalice Shah-Caldwell

Imaging and MultimediaRandy Bassett, Dean Dauphinais, RobertDuncan, Leitha Etheridge-Sims, Mary Grimes,Lezlie Light, Jeffrey Matlock, Dan Newell,Dave Oblender, Christine O'Bryan, Kelly A.Quin, Luke Rademacher, Robyn V. Young

Product DesignMichelle DiMercurio, Pamela A. E. Galbreath,Michael Logusz

ManufacturingStacy Melson

© 2001-2002; © 2002 by Gale. Gale is animprint of The Gale Group, Inc., a division ofThomson Learning, Inc.

Gale and Design® and Thomson Learning ™are trademarks used herein under license.

For more information, contactThe Gale Group, Inc 27500 Drake Rd.Farmington Hills, MI 48334-3535Or you can visit our Internet site athttp://www.gale.com

ALL RIGHTS RESERVED.No part of this work covered by the copyrighthereon may be reproduced or used in anyform or by any means—graphic, electronic, ormechanical, including photocopying, record-ing, taping, Web distribution or informationstorage retrieval systems—without the writtenpermission of the publisher.

For permission to use material from this prod-uct, submit your request via Web athttp://www.gale-edit.com/permissions, or youmay download our Permissions Request formand submit your request by fax or mail to:

Permissions DepartmentThe Gale Group, Inc27500 Drake Rd.Farmington Hills, MI 48331-3535Permissions Hotline: 248-699-8006 or 800-877-4253, ext. 8006Fax: 248-699-8074 or 800-762-4058

Since this page cannot legibly accommo-date all copyright notices, the acknowl-edgments constitute an extension of thecopyright notice.

While every effort has been made tosecure permission to reprint material andto ensure the reliability of the informa-tion presented in this publication, TheGale Group, Inc. does not guarantee the accu-racy of the data contained herein. The GaleGroup, Inc. accepts no payment for listing; andinclusion in the publication of any organiza-tion, agency, institution, publication, service,or individual does not imply endorsement ofthe editors or publisher. Errors brought to theattention of the publisher and verified to thesatisfaction of the publisher will be correctedin future editions.

Printed in the United States of America

ISSN 1533-7561

Page 3: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

x i

IntroductionPurpose of the Book

The purpose of Nonfiction Classics for Stu-dents (NCfS) is to provide readers with a guide tounderstanding, enjoying, and studying nonfictionworks by giving them easy access to informationabout the work. Part of Gale’s ‘‘For Students’’literature line, NCfS is specifically designed to meetthe curricular needs of high school and undergradu-ate college students and their teachers, as well as theinterests of general readers and researchers consid-ering specific works. While each volume containsentries on ‘‘classic’’ works frequently studied inclassrooms, there are also entries containing hard-to-find information on contemporary pieces, in-cluding works by multicultural, international, andwomen authors.

The information covered in each entry includesan introduction to the work and the work’s author; asummary, to help readers unravel and understandthe events in a work; descriptions of key figures,including explanation of a given figure’s role in thework as well as discussion about that figure’s rela-tionship to other figures in the work; analysis ofimportant themes in the work; and an explanation ofimportant literary techniques and movements asthey are demonstrated in the work.

In addition to this material, which helps thereaders analyze the work itself, students are alsoprovided with important information on the literaryand historical background informing each work.

This includes a historical context essay, a boxcomparing the time or place the work was written tomodern Western culture, a critical essay, and ex-cerpts from critical essays on the work, when avail-able. A unique feature of NCfS is a specially com-missioned critical essay on each work, targetedtoward the student reader.

To further aid the student in studying andenjoying each work, information on media adapta-tions is provided, as well as reading suggestions forworks of fiction and nonfiction on similar themesand topics. Classroom aids include ideas for re-search papers and lists of critical sources that pro-vide additional material on each work.

Selection CriteriaThe titles for each volume of NCfS were se-

lected by surveying numerous sources on teachingliterature and analyzing course curricula for variousschool districts. Some of the sources surveyed in-cluded: literature anthologies; Reading Lists forCollege-Bound Students: The Books Most Recom-mended by America’s Top Colleges; a CollegeBoard survey of works commonly studied in highschools; a National Council of Teachers of English(NCTE) survey of works commonly studied in highschools; Arthur Applebee’s 1993 study Literaturein the Secondary School: Studies of Curriculum andInstruction in the United States; and the ModernLibrary’s list of the one hundred best nonfictionworks of the century.

Page 4: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

I n t r o d u c t i o n

N o n f i c t i o n C l a s s i c s f o r S t u d e n t sx i i

Input was also solicited from our expert advi-sory board, as well as educators from various areas.From these discussions, it was determined that eachvolume should have a mix of ‘‘classic’’ works(those works commonly taught in literature classes)and contemporary works for which information isoften hard to find. Because of the interest in ex-panding the canon of literature, an emphasis wasalso placed on including works by international,multicultural, and women authors. Our advisoryboard members—educational professionals—helpedpare down the list for each volume. If a work wasnot selected for the present volume, it was oftennoted as a possibility for a future volume. Asalways, the editor welcomes suggestions for titles tobe included in future volumes.

How Each Entry Is OrganizedEach entry, or chapter, in NCfS focuses on one

work. Each entry heading lists the full name of thework, the author’s name, and the date of the work’spublication. The following elements are containedin each entry:

• Introduction: a brief overview of the workwhich provides information about its initialpublication, its literary standing, any contro-versies surrounding the work, and major con-flicts or themes within the work.

• Author Biography: this section includes basicfacts about the author’s life and focuses onevents and times in the author’s life that in-spired the work in question.

• Summary: a description of the major events inthe work. Subheads demarcate the work’s vari-ous chapters or sections.

• Key Figures: an alphabetical listing of majorfigures in the work. Each name is followed by abrief to an extensive description of the person’srole in the works, as well as discussion of thefigure’s actions, relationships, and possiblemotivation.

Figures are listed alphabetically by last name. Ifa figure is unnamed—for instance, the narrator inPilgrim at Tinker Creek—the figure is listed as‘‘The Narrator’’ and alphabetized as ‘‘Narra-tor.’’ If a person’s first name is the only onegiven, the name will appear alphabetically by thename. Variant names are also included for eachperson. Thus, the full name ‘‘Richard MoncktonMilnes’’ would head the listing for a figure in

The Education of Henry Adams, but listed in aseparate cross-reference would be his more for-mal name ‘‘Lord Houghton.’’

• Themes: a thorough overview of how the majortopics, themes, and issues are addressed withinthe work. Each theme discussed appears in aseparate subhead, and is easily accessed throughthe boldface entries in the Subject/Theme Index.

• Style: this section addresses important style ele-ments of the work, such as setting, point ofview, and narration; important literary devicesused, such as imagery, foreshadowing, sym-bolism; and, if applicable, genres to which thework might have belonged, such as Gothicismor Romanticism. Literary terms are explainedwithin the entry but can also be found in theGlossary.

• Historical Context: This section outlines thesocial, political, and cultural climate in whichthe author lived and the work was created. Thissection may include descriptions of relatedhistorical events, pertinent aspects of daily lifein the culture, and the artistic and literarysensibilities of the time in which the work waswritten. If the piece is a historical work, infor-mation regarding the time in which the work isset is also included. Each section is brokendown with helpful subheads.

• Critical Overview: this section provides back-ground on the critical reputation of the work,including bannings or any other public contro-versies surrounding the work. For older works,this section includes a history of how the workwas first received and how perceptions of itmay have changed over the years; for morerecent works, direct quotes from early reviewsmay also be included.

• Criticism: an essay commissioned by NCfSwhich specifically deals with the work and iswritten specifically for the student audience, aswell as excerpts from previously publishedcriticism on the work, when available.

• Sources: an alphabetical list of critical materialused in the compilation of the entry, with fullbibliographical information.

• Further Reading: an alphabetical list of othercritical sources that may prove useful for thestudent. It includes full bibliographical infor-mation and a brief annotation.

Page 5: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

I n t r o d u c t i o n

V o l u m e 4 x i i i

In addition, each entry contains the followinghighlighted sections, set separate from the main text:

• Media Adaptations: a list of important film andtelevision adaptations of the work, includingsource information. The list may also includesuch variations on the work as audio record-ings, musical adaptations, and other stageinterpretations.

• Topics for Further Study: a list of potentialstudy questions or research topics dealing withthe work. This section includes questions re-lated to other disciplines the student may bestudying, such as American history, world his-tory, science, math, government, business, ge-ography, economics, psychology, etc.

• Compare and Contrast: an ‘‘at-a-glance’’ com-parison of the cultural and historical differ-ences between the author’s time and cultureand late twentieth-century/early twenty-firstcentury Western culture. This box includespertinent parallels between the major scien-tific, political, and cultural movements of thetime or place the work was written, the time orplace the work was set (if a historical work),and modern Western culture. Works writtenafter 1990 may not have this box.

• What Do I Read Next?: a list of works thatmight complement the featured work or serveas a contrast to it. This includes works by thesame author and others, works of fiction andnonfiction, and works from various genres,cultures, and eras.

Other FeaturesNCfS includes ‘‘Literature: Conversation, Com-

munication, Idea, Emotion,’’ a foreword by CarolDell’Amico, an educator and author. This essayexamines nonfiction as a lasting way for authors tocommunicate as well as the influence these workscan have. Dell’Amico also discusses how Nonfic-tion Classics for Students can help teachers showstudents how to enrich their own reading experi-ences and how the series is designed to aid studentsin their study of particular works.

A Cumulative Author/Title Index lists the au-thors and titles covered in each volume of the NCfSseries.

A Cumulative Nationality/Ethnicity Index breaksdown the authors and titles covered in each volumeof the NCfS series by nationality and ethnicity.

A Subject/Theme Index, specific to each vol-ume, provides easy reference for users who may bestudying a particular subject or theme rather than asingle work. Significant subjects from events tobroad themes are included, and the entries pointingto the specific theme discussions in each entry areindicated in boldface.

Entries may include illustrations, including pho-tos of the author, stills from stage productions, andstills from film adaptations.

Citing Nonfiction Classics for StudentsWhen writing papers, students who quote di-

rectly from any volume of Nonfiction Classics forStudents may use the following general forms.These examples are based on MLA style; teachersmay request that students adhere to a different style,so the following examples may be adapted as needed.

When citing text from NCfS that is not attrib-uted to a particular author (for example, the Themes,Style, Historical Context sections, etc.), the follow-ing format should be used in the bibliography section:

‘‘The Journalist and the Murderer.’’ Nonfiction Clas-sics for Students. Ed. Elizabeth Thomason. Vol. 1.Farmington Hills, MI: The Gale Group, 2001, pp.153–56.

When quoting the specially commissioned es-say from NCfS (usually the first piece under the"Criticism" subhead), the following format shouldbe used:

Hart, Joyce. Critical Essay on ‘‘Silent Spring.’’ Non-fiction Classics for Students. Ed. Elizabeth Thomason.Vol. 1. Farmington Hills, MI: The Gale Group, 2001,pp. 316–19.

When quoting a journal or newspaper essaythat is reprinted in a volume of NCfS, the followingform may be used:

Limon, John. ‘‘The Double Helix as Literature.’’Raritan Vol. 5, No. 3 (Winter 1986), pp. 26–47;excerpted and reprinted in Nonfiction Classics forStudents, Vol. 2, ed. Elizabeth Thomason (Farming-ton Hills, MI: The Gale Group, 2001), pp. 84–95.

When quoting material reprinted from a bookthat appears in a volume of NCfS, the followingform may be used:

Gunnars, Kristjana. ‘‘Life as Fiction: Narrative Appro-priation in Isak Dinesen’s Out of Africa,’’ in IsakDinesen and Narrativity, ed. Gurli A. Woods, (CarletonUniversity Press, 1990), pp. 25–34; excerpted andreprinted in Nonfiction Classics for Students, Vol. 2,ed. Elizabeth Thomason (Farmington Hills, MI: TheGale Group, 2001), pp. 281–86.

Page 6: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

I n t r o d u c t i o n

N o n f i c t i o n C l a s s i c s f o r S t u d e n t sx i v

We Welcome Your SuggestionsThe editor of Nonfiction Classics for Students

welcomes your comments and ideas. Readers whowish to suggest works to appear in future volumesor who have other suggestions are cordially invitedto contact the editor. You may contact the editor viaE-mail at: [email protected]. Or writeto the editor at:

Editor, Nonfiction Classics for StudentsThe Gale Group27500 Drake Rd.Farmington Hills, MI 48331–3535

Page 7: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

x v i i

AcknowledgmentsThe editors wish to thank the copyright holders

of the excerpted criticism included in this volumeand the permissions managers of many book andmagazine publishing companies for assisting us insecuring reproduction rights. We are also grateful tothe staffs of the Detroit Public Library, the Libraryof Congress, the University of Detroit Mercy Li-brary, Wayne State University Purdy/Kresge LibraryComplex, and the University of Michigan Librariesfor making their resources available to us. Follow-ing is a list of the copyright holders who havegranted us permission to reproduce material in thisvolume of Nonfiction Classics for Students (NCfS).Every effort has been made to trace copyright, but ifomissions have been made, please let us know.

COPYRIGHTED MATERIALS IN NCfS,VOLUME 3, WERE REPRODUCED FROMTHE FOLLOWING PERIODICALS:

American Literature, v. 68, June, 1996. Copy-right © 1986 by Duke University Press. Reproducedby permission.—Challenge, v. 36, July-August,1993 for “The Heresies of John Kenneth Galbraith”by Thomas Karier. Reproduced by permission ofthe author.—Colby Quarterly, v. XXXII, Decem-ber, 1986. Reproduced by permission.—Criticism,v. V, Winter, 1963. Copyright, 1963, Wayne StateUniversity Press. Reproduced by permission ofWayne State University Press.—Eire-Ireland, v.IX, 1974. Copyright 1974 Irish American Cul-tural Institute. Reproduced by permission.—Jour-

nal of Economic Issues, v. XXIII, June, 1989for “Rereading the Affluent Society” by RobertHeilbroner. Reproduced by permission of the au-thor.—Melus, v. 11, Winter, 1984. CopyrightMELUS: The Society for the Study of Multi-EthnicLiterature of the United States, 1984. Reproducedby permission.—The Nation, New York, v. 267,November 16, 1998. © 1998 The Nation magazine/The Nation Company, Inc. Reproduced by permis-sion.—Progressive, v. 57, June, 1993. Copyright ©1993 by The Progressive, Inc. Reproduced by per-mission of The Progressive, 409 East Main Street,Madison, WI 53703.—Yeats, v. II, 1984. Copyright© 1984 by Cornell University. All rights reserved.Reproduced by permission.

COPYRIGHTED MATERIALS IN NCfS,VOLUME 3, WERE REPRODUCED FROMTHE FOLLOWING BOOKS:

Bloom, Harold. From Sigmond Freud’s ‘‘TheInterpretation of Dreams.’’ Edited by Harold Bloom.Chelsea House Publishers, 1987. © 1987 by ChelseaHouse Publishers. All rights reserved. Reproducedby permission.—Busby, Mark. From Ralph Ellison.Edited by Warren French. Twayne, 1991. Repro-duced by permission.—Frieden, Ken. From Freud’sDream of Interpretation. State University of NewYork Press, 1990. Reproduced by permission.—Martin, Rex. From Rawls and Rights. UniversityPress of Kansas, 1985. Reproduced by permissionof the author.—O’Meally, Robert G. From The

Page 8: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A c k n o w l e d g m e n t s

N o n f i c t i o n C l a s s i c s f o r S t u d e n t sx v i i i

Craft of Ralph Ellison. Harvard University Press,1980. Reproduced by permission.—Packer, B. L.From Emerson’s Fall: A New Interpretation ofthe Major Essays. Continuum, 1982. Copyright ©1982 by B. L. Packer. All rights reserved. Repro-duced by permission.—Rowe, John Carlos. FromThrough the Custom House: Nineteenth-CenturyAmerican Fiction and Modern Theory. Johns Hop-kins University Press, 1982. Copyright © 1982by The Johns Hopkins University Press. Repro-duced by permission.—Wolheim, Richard. From“Dreams,” in Sigmond Freud’s “The Interpreta-tion of Dreams.” Edited by Harold Bloom. ChelseaHouse Publishers, 1987. © 1987 by Chelsea HousePublishers. All rights reserved. Reproduced bypermission.

PHOTOGRAPHS AND ILLUSTRATIONSAPPEARING IN NCfS, VOLUME 3, WERERECEIVED FROM THE FOLLOWINGSOURCES:

An Alzheimer’s patient receives a visitor in along-term health-care facility, photograph. PrenticeHall, Inc./Simon & Schuster/PH College. Repro-duced by permission.—Aschner, Jacob and Samuel,photograph. © Corbis. Reproduced by permission.—Bombed buildings, Dresden, Germany, 1946, pho-tograph. CORBIS/Bettmann. Reproduced by per-mission.—Civil rights marchers walking along Route80, photograph. AP/Wide World Photos. Repro-duced by permission.—Crowds gathering for Christ-mas, photograph. © Bettmann/Corbis. Reproducedby permission.—Ellison, Ralph (wearing suit andglasses), photograph. Archive Photos. Reproducedby permission.—Emerson, Ralph Waldo, engravingby S.A. Choff c. 1878. The Library of Congress.—Escobar, Pablo, photograph. AP/Wide World Pho-tos. Reproduce by permission.—Faludi, Susan, SanFrancisco, California, photograph. AP/Wide WorldPhotos. Reproduced by permission.—Farmer, James,Bogalusa, Louisiana, 1965, photograph. AP/WideWorld Photos. Reproduced by permission.—Freud,Sigmund, photograph. The Library of Congress.—Friedan, Betty, 1978, photograph. AP/Wide World

Photos. Reproduced with permission.—Galbraith,John Kenneth, photograph. The Library of Con-gress.—Gregory, Augusta, photograph. The Libraryof Congress.—Hines, Earl, 1939, Savoy Ballroom,Harlem, photograph by Charles Peterson. ArchivePhotos, Inc. Reproduced by permission.—Hobbes,Thomas, drawing. Archive Photos, Inc. Reproducedby permission.—Interior of Sigmund Freud’s study,photograph. Archive Photos, Inc. Reproduced bypermission.—Interior of the study in Ralph WaldoEmerson, photograph. The Library of Congress.—Klemperer, Victor, photograph. The Granger Col-lection, New York. Reproduced by permission.—Lamott, Annie, photograph. Getty Images. Repro-duced by permission.—Malcolm X, photograph.AP/Wide World Photos. Reproduced by permis-sion.—Marquez, Gabriel Garcia, 1982, photograph.AP/Wide World Photos. Reproduced by permis-sion.—Mill, John Stuart, drawing. Archive Photos,Inc. Reproduced by permission.—Muhammad, Eli-jah, speaking at a press conference, photograph. ©Bettmann/Corbis. Reproduced by permission.—“Oedipus and The Sphinx,” oil painting by JeanAuguste Dominique Ingres. © National GalleryCollection. By kind permission of the Trustees ofthe National Gallery, London/Corbis. Reproducedby permission.—Pedestrians walking along LenoxAvenue in Harlem, New York, photograph. ©Bettmann/Corbis. Reproduced by permission.—Reduced plan of hand drawn map of Walden Pond,drawing.—Rodriguez, Richard, photograph by RogerRessmeyer. CORBIS. Reproduced by permission.—Rodriguez, Richard, visiting the Sacred Heart School,photograph by Roger Ressmeyer. Corbis. Repro-duced by permission.—Schlafly, Phyllis, photo-graph. AP/Wide World Photos. Reproduced withpermission.—Thoreau, Henry David, drawing. TheLibrary of Congress.—Thoreau, Henry David’s birth-place. The Granger Collection Ltd.—Washington,Denzel, in title role in the film “Malcolm X” 1992,photograph. The Kobal Collection. Reproduced bypermission.—Wilde, Oscar, photograph. The Libraryof Congress.—Yeats, William Butler, photograph.The Library of Congress.

Page 9: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

2 9 5

A Theory of JusticeJohn Rawls

1971

A Theory of Justice (1971), by John Rawls, is ‘‘oneof the most influential works in moral and politicalphilosophy written in the twentieth century,’’ ac-cording to Samuel Freeman in the Collected Papersof John Rawls (1999).

A Theory of Justice is Rawls’s attempt to for-mulate a philosophy of justice and a theoreticalprogram for establishing political structures de-signed to preserve social justice and individualliberty. Rawls writes in reaction to the then pre-dominant theory of utilitarianism, which posits thatjustice is defined by that which provides the greatestgood for the greatest number of people. Rawlsproposes a theoretical person who, shrouded in aveil of ignorance, must design a just society withoutforeknowledge of his or her own status in thatsociety. Rawls asserts that from this objective van-tage point, which he calls the original position, theindividual will choose a system of justice thatadequately provides for those positioned on thelowest rungs of society. The individual will do sobecause he or she may end up in such a disadvan-taged position and will want to be adequately pro-vided for. Rawls draws from earlier theories ofpolitical philosophy that posit a social contract bywhich individuals implicitly agree to the terms onwhich they are governed in any society. Rawlsconcludes that such a social contract, formulatedfrom the perspective of the original position, willguarantee a just society without sacrificing thehappiness or liberty of any one individual.

Page 10: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

N o n f i c t i o n C l a s s i c s f o r S t u d e n t s2 9 6

Rawls addresses issues of liberty, social equal-ity, democracy, and the conflict of interests betweenthe individual and society.

Author Biography

John Bordley Rawls is one of the most influentialphilosophers of the twentieth century. He was bornon February 21, 1921, in Baltimore, Maryland, theson of William Lee Rawls and Anna Abel (Stump)Rawls. Rawls received a bachelor of arts degreefrom Princeton University in 1943. During WorldWar II, he served in the military, stationed in thePacific. He attended Cornell University for a yearfrom 1947–1948 and earned a doctorate from Prince-ton in 1950. In 1949, he married Margaret WarfieldFox, with whom he had four children.

Throughout his academic career, Rawls heldposts in philosophy departments at several presti-gious universities in England and the United States,including Princeton University, Oxford University,Cornell University, and the Massachusetts Instituteof Technology. He became a professor of philoso-phy at Harvard University in 1962, where he re-mained through his semi-retirement as professoremeritus. As an academic, Rawls was active inseveral national organizations, serving as presidentof the American Association of Political and LegalPhilosophers from 1970–1972, and president of theAmerican Philosophical Association in 1974. Healso co-edited the journal Philosophical Reviewfrom 1956–1959.

Rawls’s masterpiece of political philosophy, ATheory of Justice, was first published in 1971.Although he wrote numerous articles in academicjournals, Rawls did not publish another book untilthe 1990s. Justice as Fairness and Two Concepts ofRules both appeared in 1991, followed by PoliticalLiberalism in 1993. John Rawls: Collected Papers,edited by Samuel Freeman, was published in 1999,and Rawls’s Lectures on the History of MoralPhilosophy, edited by Barbara Herman, was pub-lished in 2000. Rawls was awarded the NationalHumanities Medal by the National Endowment forthe Arts in 1999.

In a preface to Collected Papers, Freemanobserves that Rawls’s career as a philosopher hasbeen ‘‘guided by a reasonable faith that a justsociety is realistically possible.’’

Plot Summary

Justice as FairnessIn A Theory of Justice, Rawls begins with the

statement that, ‘‘Justice is the first virtue of socialinstitution,’’ meaning that a good society is onestructured according to principals of justice. Rawlsasserts that existing theories of justice, developed inthe field of philosophy, are not adequate: ‘‘Myguiding aim is to work out a theory of justice that is aviable alternative to these doctrines which havelong dominated our philosophical tradition.’’ Hecalls his theory—aimed at formulating a conceptionof the basic structure of society in accordance withsocial justice—justice as fairness.

Rawls sets forth to determine the essentialprinciples of justice on which a good society may bebased. He explains the importance of principles ofjustice for two key purposes: first, to ‘‘provide away of assigning rights and duties in the basicinstitutions of society’’; and secondly, to ‘‘definethe appropriate distribution of the benefits and bur-dens’’ of society. He observes that, by his defini-tion, well-ordered societies are rare due to the factthat ‘‘what is just and unjust is usually in dispute.’’He further notes that a well-ordered and perfectlyjust society must be formulated in a way thataddresses the problems of ‘‘efficiency, coordina-tion, and stability.’’

Critique of UtilitarianismThroughout the twentieth century, the domi-

nant philosophical theory of justice in Westernphilosophy was utilitarianism. Utilitarianism wasfirst developed in the nineteenth century by ‘‘thegreat utilitarians,’’ whom Rawls lists as David Hume,Adam Smith, Jeremy Bentham, and John StuartMill. Utilitarianism essentially posits that a justsociety is one based on achieving the greatest good,or happiness, for the greatest number of people.However, many theorists have found this principleultimately unsatisfactory because it implies that thehappiness of a minority of people may be justlysacrificed to secure the happiness of the majority.Rawls defines the strict classical doctrine of utili-tarianism in terms that capture the fundamentalbasis of the theory as one that seeks to evaluatesocietal good in quantitative, mathematical terms:

The main idea is that society is rightly ordered, andtherefore just, when its major institutions are arrangedso as to achieve the greatest net balance of satisfactionsummed over all the individuals belonging to it.

Page 11: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

V o l u m e 3 2 9 7

Rawls’s central critique of utilitarian theory isthat it makes no distinction between the happinessof any one individual and the total sum happiness ofsociety as a whole. He concludes: ‘‘Utilitarianismdoes not take seriously the distinction betweenpersons.’’

Critique of IntuitionismThe other predominant school of ethical theory

in the twentieth century, intuitionism, is, accordingto Rawls, equally unsatisfactory. Intuitionism, firstdeveloped in the eighteenth century, posits thathumans possess an innate, intuitive, sense of justiceand morality. Rawls admits, however, that one cannever completely get away from a certain degree ofintuitionism in developing his own theory of justiceas fairness. However, he suggests several tentativemeans of at least reducing the degree of intuition in-volved in the process. Primarily, he addresses whathe calls the priority problem, whereby intuitionismfails to establish a means of evaluating the relativeimportance of any one ethical principle over anyother. Rawls suggests as a remedy to the priorityproblem that specific principles of justice be rankedin order of importance, so that the first would takeprecedence over the second, and so on.

The Social ContractIn formulating his theory of justice as fairness,

Rawls draws from an earlier, long-neglected, theoryof the social contract, as developed in the seven-teenth and eighteenth centuries by Thomas Hobbes,John Locke, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, and ImmanuelKant. Social contract theory assumes that govern-mental leadership functions on the implicit assump-tion of an agreement, or social contract, between theruler and the ruled, according to which the individ-ual willingly sacrifices some personal liberties tosecure the greater good of society. Rawls assertsthat social contract theory ‘‘seems to offer an alter-native systematic account of justice that is superior,or so I argue, to the dominant utilitarianism of thetradition.’’

The Original PositionTo devise a system upon which a just society

could be based, Rawls proposes a hypothetical manwhose choices are made from the standpoint of aveil of ignorance. Rawls imagines a man who mustdesign a society in which he does not know ahead oftime what social or economic status he himself willhold. From the perspective of this veil of ignoranceas to his own fate, Rawls argues, one can only seek

to create a society whereby the least fortunate areprovided with adequate means of happiness sinceone may find oneself in precisely that position.Rawls refers to this hypothetical perspective as theoriginal position. He notes that the hypotheticalperson in the original position must be assumed tobe a rational thinker.

The Two Principles of JusticeAccording to Rawls, the original position re-

sults in the successful achievement of two centralprinciples of justice. The first principle assures thatthe liberty of the individual may be maximized,given that it does not impinge upon the correspond-ing freedoms of any other individual. The secondprinciple assures that even the most economicallyand materially disadvantaged members of societyare provided for as best as possible. An importantpoint of this second principle is that Rawls admitsroom for social and economic inequality, given thatthose at the lowest end of the spectrum are at leastadequately supported.

Key Figures

Saint Thomas AcquinasThomas Aquinas (1225–1274) was an Italian

theologian of the medieval era who was canonizedin 1323. Aquinas based his theological argumentson the ideas of Aristotle. Rawls refers to Aquinas ina discussion of different theories about toleration ofreligious differences, asserting that Aquinas and theProtestant reformers believed that intolerance ofother religions was ‘‘a matter of faith.’’

AristotleAristotle (384–322 B.C.) was the third of the

three great Greek philosophers (the others beingPlato and Socrates) whose ideas have immeasurablyinfluenced Western thought. Rawls refers to Aris-totle in terms of his definition of justice and hisconcept of perfection. Rawls coins the term ‘‘Aris-totelian principle’’ to describe Aristotle’s philoso-phy regarding the relationship between happiness,activity, and enjoyment.

Jeremy BenthamJeremy Bentham (1748–1832) was an English

philosopher and economist, known as the first andforemost proponent of utilitarianism. His majorworks include An Introduction to the Principles of

Page 12: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

N o n f i c t i o n C l a s s i c s f o r S t u d e n t s2 9 8

Morals and Legislation (1789). Rawls contrastsBentham’s utilitarian theory with his own theory ofjustice as fairness.

F. Y. EdgeworthFrancis Ysidro Edgeworth (1845–1926) was

an Irish economist and statistician, known for hiswork in applying mathematical principles to thefields of economics and statistics. He also triedto apply mathematics to the theory of ethics. His ma-jor works are New and Old Methods of Ethics(1877) and Mathematical Psychics (1881). Refer-ring to Edgeworth as a utilitarian economist, Rawlsdiscusses his ideas in contrast to those of jus-tice as fairness. Rawls also criticizes Edgeworth’sargument for the utility principle on the basis thathis basic assumptions are ‘‘unrealistic’’ and‘‘implausible.’’

Sigmund FreudSigmund Freud (1856–1939) is indisputably

recognized as the father of psychoanalytic theory.He was an Austrian Jewish physician, whose theo-ries of psychoanalysis form the basis of psychoana-lytic theory. His major works include: Interpreta-tion of Dreams (1900), Five Lectures on Psycho-Analysis (1910), and The Ego and the Id (1923).Rawls mentions Freud in a discussion of the psy-chology of morals. He argues against Freud’s the-ory of the origin of the sense of justice as rooted infeelings of envy and jealousy.

Thomas HobbesThomas Hobbes (1588–1679) was an English

philosopher who was an early figure in developing autilitarian philosophy of morals. Hobbes’s majorwork is Leviathon (1651). His theories regarding thesocial contract are taken up by Rawls in his owntheory of justice as fairness.

David HumeDavid Hume (1711–1776) was a Scottish phi-

losopher and economist. He attempted to applyscientific method to an inquiry into human nature,particularly in terms of the concept of knowledge.Rawls mentions that Hume referred to justice as‘‘the cautious, jealous virtue.’’ He makes referenceto Hume’s works, A Treatise of Human Nature(1739) and An Inquiry Concerning the Principles ofMorals (1751). Rawls discusses his own ideas re-garding the circumstances of justice as based inthose of Hume. He further mentions Hume in adiscussion of the concept of a rational and impartial

sympathetic spectator capable of determining theconditions of a just society.

Immanuel KantImmanuel Kant (1724–1804) was a German

philosopher of the Enlightenment era whose ideasforever transformed philosophical thinking, par-ticularly in the areas of ethics, knowledge, andaesthetics. His work was influential in the latertheories of the idealists. Rawls refers frequently tosuch works by Kant as The Foundations of theMetaphysics of Morals and The Critique of Practi-cal Reason. He discusses Kant among the theoristswho developed the social contract theory. He fur-ther mentions Kant in discussion of theories of the‘‘good’’ and the concepts of envy and duty. In adiscussion of moral learning, Rawls refers to Kantamong several philosophers who believed that mo-rality is a natural, innate quality of humanity. In asection entitled ‘‘The Kantian Interpretation of Jus-tice as Fairness,’’ Rawls provides an analysis of thephilosophy of Kant in relation to his own theory ofjustice as fairness.

John LockeJohn Locke (1632–1704) was an English phi-

losopher of the Enlightenment era. His major workwas An Essay Concerning Human Understanding.Rawls also refers to his Second Treatise on Govern-ment. Rawls states his intention to further developand refine the theory of the social contract, as earlierdiscussed by Locke, among others. In a discussionof the basis of morality, Rawls points out thatLocke’s fundamental principal of morals assumesthat God is the legitimate moral authority. He latermentions Locke’s advocacy of a limited tolerationof religious differences to maintain public order.

Karl MarxKarl Marx (1818–1883) was a German Jewish

economist, historian, and sociologist, whose ex-traordinarily influential analysis of political andeconomic history is known as Marxist theory. Hismajor works include The Communist Manifesto,written with Friedrich Engels (1848), and Capital(three volumes, 1867, 1885, 1894). Rawls brieflymentions various interpretations of Marxist theory,particularly in terms of the relationship between theindividual and society.

John Stuart MillJohn Stuart Mill (1806–1873) was an English

economic theorist and philosopher known as an

Page 13: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

V o l u m e 3 2 9 9

influential exponent of utilitarianism. Mill was anearly advocate of women’s suffrage and was one ofthe founders of the first women’s suffrage society,later known as the National Union of Women’sSuffrage Societies, in 1867. Rawls refers to Mill’sbook On Liberty in discussing his ideas about jus-tice, liberty, values, voting rights, and morality. Hefocuses on Mill’s arguments in favor of free institu-tions, meaning societies designed to allow for per-sonal liberty among individuals. Rawls, however,points out that Mill believed men with greatereducation and more wisdom should be grantedgreater power within a democratic society, thusarguing for unequal freedoms among men.

Friedrich NietzscheFriedrich Nietzsche (1844–1900) was a highly

influential German classical philosopher. His majorworks include Thus Spoke Zarathustra (1883–1885),Beyond Good and Evil (1886), and On the Geneal-ogy of Morals (1887). In a discussion of the natureof goodness, Rawls mentions that Nietzsche, alongwith Aristotle, was a theorist of perfectionism, inthe sense that he felt the goal of society is therealization of human excellence in art, science, andculture. Rawls observes that Nietzche indicates‘‘that mankind must continually strive to producegreat individuals.’’

Jean-Jacques RousseauJean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–1778) was a

highly influential French philosopher and writerwhose ideas were a major source of inspiration forthe French Revolution of 1789. His major worksinclude The Social Contract (1762). Rawls assertsthat his aim is to develop and refine the theory of thesocial contract, as originally conceptualized by Rous-seau and other theorists. In a discussion of the issueof religious toleration, Rawls observes that Rous-seau, like Locke, advocated limited toleration ofdiverse religious beliefs. In a discussion of morallearning, Rawls notes that Rousseau believed moralfeelings are a natural, innate quality of the ma-ture adult.

Arthur SchopenhauerArthur Schopenhauer (1788–1860) was a Ger-

man philosopher known as an advocate of pessi-mism. Rawls refers to his On the Basis of Ethics(1840) in a brief mention of Schopenhauer’s cri-tique of Kantian philosophy.

Henry SidgwickHenry Sidgwick (1838–1900) was an English

philosopher and writer. His highly influential Meth-ods of Ethics (1874) put forth a theory of ethicsbased on utilitarianism. Sidgwick attempted to de-fine a rational method on which to base ethicaldecisions. He concluded that there are three possi-ble methods for ethical decision-making: egoism,utilitarianism, and intuitionism. He formulated atheory of universal hedonism, by which the pleas-ures of the individual and the good of society couldbe reconciled. Rawls refers to Sidgwick’s Methodsof Ethics throughout A Theory of Justice, citingSidgwick as one of the great classical utilitarianphilosophers. Rawls discusses Sidgwick’s ideas incontrast to his own theory of justice as fairness. Hedescribes Sidgwick’s ideas about institutions offormal justice, noting that Sidgwick maintained that‘‘law and institutions may be equally executed andyet be unjust.’’ Rawls further discusses Sidgwick’scritical stance toward the theories of Kant, and hisadvocacy of the theory of universal hedonism.

Adam SmithAdam Smith (1723–1790) was a Scottish po-

litical economist and social philosopher of theEnlightenment. His major work, An Inquiry into theNature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (1776),put forth the first systematized theory of politicaleconomy. During his lifetime, Smith was interna-tionally recognized for his influence on both socialscience and economic theory. Rawls refers to Smithin terms of his theory of the invisible hand of marketinfluences, as put forth in Wealth of Nations.

Themes

Individual LibertiesIn formulating his theory of justice as fairness,

Rawls makes clear that the guaranteed freedom ofeach and every individual is essential to the estab-lishment of a just society. He thus determines thatliberty is the first priority in a hierarchy of principlesdefining justice; he places limitations on individualliberty only insofar as it impinges on the liberty ofothers. The first principle is stated as: ‘‘each personis to have an equal right to the most extensivescheme of equal basic liberties compatible with asimilar scheme of liberties for others.’’ In definingwhat he means by liberty, Rawls points out thatthere are different types of liberty and that some are

Page 14: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

N o n f i c t i o n C l a s s i c s f o r S t u d e n t s3 0 0

Topics forFurther

Study• To what extent do you agree or disagree with

Rawls’s theory of justice as fairness? Can yousuggest an alternative theory?

• Read one of Rawls’s articles from the CollectedPapers (1999). What is his argument? How doesit fit in with his theory of justice as fairness? Towhat extent do you agree or disagree with Rawls’sargument in this article?

• Rawls makes reference to a number of influentialphilosophers (as listed in the Key Figures sectionof this entry). Pick one of these philosophers andlearn more about his life. What were this per-son’s contributions to philosophical thought?

• A Theory of Justice was first published in 1971during an era of great turmoil in American his-tory. Learn more about one of the major eventsor series of events that took place in the UnitedStates between the mid-1960s and mid-1970s. Inwhat ways did this event raise issues relevant toRawls’s conception of a just society?

• Evaluate your own society in accordance withthe principles of justice as fairness put forth byRawls. To what extent is it a just society in itsbasic political and legal structure? In what waysdo you consider it an unjust society? What meas-ures could be taken to make it more just?

more crucial to a just society than others. The mostimportant liberties he describes as first, ‘‘freedomof thought and liberty of conscience,’’ and second,‘‘freedom of person and the civil liberties.’’ Rawlsfurther establishes three items that must be ac-counted for in any definition of liberty: a specifica-tion of which individuals are free, a specification ofwhat restrictions they are free from, and a specifica-tion of ‘‘what it is they are free to do or not do.’’Rawls provides a list of the essential liberties, whichincludes: political liberty, freedom of thought, free-dom from assault upon the mental or physical wellbeing of the individual, the right to ownership ofproperty, and freedom from arbitrary arrest andseizure. He states that, in accordance with the firstprinciple of justice, all of the above listed libertiesare to be guaranteed equally to all individuals.

The Individual versus SocietyA central concern in defining a just society is

always in regard to the potential for conflict be-tween the interests of the individual and the interestsof society as a whole. Rawls points out that theindividual must be granted the maximum liberty,but only insofar as it does not have a negative effecton the liberties of others. He asserts that a centralflaw in the theory of utilitarianism is that it assumes

the benefit to a majority can justify restrictions onthe liberties of any individual or group of individu-als. Rawls, on the other hand, avers that there is nojustification for limiting the basic liberties of anyone individual (granted it does not interfere withthose of anyone else). He takes, as an example, theissue of religious tolerance, concluding that a relig-ion that cannot tolerate the co-existence of otherreligions must be limited, only to protect the fullestexpression of all religions.

Social Equality and InequalityImplicit in Rawls’s idea of a just society is that

it is one structured so as to maximize social equal-ity. Rawls makes clear that a certain degree ofinequality is tolerable, even in a just society. Hefocuses particularly on inequalities in the distribu-tion of wealth and in the level of political powerheld by different individuals. He argues that theseinequalities are acceptable, given that those on thevery lowest rungs of society are guaranteed at least aminimum of financial means, political influence(such as voting), and basic rights. His argumentagainst utilitarianism is in part that it allows for theutter devastation of some members of society, aslong as the prosperity and happiness of others ismaximized. Rawls, as well as other philosophers

Page 15: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

V o l u m e 3 3 0 1

before him, have pointed out that there is a degree ofinhumanity in this aspect of utilitarian theory, whichdisregards any concern with social equality. Rawls,on the other hand, proposes a system that allows forlimited social inequality.

DemocracyRawls suggests that the principles upon which

a just society is structured are particularly compat-ible with the form of government known as aconstitutional democracy. He prioritizes what hecalls the principle of (equal) participation, which‘‘requires that all citizens are to have an equal rightto take part in, and to determine the outcome of’’ thepolitical and legal process. He elaborates that thisincludes the stipulation of one citizen, one vote, andthe assurance that elections are fair and free, andregularly held. He adds that the principle of equalparticipation includes the right of all citizens to runfor public office. In addition, ‘‘all citizens shouldhave the means to be informed about politicalissues.’’ Rawls assumes that a democratic societymust be structured in accordance with the basicrights of freedom of speech and assembly, andliberty of thought and conscience. In a preface to the1999 revised edition of A Theory of Justice, Rawlsexpresses his intentions in formulating the theory ofjustice as fairness, in regard to constitutionaldemocracy:

The central ideas and aims of this conception I see asthose of a philosophical conception for a constitu-tional democracy. My hope is that justice as fairnesswill seem reasonable and useful, even if not fullyconvincing, to a wide range of thoughtful politicalopinions and thereby express an essential part of thecommon core of the democratic tradition.

Style

RevisionThe results of an ongoing revision process are

an important element of Rawls’s writing style.Critics frequently comment on A Theory of Justiceas the representation of an ongoing process ofphilosophical theorizing on the part of Rawls, whichhas taken place over the course of some forty years.A Theory of Justice, first published in 1971, isactually made up primarily of revised articles Rawlshad previously published in academic journals, somegoing back as early as 1958. Thus, it has beenobserved that the development and refinement ofhis ideas between 1958–1971 can be traced within

the text of a single book. Furthermore, Rawls sig-nificantly revised A Theory of Justice in 1975, toprepare it for translation into other languages; how-ever, these revisions were not incorporated into theEnglish-language version of the text until 1999.Rawls points out that, until the 1999 edition, ‘‘thetranslated editions . . . have been superior to theoriginal.’’ Rawls continued, over the course ofsome twenty-eight years after the publication of ATheory of Justice, to respond to the questions andcomplaints of many of his critics; thus, the 1999revised edition incorporates the culmination of thesedevelopments into the original 1971 book, in addi-tion to the revisions made for the 1975 translation.

Voice: First PersonRawls puts forth his argument in the narrative

voice of both the first person singular—meaningthat he uses the pronoun ‘‘I’’ to indicate the sourceof his ideas—and the first person plural—meaningthat he also uses the pronoun ‘‘we’’ to express hisideas. This choice may be contrasted with an ap-proach that assumes an objective, or third-personvoice by which to put forth a philosophical argu-ment. Rawls appropriately chooses the first personsingular narrative voice, which allows him to articu-late his ideas in the style of an individual workingout a complex, admittedly imperfect, sometimesprovisional, philosophy—rather than the definitive,objective conclusions of a third person omniscient(all-knowing) narrator. Although Rawls argues inphilosophical abstractions, his use of the first person‘‘I’’ is a means of presenting his ideas as the resultof an ongoing thought process.

Rawls also uses the first person plural, thepronoun ‘‘we’’ in such phrases as: ‘‘We should dowhat we can to formulate explicit principles.’’ Inusing the first person plural, Rawls draws the readerinto his thought processes, inviting the reader toactively participate in thinking through the prob-lems with which Rawls himself is grappling. Hisuse of both singular and plural first person narrativevoice represents Rawls’s works as an ongoing proc-ess of developing and refining his theories in dia-logue with both himself and his readers.

ToneRawls admits to the reader a certain degree of

self-doubt as to whether or not he has succeeded indeveloping his theory; this is not a weakness inRawls’s writing style but an honest and realisticadmission that he, like the reader, is merely one manattempting to make sense of the world—he does not

Page 16: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

N o n f i c t i o n C l a s s i c s f o r S t u d e n t s3 0 2

pretend to be putting forth the answer to the timelessquestions that he is addressing. Thus, he allowshimself the opportunity to express doubts about hisown ideas, or to admit that some of his ideas havenot yet been fully developed. He indicates this in atone of tentativeness, or self-doubt, throughout thebook, using such phrases as: ‘‘I shall try to show’’;‘‘I wish to develop’’; and ‘‘It seems desirable at thispoint . . . to discuss.’’

AbstractRawls opens each of the three main parts of A

Theory of Justice with an abstract—a condenseddescription, or summary, of the ideas put forth inthat section of the book. Abstracts are frequentlyincluded in the opening of academic articles andallow the reader to quickly assess the central argu-ment that follows.

Historical Context

A Theory of Justice was first published in 1971, inthe midst of a period of social and political contro-versy and upheaval in American society. From themid-1960s through the mid-1970s, major issues ofongoing national concern included: the civil rightsmovement, the Vietnam War, the nationally de-clared War on Poverty, the women’s liberationmovement, and the gay rights movement. Through-out this period, many Americans were concernedwith issues of social justice, asking themselvesquestions similar to the ones that Rawls addresses inA Theory of Justice: What is a just society? Thevariety of controversies that reigned throughout the1960s and 1970s revolved around this fundamentalquestion, raising such basic issues to a democraticsociety as social equality and individual liberties.

The Civil Rights MovementThe civil rights movement, which began in the

1950s, was a widespread effort throughout the UnitedStates to fight for greater equality for African-American citizens. The civil rights movement canbe dated from 1955, when Martin Luther King, Jr.,organized a bus boycott in Montgomery, Alabama,to protest segregation—African Americans had beenrequired to sit in the back of buses and to give uptheir seats to white people. A series of federalactions and legislation designed to expand andprotect the rights of African Americans followedthroughout the 1950s and 1960s. In 1957, federaltroops were sent to Little Rock, Arkansas, to protect

the rights of African Americans to attend integratedpublic schools. In 1960, Congress passed the CivilRights Act, which was designed to protect thevoting rights of African Americans. The Civil RightsAct of 1964 further ensured far-reaching protectionof civil rights to African Americans. The subse-quent Voting Rights Act of 1965 even more stronglyenforced the ability of African Americans to exer-cise their right to vote. Nonetheless, ongoing racialinequality provoked violent race riots in major citiesthroughout the country in the years 1965–1968. Thecivil rights movement received a tragic blow whenMartin Luther King, Jr., was assassinated in thespring of 1968. However, the efforts of the civilrights movement continued, in addition to moreradical movements for racial equality, such as theBlack Panthers, founded by Huey Newton and BobbySeale, and the black nationalism of Malcolm X.Inspired by the efforts of African Americans, otherethnic minority groups, such as Latinos and NativeAmericans, launched organizations to fight for greaterequality as American citizens.

The Vietnam WarThe Vietnam War took place between a com-

munist North Vietnam and South Vietnam, whichwas backed by the United States. United Statesinvolvement in Vietnam was sanctioned by thepassing of the Gulf of Tonkin resolution in 1964. Aturning point in American public opinion of theVietnam War came in 1968 when, as a result of theTet Offensive, many Americans first perceived thatthe extent of the communist forces would not makefor an easy victory. Massive anti-war demonstra-tions and large-scale draft evasion grew throughoutthe late 1960s and early 1970s. In 1970, during anon-violent student protest on the campus of KentState University, in Ohio, four students were shotdead by the Ohio National Guard. In 1973, a cease-fire agreement was signed, whereby the UnitedStates withdrew forces from Vietnam, sufferingmilitary defeat after a decade of fighting and the lossof some 58,000 American lives.

The War on PovertyDuring the 1960s, President Lyndon B. John-

son initiated extensive legislation designed to enacthis declared War on Poverty, as part of his programfor a great society. Many benefits were extended tothe socio-economically disadvantaged, to ease theburden of economic inequality in the United States.The Housing and Urban Development Act of 1965was passed to support programs for federal housing.

Page 17: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

V o l u m e 3 3 0 3

Compare&

Contrast• 1789: Introduction to the Principles of Morals

and Legislation, by Jeremy Bentham, delineatesthe principle of utility, which posits that moralityis determined by whatever results in the greatestgood for society as a whole, regardless of thefortunes of any individual or group of individu-als. This theory goes against intuitionism, aschool of thought that implies that humans havean intuitive sense of right and wrong.

1971: A Theory of Justice, by John Rawls, trans-forms the fields of ethical and political philosphy,posing the first convincing challenge to the domi-nance of utilitarian thought.

Today: Ongoing critical response to Rawls, bothsupportive and dismissive, is a continuing meas-ure of his influence on the field of ethics.

• Mid-1800s: Legal, educational, and general so-cial reform occurs in England as a result ofcorruption and dissatisfaction. A new legal sys-tem, largely based on utilitarianism, supplants asystem more or less based on natural law.

1960s and 1970s: In the midst of much socialand political upheaval, including the civil rightsmovement, women’s liberation movement, gayrights movement, and a nationally declared ‘‘Waron Poverty,’’ many Americans concern them-selves with social justice and its existence withina democratic society.

Today: Discrimination persists in many forms,despite being largely illegal. Welfare reformsattempt to reduce poverty.

• Mid-1800s: The Civil War leads to the completeabolishment of legal slavery in the United States.

1960s and 1970s: Legislation is passed to endsegregation in the United States. Affirmativeaction is conceived and is slowly instituted.

Today: Segregation is illegal. Affirmative ac-tion is widely instituted and is the subject ofmany political and legal disputes. The Americanattempt at civil equality is emulated by othercountries, such as South Africa.

The Medicare Bill guaranteed health care coveragefor senior citizens. In 1966, the minimum wage wasraised, and in 1967, social security pensions wereraised. Many other reforms were enacted during thisperiod, focusing on such concerns as educationalaid, urban renewal, and mass transportation.

Women’s LiberationThe women’s liberation movement, inspired by

the civil rights movement, was an extensive effort togain greater equality for women in all areas ofsociety and culture, including work, the family, andpolitics. The women’s liberation movement hasbeen referred to using a variety of terms, includingwomen’s lib, the feminist movement, or simplyfeminism. The women’s liberation movement of the1960s and 1970s is also referred to as second wavefeminism, distinguishing it from the first wavefeminism of the nineteenth and early-twentieth cen-

tury women’s suffrage movement. The feministmovement has been referred to as a ‘‘bloodlessrevolution’’ because of the extensive and far-reach-ing societal changes it accomplished without the useof violence. Early second wave feminists organizedconsciousness-raising groups, small, loosely organ-ized groups of women, often meeting in privatehomes to discuss an entire range of concerns affect-ing women’s lives. They were influenced by suchearly publications as The Second Sex (1949), byFrench writer Simone de Beauvoir, and The Femi-nine Mystique (1963), by Betty Friedan. The NationalOrganization for Women (NOW) was founded in1966, focusing on reform for women’s rights at thepublic level. The widely circulated motto of thewomen’s lib movement was ‘‘the personal is politi-cal’’—a statement that captured the extent to whichfeminists perceived that even the most personalexperiences, such as family, sex, and relationships,

Page 18: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

N o n f i c t i o n C l a s s i c s f o r S t u d e n t s3 0 4

had political implications in regard to women’sstatus in society.

Gay PrideThe gay pride movement is generally dated

from the night of June 28, 1969, when gay activistsrioted in protest of the arrest of patrons of a gay barcalled the Stonewall Inn, in Greenwich Village inNew York City. This was the first time in which apublic, semi-organized protest by homosexuals hadcome to national attention, and the organization of awidespread and far-reaching gay pride movementsoon followed. Gay Pride Week is now celebratedannually in June, in commemoration of the water-shed incident now referred to simply as ‘‘Stonewall.’’

Critical Overview

A Theory of Justice has had tremendous, far-reach-ing impact on twentieth-century philosophicalthought. Rawls is widely credited with breathingnew life into the field of political philosophy, which,by the 1950s, had nearly ceased to develop in anysignificant direction. Victoria Davion and ClarkWolf, in The Idea of a Political Liberalism (2000)assert, ‘‘By any account, the appearance of [ATheory of Justice] was a turning point for politicalphilosophy,’’ adding that it ‘‘could not have beenmore cataclysmic in its effect on the field.’’ As RexMartin avers, in Rawls and Rights (1985), A Theoryof Justice ‘‘is widely regarded as an important andseminal treatise on some of the main topics of moraland political philosophy.’’ Rawls’s work also hadan important effect on liberal thought. As A. P. Raoasserts, in Three Lectures on John Rawls (1981),‘‘Rawls not only brought some freshness into theAnglo-American moral philosophy, but also res-cued liberal thinking from sterility, and liberal ide-ology from impotence.’’

The book, however, inspired extensive criti-cism, as well as praise. Brian Barry, in The LiberalTheory of Justice (1973), claims, ‘‘Rawls’s theoryof justice does not work and . . . many of hisindividual arguments are unsound.’’ Yet Barry isquick to add:

It is, quite simply, a work that anyone in the futurewho proposes to deal with any of the topics it touchesmust first come to terms with if he expects thescholarly community to take him seriously.

David Lewis Schaefer, in Justice or Tyranny?(1979), offers harsh criticism on the grounds thatRawls’s work is not that of true political philosophy,but rather of political ideology. Schaefer asserts,‘‘Rawls’s writings . . . embody what I believe to beboth a popular yet seriously deficient political ideol-ogy and a widely shared yet grossly inadequateunderstanding of the nature of political philoso-phy.’’ He goes on to state, ‘‘the widespread acclaimthat A Theory of Justice has received from theacademic community despite the book’s manifolddefects is . . . a disheartening sign of contemporarydecay, not only in political philosophy, but inscholarship.’’

Even Rawls’s most ardent admirers find manyweaknesses in this seminal work. Robert Paul Wolff,in Understanding Rawls (1977), opines that Rawls’scentral idea in A Theory of Justice is ‘‘one of theloveliest ideas in the history of social and politicaltheory’’; yet, he confirms, ‘‘The logical status of theclaims in the book never becomes entirely clear.’’

Whether criticizing or celebrating his theories,none doubt the impact of his ideas on the field ofphilosophy. Rao notes that the sheer volume ofcritical response to A Theory of Justice has beenenormous, remarking that, since the book’s firstappearance, ‘‘Rawls’s studies have become a heavyindustry.’’ As Davion and Wolf point out:

Rawls has, for the most part, inspired philosophers notas disciples or followers but as critics and opponents.But even Rawls’s most articulate critics have adoptedargumentative methods that betray his deep influence.Critical attention of this sort is, we believe, the highestform of scholarly compliment.

They add that, despite the many legitimatecriticisms of his ideas, ‘‘clearly it is to Rawls’scredit that his books and papers continue to inspirecontroversy and productive disagreement and togenerate articulate reasoned response instead ofpassive doctrinal adherence.’’ Further:

Among political theorists, there is clearly no overlap-ping consensus on the success of any particularRawlsian argument, or even on the idea of an overlap-ping consensus itself. There is much more agreementon the overwhelming significance of Rawls’s contri-bution to the field and on his enduring influence:Rawls’s work has redefined the central issues ofpolitical philosophy and raised the standard of rigorand argument for the entire field.

As Rao observes of his widespread and lastinginfluence, ‘‘Rawls has become an integral part ofthe general intellectual culture, and the ideology, ofthe Anglo-American world.’’

Page 19: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

V o l u m e 3 3 0 5

Criticism

Liz BrentBrent has a Ph.D. in American culture, special-

izing in film studies, from the University of Michi-gan. She is a freelance writer and teaches courses inthe history of American cinema. In the followingessay, Brent discusses the principle of equality ofopportunity in Rawls’s theory of justice as fairness.

A central concern for Rawls is the problem of howto regulate equality of opportunity, given that thepotential for any person to succeed in life is in partdetermined by their inborn, innate talents and abili-ties, and in part by the social, material, and psycho-logical conditions under which they are raised aschildren.

Rawls’s second principle of justice of fairnessstates that:

Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged sothat they are both (a) reasonably expected to be toeveryone’s advantage, and (b) attached to positionsand offices open to all.

In other words, a certain degree of social ine-quality is acceptable, provided that it is ultimately tothe benefit of all citizens; for instance, the presidentin a democratic society has more power than theaverage citizen, but the vesting of this power in oneindividual is considered to be beneficial to all citi-zens in facilitating the functioning of democracy.Rawls explains that there are several ways of inter-preting this second principle; he chooses to interpretit in the sense he refers to as democratic equality:that equality means equality of opportunity—thateveryone ought to be given an equal opportunity.

However, Rawls observes that fair opportunitycannot regulate the factor of what he calls thenatural lottery—meaning the natural talents andabilities accorded to any given individual, merelyby accident of birth. He points out that this unequaldistribution of natural talents and abilities amongindividuals is ‘‘arbitrary from a moral point ofview’’; in other words, there is no moral basis forwhy any one individual should be born with greaterintelligence, or greater musical talent (for example),than any other. Rawls makes clear that those withthe good fortune to be born with greater naturaltalents and abilities must recognize that their statusis simply the luck of the draw, and not an indicationof superiority as a human being: ‘‘We do notdeserve our place in the distribution of native en-dowments, any more than we deserve our initial

Rawls draws on Thomas Hobbes’s‘‘social contract’’ theories

starting place in society.’’ He points out that theinequality of innate talents and abilities, which is thecondition of the natural lottery, is not an indicationthat any one person deserves more in life than anyother; these inborn inequalities ‘‘are simply naturalfacts.’’ However, society has the ability to accom-modate such innate inequalities to maximize thedegree of social and material equality enjoyed byeach and every citizen: ‘‘What is just and unjust isthe way that institutions deal with these facts.’’

Rawls suggests that given that there will al-ways be such innate inequalities in the potential ofeach individual, society can at least guarantee toeach citizen ‘‘a formal equality of opportunity inthat all have at least the same legal rights of accessto all advantageous social positions.’’ He adds that,‘‘all should have a fair chance to attain’’ any givendesirable social position; for example, not onlyshould every citizen be allowed the legal opportu-nity to become a doctor, but every citizen should beguaranteed a fair chance to achieve the educationlevel necessary to become a doctor.

Rawls elaborates that the social status intowhich one is born should not hinder the opportunityto realize the individual’s natural potential for suc-cess in whatever field his or her talents lie: he states

Page 20: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

N o n f i c t i o n C l a s s i c s f o r S t u d e n t s3 0 6

WhatDo I Read

Next?• In Rawls: A Theory of Justice and Its Critics

(1990), Chandran Kukathas and Philip Pettitprovide analytical discussion of the central criti-cal responses to Rawls’s work.

• In Culture War and Ethical Theory (1997), Rich-ard F. Von Dohlen discusses Rawls’s theories inrelation to cultural conflicts facing the UnitedStates in the twentieth century.

• In Pluralism and Consensus: Conceptions of theGood in the American Polity (1998), ChristopherBeem discusses philosophies of liberalism and

pluralism, including the theories of Rawls, inrelation to American politics and government.

• John Rawls: Collected Papers (1999), edited bySamuel Freeman, includes almost all of Rawls’spublications (other than his books), arranged inchronological order.

• Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy(2000), edited by Barbara Herman, includesRawls’s lectures on the history of modern ethicsfrom the seventeenth through the twentiethcenturies.

‘‘those who are at the same level of talent andability, and have the same willingness to use them,should have the same prospects of success regard-less of their initial place in the social system.’’ Heexplains, ‘‘those with similar abilities and skillsshould have similar life chances.’’ In other words,society cannot compensate for inequalities in natu-ral talents and abilities—but society should ensurethat those with equal talents and abilities be grantedequal opportunity to realize their innate potential:‘‘The expectations of those with the same abilitiesand aspirations should not be affected by their socialclass.’’

One of the most important factors in providingthis equality of opportunity is ‘‘maintaining equalopportunities of education for all.’’ Rawls assertsthat the education system is central to establishingequality of opportunity for all citizens: ‘‘Chances toacquire cultural knowledge and skills should notdepend upon one’s class position, and so the schoolsystem, whether public or private, should be de-signed to even out class barriers.’’

When Rawls speaks of the value of education,he makes clear that it is not merely a matter oftraining the citizen for economic productivity; moreimportantly, education is a means of enhancing thequality of life of even the most disadvantagedmembers of society. He states, ‘‘The value of edu-

cation should not be assessed solely in terms ofeconomic efficiency and social welfare.’’ Rather,‘‘Equally, if not more important, is the role ofeducation in enabling a person to enjoy the cultureof his society and to take part in its affairs, and inthis way to provide for each individual a securesense of his own worth.’’

Rawls, however, admits that even these meas-ures to guarantee equal opportunity cannot compen-sate for the natural lottery, whereby some are bornwith greater talents and abilities than others. Inaddition, he points out that, ‘‘the principle of fairopportunity can be only imperfectly carried out, atleast as long as some form of family exists.’’ Heexplains:

The extent to which natural capacities develop andreach fruition is affected by all kinds of social condi-tions and class attitudes. Even the willingness to makean effort, to try, and so to be deserving in the ordinarysense is itself dependent upon happy family and socialcircumstances.

Thus, the ideal of fair equality of opportunitydoes not address the concern that ‘‘the internal lifeand culture of the family influence, perhaps as muchas anything else, affect a child’s motivation and hiscapacity to gain from education, and so in turn hislife prospects.’’ Thus, ‘‘Even in a well-orderedsociety that satisfies the two principles of justice,the family may be a barrier to equal chances be-

Page 21: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

V o l u m e 3 3 0 7

tween individuals.’’ Equal opportunity in educationfor those with equal innate natural talents and abili-ties does not compensate for the home life of thechild, which may limit his or her potential.

Rawls defines the concept of the natural aris-tocracy as referring to the greater endowment ofnatural talents and abilities to some than to others; inother words, this idea asserts that some individualsnaturally occupy a greater social status, based ontheir inborn potential. Rawls asserts that the idea ofa natural aristocracy is not necessarily unjust, aslong as the elevated privileges awarded to thosewith greater talent are ultimately used to the benefitof all citizens, including those with lesser naturaltalent and ability. It is the responsibility of thosewith greater innate talents and abilities to use theseadvantages for the benefit of the less privilegedmembers of society. Rawls argues that the naturalaristocracy thus can be to the advantage of societyas a whole, for ‘‘the opportunities of the leastfavored sectors of the community would be stillmore limited if these inequalities were removed.’’Thus, ‘‘those who have been favored by nature,whoever they are, may gain from their good fortuneonly in terms that improve the situation of thosewho have lost out.’’ Further, any rewards thataccrue from this initial vantage point should not beregarded as the natural due of those with the goodfortune to possess superior advantages.

To compensate for the unequal distribution ofnatural talents and abilities, as well as the unequalcircumstances into which different individuals areborn, Rawls offers the principle of redress. Hedefines this as the principle that undeserved ine-qualities call for redress, and adds, ‘‘since inequali-ties of birth and natural endowment are undeserved,these inequalities are to be somehow compensatedfor.’’ Thus, a greater portion of the resources of asociety ought to be directed toward the leastadvantaged, so that ‘‘society must give more atten-tion to those with fewer native assets and to thoseborn into the less favorable social positions.’’ Rawlsagain points to the education system as a centrallocation for enacting the principle of redress: ‘‘Inpursuit of this principle greater resources might bespent on the education of the less rather than themore intelligent, at least over a certain time of life,say the earlier years of school.’’

Rawls thus puts forth a theoretical perspectivefrom which a society may be structured to maximizeequality of opportunity while taking into accountthe inequalities afforded by the natural lottery—

It is the responsibility of

those with greater innate talents

and abilities to use these

advantages for the benefit of the

less privileged members of society.’’

whereby individuals are endowed with an unequaldistribution of natural talents and abilities—as wellas unequal family, social, and economic circum-stances in which to develop these innate talents andabilities.

Source: Liz Brent, Critical Essay on A Theory of Justice, inNonfiction Classics for Students, The Gale Group, 2002.

Rex MartinIn the following essay, Martin surveys Rawls’s

theories of rights.

In this chapter I will first identify the various levelsor stages at which Rawls has found talk of rights tobe significant (i.e., rights in the original position,rights emerging from the original position in theprinciples of justice formulated there, etc.). I thengo on to show how Rawls would regard rights atthese various levels to be justified. The focus of ourdiscussion will be on rights as embedded in thebasic structure of a society. I will try to provide aninterpretation of Rawls’s claim that such rights arenatural rights. Then, last of all, I will consider theimplications of this conception of natural rights forglobal justice.

1. Rawls on Rights and TheirJustification

We could conveniently divide Rawls’s theoryhere into a four-part structure. The first and topmostpart concerns the so-called primary goods. Thesecond part concerns the formulation of the princi-ples of justice and the choice of a particular set ofsuch principles over alternative ones. (Rawls’s pre-ferred set, which he calls the ‘‘two principles ofjustice,’’ would, he thinks, be chosen in the originalposition.) The next part concerns the institutionaliz-ing of the (two) principles of justice in what Rawlscalls the ‘‘basic structure’’ of a society. The lastpart, then, concerns the actual workings of a society

Page 22: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

N o n f i c t i o n C l a s s i c s f o r S t u d e n t s3 0 8

Rawls’s failure to deal with

the analytic issues poses an

obstacle to his program as a

justification of rights.’’

so organized and, in particular, some of the institu-tions and subordinate arrangements that would cropup in such a society—or, at least, in any such societyunder modern conditions. Interestingly, Rawls re-fers to rights at each of these four levels.

The primary goods, as we might recall fromchapter 1, are goods which, presumptively, anyrational person would want, whatever his plan oflife or value orientation might be. These goods,abstractly stated, are divided by Rawls into (a) thesocial primary goods—liberty, opportunity and pow-ers, income and wealth, the bases of self-respect—and (b) the natural ones—health and vigor, intelli-gence and imagination. As I suggested in chapter 1,we can view the deliberations of persons in theoriginal position respecting justice as an attempt todefine and select preferred principles for allocatingor arranging the social primary goods among indi-viduals. It is interesting to note that sometimesRawls includes rights among these primary goods,but sometimes he does not.

In my judgment the listing of rights at this levelis confusing and should be dispensed with. Rawls isobviously rather casual on this point. The mattermay call for more attention than he has given it,however; for there are two quite distinct reasonswhy rights as primary goods would be a problematicnotion in Rawls’s theory of justice.

First, we had established in chapter 1 that theoriginal position, as an arena for the formulation ofthe principles of justice, could have no featureswhich in and of themselves would be strong enoughto generate a principle of justice. For we wanted theeligible principles to follow, not deductively fromany descriptive feature of the original position (orany elements initially included in it), but from thearguments that were deployed there. But rights,unlike the other primary goods, are overtly norma-tive entities; moreover, a conventional principle ofjustice would assert that rights should be respected

or that rights should not be violated. Thus, insofar asrights are among the social primary goods, we couldgenerate a strong—albeit conventional—principleof justice almost immediately out of the primarygoods. And there would be no need, then, for theelaborate mechanisms of the theory of justice toallow for the construction of some such principle inthe original position. This would violate the con-straint that there should be no normative elements ofjustice introduced into the theory prior to the con-struction of the preferred principles of justice.

Moreover, rights appear to be a moral categorywith which utilitarian thinkers have difficulty, asshould be evident from chapter 1. So, if rights wereto be included among the social primary goods, thenthis would strongly prejudice the deliberation infavor of a specific sort of moral theory. We wouldalso simultaneously prejudice the event against autilitarian solution, if it is true that utilitarians have aproblem in accounting for basic rights. So, ongrounds of the desired normative weakness—ornondeductivity—of the original position model andof the moral neutrality of that model with respect tothe competing principles of justice, we should at-tempt to expunge rights from the list of socialprimary goods.

This brings me to the second point. To treatrights as primary goods is to regard them as bothpretheoretical (i.e., as prior to the theory of justice)and as noninstitutional (since they would antedatethe basic structure of a society and, for that matter,all other social institutions). But this seems to begimportant questions about the nature of rights, whichneed to be expressly decided (a point that we shallreturn to in the next section).

Fortunately, Rawls’s inclusion of rights amongthe social primary goods does not appear to repre-sent anything deep-seated. It is relatively offhandand, apparently, relatively easily set aside. Let ustreat rights as effectively purged from the list ofsuch goods, although there is still the interestingquestion (to which we will return later in thissection) of why Rawls would tend to include them.

This takes us to the second stage of our analysisin this section. Rawls argues that in the originalposition, under conditions of extreme uncertainty inwhich there are no objective bases for judgingprobabilities, the two principles would be formu-lated and selected as the preferred principles.

The important thing, for our purposes, is thatthe first principle is usually stated by Rawls as itself

Page 23: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

V o l u m e 3 3 0 9

identifying a right. For example, in his standardstatement of the two principles, the first is said torequire that ‘‘each person is to have an equal right tothe most extensive total system of equal basicliberties compatible with a similar system of libertyfor all.’’ I would suggest, then, that on this readingthe Rawlsian first principle states a basic moralright. And whatever justification attaches to the twoprinciples, as justification through a choice proce-dure that is both fair and rational, attaches ipso factoto this basic moral right.

The second principle, however, is not formu-lated by Rawls as a right. Rather, it is characteristi-cally rendered in somewhat different terms: ‘‘Socialand economic inequalities are to be arranged so thatthey are both: (a) to the greatest benefit of the leastadvantaged . . . and (b) attached to offices andpositions open to all under conditions of fair equal-ity of opportunity.’’

The two principles, as they emerge from theoriginal position, are exceedingly abstract. Just asthe primary goods belong to what Rawls calls a‘‘thin’’ theory of the good, so the two principlesconstitute a ‘‘thin’’ theory of justice. They requireto be embodied. Justice is, or should be, a virtue ofsociety, specifically of its basic structure. The ob-ject of the two principles is the design or thenormative analysis of the basic structure of a soci-ety. Included in that structure is a society’s politicalsystem and its economic system. Each of these, inturn, would be made up of a set of structuralelements or institutions (as we saw in chapter 1),with some being described as main institutions (e.g.,the political constitution or the supply/demand mar-ket) and others as background institutions (e.g.,antitrust regulation as a control on the market).

The idea is that a just society would conform tothe two principles by building them into its basicstructure: institutions are set up which, when oper-ating together, give results that tend to satisfy thetwo principles over time. These institutions, then,represent a set of middle principles standing be-tween the two principles and the actual operation ofa society. The background institutions check tend-encies in the main institution which might over timetake it away from its original seated disposition;they not only keep the main institution on track—and it, them—but also they remedy its deficiencies,as regards justice. The result is that the ‘‘ongoinginstitutional processes are . . . constrained and theaccumulated results of individual transactions con-tinually adjusted.’’

Rawls references John Stuart Mill’sfamous work, On Liberty

Rawls repeatedly talks of the two principles, inparticular the first one (Equal Basic Liberties), asassigning rights and duties. But this is inexact. Thetwo principles assign rights and duties by means ofthe basic structure. Rawls thinks, for example, thatthe inclusion of a bill of rights within the constitu-tion is one important way in which the first principleof justice could be institutionalized in a given soci-ety. So, the constitution (or some other feature of thebasic structure) assigns determinate rights to indi-vidual persons; what the first principle does is to‘‘govern’’—or better, to justify—the business ofassigning equal basic rights to individuals. Basicstructure rights, in particular those attaching to themain institution(s), are conceived by Rawls as analo-gous in a variety of ways to natural rights.

The last level in Rawls’s theory of rights con-cerns the legitimate expectations of individual per-sons. We can assume that these expectations wouldinclude those established at the higher levels, assecured by justice. Thus, constitutionally protectedpolitical and personal rights as laid down in thebasic structure of a society would be legitimateexpectations of individuals in that society. And aswell, other legitimate expectations would grow upin and around the operation of the various institu-

Page 24: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

N o n f i c t i o n C l a s s i c s f o r S t u d e n t s3 1 0

tions in the basic structure (e.g., the highly detailedlist of rights that have grown up around the institu-tions of trial by jury or of private ownership ofproperty or of equality of opportunity).

But the basic structure is also a framework forthe transactions of individuals and associations.Now, individuals do not merely interact (and asso-ciations—such as labor unions or corporations oruniversities—do not merely interact) with the em-bodied principles and subsequent workings of thebasic structure. Individuals also interact with oneanother and with associations. (The same is true forassociations: they interact with one another andwith individuals.) Accordingly, rules and practicesthat are characteristic of these sorts of transactionscould be formulated as well. Thus, we could followa line of devolvement away from the institutions ofthe basic structure. And here we would encounter avast variety of subsidiary institutions and practices,of private associations and cooperative ventures.Nonetheless, expectations would attach to the op-eration of these subsidiary elements and, insofar asthe institutions and practices in question were com-patible with justice or loosely derivative from it, theexpectations would be legitimate ones, as secured orenframed by justice. Thus we can speak of subsidi-ary rights, as distinct from basic structure rights, ofmany sorts: rights under this contract or that, ofparticular organizational structures, of individualfamily life (e.g., the Martin family), and so on. Ingeneral, Rawls encompasses these rights under theheading of fairness or fair play. They are all institu-tional rights that are justified primarily by theirrelationship to elements in the basic structure, ratherthan directly by the two principles of justice them-selves. In the absence of reasonably just institutions,we would, of course, have to turn to the two princi-ples; but these could cover only the clear cases (i.e.,practices that were grossly unjust, such as slavery,or obviously fair, such as a nonexploitative andvoluntary cooperative arrangement or agreement).Since my concern in this study is with basic moraland constitutional rights and their justification, Iwill have little to say about these subsidiary institu-tional (or practice) rights.

I have schematically represented Rawls’smethod of justification as proceeding from the topdown. Thus, the top level (deliberation in the origi-nal position about the rational and fair distributionof social primary goods) is used to justify the basicmoral right that is stated in the first principle ofjustice; and the first principle of justice is used inturn to justify the constitutional rights that are built

into the basic structure of a just society; and these, inturn, play a role of sorts in the justification of allsubsidiary rights. But Rawls adds an importantcontrol on this procedure by requiring that thejustifying principle or theme be matched with cer-tain considered judgments (either in the form ofmaxims or of paradigm cases) which exhibit or helpto exhibit the moral character of that which is to bejustified (the ‘‘subject’’ of justification). For exam-ple, determination of the constitutional right ofpersons to be free from the injuries of ‘‘cruel andunusual punishment’’ would involve not merely thefirst principle of justice and its grounds (the primarygoods of liberty and opportunity and of self-respect—i.e., the bases of self-respect) but also consideredjudgments about punishment and practices that havebeen associated with it historically (including suchmatters as mutilation as a form of corporal punish-ment, public execution and other forms of capitalpunishment, harsh treatment of those who have notbeen judged guilty or of those who have beenjudged insane, the aims of punishment, relevantmaxims as to what is legally just, etc.). Rawls callsthis matching procedure the method of reflectiveequilibrium.

In the application of this method a certainamount of to-ing and fro-ing normally results, withadjustments being made in the initial formulation ofthe justifying principle (or in its range of extension)as well as in our considered judgments. The goal ofthe method is to bring the two levels—that ofjustifying principle and that of the practice to bejustified (and the material relevant to it)—intoalignment.

We can put this point more precisely now bydistinguishing between a narrow reflective equilib-rium and a wide one. Briefly, a narrow reflectiveequilibrium means that the justifying principle ofjustice (e.g., the first principle) is matched, more orless on its own, with the considered judgments. Awide reflective equilibrium, by contrast, involvesmatching these judgments not merely with the prin-ciple itself but also with the various elements thatwent into its construction. From chapter 1 we arefamiliar with these elements as the ones that areorganized around the original position ‘‘model’’ inthe Rawlsian account of the deliberations about theprinciples of justice for the basic structure of asociety. It is this peculiar sort of coherence betweenprinciples and their theoretical backdrop, on the onehand, and considered judgments, on the other, thatsatisfies the standard of justification in matters ofjustice and, hence, of rights.

Page 25: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

V o l u m e 3 3 1 1

Rawls’s account of the justification of rights issubject to most of the criticisms that can be made,more generally, of his theory of justice. Somecriticisms, however, can be made specifically of thistheory of rights.

Rawls’s conception of rights is opaque. Hedoes not attempt an analysis of the concept, andthough he uses the term ‘rights’ freely, he does sowithout explication. The context is usually unhelpful.Rawls’s failure to deal with the analytic issues posesan obstacle to his program as a justification of rights.

Oddly enough, the best place to look for guid-ance is in Rawls’s discussion of what I earlier calledsubsidiary rights and practices. Thus, although thismaterial may be relatively unimportant to our mainproject (that of developing a Rawlsian theory ofbasic moral and constitutional rights), it may, none-theless, have important implications for what Rawlsconceived rights to be. Then, if we can assume thathe consistently has meant by ‘rights’ the same thingthroughout, we can extrapolate this discussion tomore interesting contexts and thereby have thebeginnings of the Rawlsian theory we seek.

I would suggest, then, that a right for Rawls isan individual’s legitimate expectation as to what hewould receive in a just institutional distribution ofsocial primary goods. The justification of a right,then, would involve establishing the legitimacy ofthe expectation within the framework of higher-to-lower-level justification under conditions of reflec-tive equilibrium that have already been described,albeit briefly, in this section.

On this reading, liberties as social primarygoods could be called rights—not in the originalposition but, rather, under institutional arrange-ments imposed by justice. One of Rawls’s standardpairings of primary goods—the pairing of rights andliberties—would conform to this usage, though thepairing is confusing since it mixes those things thatare primary goods in the original position (liberties)with things that could be included there onlyprospectively (rights). The pairing, then, is anticipa-tory (and should not be taken literally). It is alsorevealing—suggesting, as it does, a close tie (almosta conceptual one) between rights and liberties inRawls’s thinking, as if only liberties could be rights.

At the same time the reading gives us a reasonwhy Rawls was not inclined to treat the secondprinciple of justice as itself a basic moral right or toregard the pattern of just distributions of wealth andsocial position as a pattern of rights. The reason is

this: though specific liberties can be secured to adeterminate degree to any given individual (sinceall share in the basic liberties equally), specificeconomic or social standings cannot. In economicmatters, individuals float between an upper and alower limit (both of which are determined by thedifference principle, the principle that inequalitiesof wealth and social position must be arranged sothat the prospects of the least-advantaged group aremaximized). Thus, no given individual has a legiti-mate expectation of receiving any particular dis-tributive share and, hence, cannot be said to have aright to a particular share. Even the minimum levelestablished by the difference principle does notdefine the legitimate expectation of any given indi-vidual (not even those who form the group of theleast advantaged); rather the expectation is that of a‘‘representative,’’ or ideal-type, individual. Accord-ingly, Rawls characteristically withholds the term‘rights’ in his discussion of the second principle andits applications. And Rawls’s approach here is mark-edly different from his handling of the first principleand its applications.

But what, exactly, does this Rawlsian concep-tion of rights amount to? I would suggest that twomain ideas are determinative here: first, the idea ofsomething distributive or individuatable and, sec-ond, the idea of something the distribution of whichcan be guaranteed.

When it is said that something can be distrib-uted, one means that it can be assigned or parceledout to the individuals in some target group or class.Thus, the towels in a locker room would be, in thissense, distributable to the members of the club,though probably the acoustical properties of theroom would not be. Rawls is interested in universalrights, that is, basic moral and constitutional rights;so, the things that someone can have a right to insuch cases would have to be things that could bedistributed to everyone: that is, the same things toeach and everybody in the relevant class (e.g.,persons, citizens).

Now, the sand on the beach on some out-of-the-way Pacific island would thus be distributable (as-suming that no one owned it), but there is no readilyavailable mechanism to achieve such a distribution;more important, there is no way to guarantee it. Thisis one reason—probably only one among several—why no one would be inclined to say that people hada right to grains of sand from this beach. Somethingis, or becomes, a right only when its distribution (weassume it to be a benefit) can be guaranteed, or at

Page 26: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

N o n f i c t i o n C l a s s i c s f o r S t u d e n t s3 1 2

least reasonably assured within practical limits, tothe individuals who are relevantly said to be therecipients.

Thus, when Rawls speaks of legitimate expec-tations, he can be interpreted to mean not only thatan individual’s claims are valid but also that they arereasonable expectations: the individual’s receivinghis share or his due can be counted on because it isbuilt into the structure of things and, we might add,because it is normatively independent of the usualconsiderations (the public good or the general wel-fare) that might be urged against it. Rights, forRawls, are not free-floating claims, of the sort oftencalled moral. They are, rather, details of an institu-tional arrangement in which the claim and themeans for delivering on it are linked closely together.

But at this point we begin to sense a certainamount of tension in Rawls’s theory. I will try, inconcluding this section, to make this unease explicit.

Some have claimed that Rawls has no place inhis theory for moral rights. But the judgment here ishasty, since the first principle, the principle of equalbasic liberties, seems itself to be a right in Rawls’saccount. And since the first principle is developedin the original position, as a principle for the designof the basic structure of a just society, it is prior toany society; the first principle itself cannot, then, beregarded as an institutional right but rather as aprescription for institutional or political rights. Andas a prescription, it is moral in character; or so itmight be argued. Thus, if the first principle is a rightat all, it must be a moral right.

Let us say provisionally, then, that the firstprinciple states a basic moral right: namely, thateach person ought to have available the most exten-sive system of equal basic liberties compatible witha similar system of liberty for all other persons.Having such liberties in a well-ordered society is thelegitimate expectation of each person. But what arethese liberties?

Now, one could reply that the first principledoes not actually specify the liberties in question; itspeaks merely of ‘‘equal basic liberties.’’ The initialspecification of liberties occurs at the point whenthe basic structure of a society is designed (perhapswith the help of the method of reflective equilib-rium). But this is to suggest that the first principlehas no essential content of liberties, leaving thedetermination of ‘‘equal basic liberties’’ to time andcircumstance. The first principle becomes, then,merely formal; it says, in effect, once the basic

liberties have been determined in the constitution,they are to be equal for all citizens. But if themeaning of ‘‘equal basic liberties’’ cannot be fixedinitially, then the first principle offers inadequateguidance as to precisely what liberties are to beinstitutionalized. The first principle—and with it,the original position—ceases to be the ‘‘Archimedeanpoint’’ (the phrase is Rawls’s) for the critique anddesign of the basic structure of a society.

The issue that I have been examining is, I think,a serious one for Rawls’s theory of equal basicliberties as rights. For if some or even a few basicliberties are by and large specified at a furtherstage—say, at the design of the basic structure—then the first principle to that degree lacks essentialcontent and stability.

Let us put this point somewhat differently. Ifthe liberties on the list lack specificity or, evenworse, fundamental identity, then it is difficult tosay that one could have a right to them. Rights are,for better or worse, fairly determinate things. Therecomes a point, as we relax and let go of detail andthen of substance, when one can no longer be said tohave a legitimate expectation. The thing loses thename of right and becomes something else—anaspiration, perhaps. This line of reply, then, hasobvious defects.

Accordingly, one could reply instead thatRawls’s first principle of justice establishes a par-ticular ‘‘list’’ of basic liberties; it identifies a spe-cific set of liberties which are to be acknowledgedas being held equally by all. (This particular readinghas been suggested by Hart.) It is, I think, the correctinterpretation; this interpretation of the first princi-ple as specifying a list of basic liberties is madeclearer, Rawls says, in revisions that were made forthe German edition of his book and in some of hislater writings.

The relevant liberties are, Rawls tells us, rightsof citizenship and of the person: such things as theright to vote; freedom of speech and assembly;liberty of conscience; the right to own personalproperty; freedom from slavery, arbitrary arrest,and seizure; and so on. They are standard civilliberties (or rights).

So the tension in Rawls’s theory, to which Ireferred earlier, can now be stated. If, on the onehand, the liberties are specified too loosely, thenthere is no clear sense in which a person can be saidto have a legitimate expectation respecting them.Hence, there would be no right to them as defined in

Page 27: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

V o l u m e 3 3 1 3

the original position but, rather, presumably only inthe more determinate institutional setting providedby what Rawls calls the basic structure of a society.On the other hand, were one to say that the basicliberties are rights (as one would be licensed to do,presumably, in the basic structure), then it wouldappear to be otiose to say of these rights that one hasa right to them.

So Rawls’s way of putting his first principleseems to fail under either option. If the basic liber-ties lack specificity (in the original position), thenone cannot be said to have a legitimate expectationregarding them there; the legitimate expectationarises, so to speak, in some subsequent institutionalsetting (where they have, presumably, the requisitespecificity). Hence, there is no right to the basicliberties that is stated by the first principle. Butwhere the liberties have the requisite specificity—as they would have in the basic structure of asociety—then they have become rights themselves(i.e., each basic liberty is itself a right), and it isredundant to speak of an additional or supervenientright to such liberties.

The dilemma appears to be that if we feedenough substance into the basic liberties to have alegitimate expectation concerning them, then there’sno point in identifying a general right (= the firstprinciple, as stated) alongside them; and if we don’t,then we won’t have a legitimate expectation, henceno right (regardless of what the first principle states).The first principle, then, seems doomed either to bepointless and trivial or to be inaccurate if takenliterally.

The problem here is, perhaps, deeper even thanthis. In his theory of justice, Rawls operates withtwo distinct but related categories of analysis: theoriginal position and the basic structure of a society.The original position is quintessentially moral. Itcan be entered by anyone at any time. When peopleare in the original position they are there, all ofthem, as free, equal, rational, and moral persons.They are societyless. The original position is aforum for discussion and the formulation of princi-ples. It is a noninstitutional context. The basicstructure of a society is quite different in theserespects. It supposes a limited and finite populationof people whose entire lives will be lived togetherand who will bequeath, among other things, a set ofinstitutional arrangements to their children. Thepeople here are all inhabitants of some particularsociety and, hence, are co-citizens with one another;as fellow citizens, they are under the particular

political (and economic and social) institutions whichgo to make up the basic structure of that one society,their society. The basic structure of that society is anarena for application, for the building of principlesof justice into the ongoing life of that one society inparticular. The citizens’ principal concern is withinstitutional design and criticism. The basic struc-ture is necessarily an institutional context.

It is not clear, however, that the notion of rightscan flourish in both contexts. Rawls, and manyothers, have all too easily assumed that it can. Rawlshas made it sound as if talk of rights is fluid and canshift effortlessly from the one context to the other.What I have been delineating is at bottom not somuch a difficulty that is internal to Rawls’s theory(though certain tensions within that theory havehelped bring it to light) as it is a fundamentalphilosophical difficulty in how one talks intelligiblyabout rights. I will begin the next section with thatissue primarily in view, as our main topic fordiscussion there.

Before we move to that point, however, let mevery briefly summarize the main results of our briefintroductory survey of rights in Rawls’s theory. Wehave determined that two of the ways in whichRawls talked about rights are dispensable: any list-ing of rights among the social primary goods wasseen to be deeply confused and misleading, hencedispensable for that reason; any reference to rightsthat individuals might have (toward other individu-als or associations) in virtue of legitimate expecta-tions that arose through the workings of institutionsthat are subordinate to the basic structure (e.g.,rights of parishioners or clergy in a church) wasseen to be peripheral to our primary concern withbasic moral or constitutional rights. That left twomain areas for further discussion: (1) the supposedmoral right stated in the first principle of justice(‘‘each person is to have an equal right to the mostextensive total system of equal basic liberties com-patible with a similar system of liberty for all’’) and(2) the basic liberties themselves as rights. And Ihave suggested some reasons for saying that thesetwo do not fit well together. If my suggestions wereto be accepted—a point that depends on the argu-ment of the next section—then we would drop theidea that the first principle states a right at all. Wecould reword it, for example, in language reminis-cent of the second principle, to say that ‘‘politicalinstitutions are to be [or should be] so arranged thatthe most extensive justifiable system of liberties isto be available for each and all.’’ We would concen-trate then entirely on the idea that the basic liberties

Page 28: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

N o n f i c t i o n C l a s s i c s f o r S t u d e n t s3 1 4

named, in effect, in the first principle are rightswhen embedded in the basic structure of a society.Our whole discussion of rights in Rawls’s theorywould lead out from that one point. We turn to thefirst stages of that project, then, in the next section.

2. Natural Rights and the BasicStructure

Rawls is one of the few contemporary philoso-phers who uses natural rights as his standard term(Hart is another). We will assume, though, that hemeans by natural rights roughly what others havemeant by human rights. And I will treat these waysof talking as more or less interchangeable.

We can also assume that Rawls does not meanby natural rights what Thomas Hobbes and JohnLocke did; for them a natural right was any right thatan individual had in the state of nature. Such adoctrine would have no appeal to Rawls. He rarelyspeaks of such a state, and when he does, it is, by andlarge, to distinguish his account of the originalposition from that of the state of nature in classicalcontract theory. In Rawls’s view, one would reachsuch a state only if the participants in the originalposition failed utterly to achieve a decision onpreferred principles of justice and then decided, ineffect, that no principle on the short list could bepreferred to having no principle at all. A state ofnature, rather like the one Hobbes envisioned, wouldresult from that failure; it marks for Rawls the pointof ‘‘no agreement.’’ There is a deep gulf, then,between natural rights in Rawls’s theory, wherethey are identified by reference to the basic libertiesthat are listed in the preferred first principle ofjustice, and the idea in traditional contract theorythat such rights are the rights an individual haswilly-nilly in a state of nature.

Our main project in this section, then, is toprovide an interpretation of what Rawls means bynatural rights so understood. I will do this bysketching out an argument to show that the conceptof rights (hence that of human or natural rights)implies certain practices or institutional arrange-ments; thus, the notion of a natural (or human) rightas wholly noninstitutional, as logically prior to allpractices of formulation and maintenance, is a mis-take. It might appear from this that I am actuallyrepudiating the Rawlsian idea of natural rights. Butthis is not so, for I do not believe Rawls’s ideareproduces the traditional conception of naturalrights at the crucial points where it breaks down.

Now, supposing my argument to be sound, weare able to settle one important issue raised in theprevious section: whether, in Rawls’s theory, thenotion of rights takes hold at the point of the abstractstatement of the first principle in the original posi-tion or at the point of applying that principle to thebasic structure of a society. For I think my argumentforces the latter conclusion.

It follows that it is idle to describe the firstprinciple of justice itself as a right (even thoughRawls’s text can bear such an interpretation). I donot, of course, mean to say that the first principle isthereby pointless but only that the term right isdispensable in its formulation. The first principlecan be put differently, without using the term rightat all, and suffer no loss of essential contentwhatsoever—something that has already been sug-gested in the previous section.

My argument is designed to show, in short, thatit is only when basic liberties are built into the basicstructure of a society that they are properly calledrights in any significant sense. And this interpreta-tion of natural rights in Rawls’s theory—as basicliberties insofar as embedded in the basic structure—is one, I think, that can be gotten from Rawls’s textsand that can be supported by sound argumentsindependently of those texts.

My main contention here is that basic moralrights—natural rights—are basic structure rights(and in that sense constitutional rights). And now tothe argument.

Let us begin by turning to one of the maindimensions of what can be called legitimate expec-tations, that of claims against other persons. It isarguable such claims require there to be specificduties which fall on determinate or assignable indi-viduals. Lacking these, claims-against could nottake hold and would thereby be defective.

Rawls apparently concurs in this. For we notethat Rawls frequently pairs rights and duties. Itseems, moreover, that he regards rights as alwaysbeing correlated with duties—at least in the sensethat all rights as legitimate expectations imply du-ties of second parties (i.e., of persons other than therightholder). And if this pairing—this correlation—were not in evidence, then the claim-to element(e.g., the claim to a particular liberty) would not inand of itself count as a legitimate expectation and,hence, would not be a right for Rawls.

The filling in of the requisite background hereneed not, however, involve creating new duties (or

Page 29: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

V o l u m e 3 3 1 5

what have you); it may involve simply hooking onto existing ones. In both cases, though, a fullylegitimate expectation, hence a natural or a humanright, will combine a valid claim to something (e.g.,a liberty) with a valid claim on or against someone.

Thus, a legitimate expectation includes thesetwo elements (a morally justified claim-to and amorally justified claim-against); but can it be lim-ited to them? The question is whether a legitimateexpectation could be limited to being simply a validclaim (as defined by these two elements)—as thatand nothing more—and still count as a legitimateexpectation, still count as a right. Could one exist, inshort, without any sort of social recognition orpromotion whatsoever?

In order to answer this question we need to puta certain amount of logical pressure on the notion ofa legitimate expectation. The existence of a legiti-mate expectation in Rawls’s sense would probablyrequire, in the simplest case, that there be dutiesactually incumbent on persons in a particular soci-ety and that these could be derived or endorsed invirtue of standards of critical morality. For dutiesthat cannot be acknowledged in a given society—orthat cannot be shown to follow, discursively, fromaccredited principles of conduct which are at leastreflectively available to persons in that society—cannot be regarded as proper duties which couldnormatively bind conduct in that society.

Now, clearly, Rawls’s theory is committed tothe formulation and social recognition of principlesof justice in the original position and to soundarguments, themselves certified publicly there, con-necting the principles to goods such as specificliberties and thence to the duties of individualpersons.

But we would not want to restrict these possi-ble acknowledgments to the original position, forthen we would lose all hold on actual persons and ontheir duties and obligations. There must be somerequirement that the duties specified in criticalmorality (in the original position, for example) carryover into the real world of human action. Onecannot have an obligation (or a duty) of which oneliterally cannot be aware. An actual person’s con-duct cannot be determined by duty (or obligation) ifit is not possible for that person, even upon reflec-tion, to be aware of that duty as a duty.

Now, where the beliefs that people have (in-cluding their moral beliefs) effectively block ac-knowledgment of something as a duty, or as a claim

on the doing of their duty, then we have preciselythe unawareness of which I am speaking. Thus, if aduty is removed or a supposed moral reason forperforming one’s duty is removed, in a given timeor place, through such unawareness, then the legiti-mate expectation dissolves and loses the name ofright. For rights imply a significant normative direc-tion of the conduct of others, and that would bemissing in the case at hand.

A parallel argument could be developed toshow that if a certain claim-to (e.g., to a specificliberty) was similarly unavailable in a given societyor could not be understood in that society as follow-ing from principles of critical morality, then it couldgive rise to no legitimate expectation there. Hence itcould not be a right, nor could it constitute anelement in a right.

So there is an unexpungeable element of ‘‘so-cial’’ recognition built into the Rawlsian idea ofrights as legitimate expectations. And I have arguedthat this factor of social recognition cannot end withthe original position but must be extended intoactual societies, insofar as they have any prospect ofbecoming well ordered. Accordingly, questions aboutbasic rights must be addressed from this standpoint,as including both the original position and the basicstructure of societies which are well ordered (or atleast reasonably that way). This, of course, is Rawls’sposition’ for he requires the elaboration of thesewould-be basic rights (or legitimate expectations) inthe form of social institutions.

Now let us take this one step further, fromrecognition to maintenance. Here we will canvassthe issue of what counts as an exemplification of anatural or human right.

Consider the case of innocent travel. I wouldargue that the right to travel would be vitiated as aright if it were not protected or promoted at all. Insuch a case the right would be a merely nominal one,a right that existed in name only but not in fact. Anideal-type nominal right is in principle never anenforceable one; enforcement simply does not be-long to its nature. Its permanent ‘‘recognition’’could be assured (the liberty put in writing, en-shrined in a declaration or in a bill of rights, honoredby lip service), but its perpetual nonenforcementwould be equally assured. Such rights do not, assome have suggested, constitute a special class offull-fledged rights. Rather, they constitute a limitingcase; they are rights only on paper and nowhere else.

Page 30: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

N o n f i c t i o n C l a s s i c s f o r S t u d e n t s3 1 6

Now, to be sure, nominal rights are rights. Thepoint is, though, that we regard the total absence ofpromotion and maintenance as infirming a right, asrendering it defective. Nominal rights are rights inone sense only (that of recognition), but they fail tofunction as rights. A merely nominal right gives nonormative direction to the conduct of other personsin fact; such persons act as if the right did not existeven on paper. No one of them takes the nominalexistence of the right as a reason for doing, or notdoing, as the right directs. The right here has inactual practice no justificatory or directive force.Where social recognition effectively counts for solittle, the rightholder is without any effective guar-antee respecting that which has been recognized andformulated as a moral right. Such a right—whenmerely nominal—has failed in a crucial respect. Itrepresents at best a marginal and precarious exam-ple of a right. On the assumption that any rightunder serious discussion here is not merely nominal,then, for any particular moral right, there wouldhave to be certain appropriate practices of promo-tion, protection, enforcement, and so forth, on thepart of society, including at least forbearance by(other) private persons. The determination of whatis appropriate for a basic moral right then becomesthe exact point at issue.

The great natural- and human-rights manifes-toes were intended to impose restraints upon gov-ernments. Individuals were involved as beneficiar-ies of these restraints but, for the most part, were notthe parties to whom the manifestoes were addressed.The right to a fair trial, which is often given as anexample of a natural right (by Rawls and others), isa right that one has against governments in particu-lar, especially one’s own. The example is by nomeans atypical. Whether we look at details ofspecific rights, as we find them in the great declara-tions of rights, or at the theory of natural rights(including its actual history), we find that govern-ment is in fact the principal addressee.

Thus, I would want to argue that, insofar as theclaims-against implicated in natural or human rightsare addressed to governments in particular, we haveto regard practices of governmental recognition andpromotion as being the appropriate form that suchsocial recognition and maintenance must take. Tothat degree, governmental practices are includedwithin the notion of natural rights. They are (or havebecome) a part of the concept in question. A natural-or human-rights claim that lacks such recognitionand promotion is still a valid claim, but it cannotqualify as a proper natural or human right.

And the issue of whether something is a naturalright, or whether such rights ‘‘exist’’ or whetherpeople ‘‘have’’ them, cannot be decided withoutconsideration of the whole range of relevant prac-tices, which include recognition in law and govern-mental maintenance of the claimed way of acting orof being treated. Such practices are ingredient in thevery notion of what it is for something to be anatural or a human right, or so my argument ismeant to show.

Now it may be, I would add, that for someuniversal moral rights the role of government isincidental or even nonexistent. These rights holdstrictly between persons. The moral right to be toldthe truth (or at least not to be lied to) or the moralright to gratitude for benefits provided or, perhaps,the moral right to have promises kept are examples.Such rights differ from, say, the right not to bekilled—even when we’re talking about the latterright as held against individuals—in being rightsthat are maintained exclusively, or almost exclu-sively, by conscience. They are moral rights merelyand in no way claims against the government.Interestingly, though, it is often in these very casesthat while we are willing to call such rights moralrights, we would tend to withhold the name ofhuman (or natural) right.

There is a sound basis for saying, then, thatnatural-rights norms (i.e., valid claims) are ad-dressed to governments primarily. And natural orhuman rights can be distinguished from other uni-versal moral rights in this very circumstance.

There is an important reason, which needsbringing out, for precisely this restriction. In talk ofspecifically human or natural rights, it is assumedthat human beings live in societies. The goods thatare identified in claims-to are here conceived asgoods obtained and enjoyed in a social setting. Thatis, such goods are conceived as provided peculiarlyor especially through life in a society. They are not,in short, thought to be attained principally, if at all,on a mere individual-person-to-all-others basis. Herethen, where the social context is emphasized, claimsagainst others are for the most part addressed not toindividuals as such but, rather, to individuals insofaras they exercise the powers of some assigned agencyin that particular social setting. Such claims-againsthold, not against everyone individually, but againstan organized society; and it is of the institutions—oragencies—of that society that satisfaction is expected.

Admittedly, it is not so much governments as itis organized societies that are selected out by human-

Page 31: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

V o l u m e 3 3 1 7

or natural-rights claims. The point, though, is thatthe basic structures of such societies are correctlyregarded as being politically organized; and it isgovernments that typically play, and have played, amajor role in such organization. Thus, governmententers the natural-rights picture as the organizer,and as one of the major agencies, of the kind ofsociety against which a natural-rights claim is char-acteristically lodged. Thus, the requirement thatnatural rights be lodged in the basic structure of asociety, that their status as rights of this sort requiressuch incorporation, seems to follow naturally. Andthis I take to be the view that Rawls is advancing.

If my analysis is correct or even plausible, wehave a reason for the central place that governmentoccupies in our concept of natural or human rights;given this reason, we find it natural that recognitionand maintenance by governmental action (the satis-faction principally sought in natural-rights claims)should be relativized to particular societies. Forthese claims, insofar as we have regard to theirprimary addressee, are satisfied by political devices(e.g., basic laws) having an appropriately universalscope within a particular society. Such a law wouldexist when, for example, a freedom to travel on thepart of every citizen (or preferably, every person)was recognized in the law of that society andscrupulously enforced. We can call any such opera-tive and universal right (i.e., universal within agiven society) a general political or civil right—or,if you will, a constitutional right. The latter, whichis the more conventional term, seems service-able enough.

This particular notion of constitutional rights iseasily inserted into Rawls’s theory. The rights hehas in mind are, on their claim-to side, universal andunconditional (in that a valid moral claim holdsgood for everyone, or at least for everyone who isalive at a given time—for the ground of the claim issimply a title to something or other that is given toall persons, merely in virtue of their being persons,in accordance with moral principles). This is how Iwould interpret Rawls’s contention that the basicliberties, as determined in the original position, arenatural rights. That is, on their claim-to side they arelike natural rights in the traditional sense. Suchclaims are explicitly accommodated in the basicstructure of any well-ordered society; and they are,under the requirement of a public sense of institu-tional justice, not only formulated and acknowl-edged but also scrupulously maintained there by theparticular government involved.

There is, I would note, though, an importantasymmetry between the claims-to part and the claims-against part of a complete (or full) valid moralclaim. The former may well be universal and virtu-ally without restriction; yet it does not follow auto-matically here that the claim-against element will besimilarly universal. For example, all human beingsare, or were at one time, children and all have (orhad) the appropriate claims to care and concern: tonourishment, upbringing, and so on. But these claimson the part of each child are principally addressed,not to anyone and everyone, but to that child’sparents or guardians in particular. Rights that arethus restricted are called special (rather than gen-eral) rights. I want to suggest that something likethis functions in the case of human or natural rights;they too are special rights. The claim-to element isunrestricted: it holds for every person (or for everyperson who is alive at a given time). But the claim-against element is typically restricted: not all per-sons, but only some (namely, agencies of govern-ment), are addressed as principally having the moralduty in question. It is their job to arrange thebasic structure so as to incorporate the substance ofthese claims-to for the benefit of their respectiveinhabitants.

Indeed, the term basic structure right, which Iintroduced in the previous section, seems to besingularly well suited to capture the peculiar senseof constitutional rights that we want to have in view.The turn to constitutional—or basic structure—rights reflects the fact that human rights typicallyare special rights and are claimed on moral groundswhich hold good for all persons, simply in virtue oftheir being persons, against particular politicallyorganized societies—specifically, against govern-ments. (Or, as Rawls would probably prefer to say,against one’s fellow citizens.) The question ofwhether a particular valid and universal moral claimhas been appropriately responded to by governmentor by the members of one’s society is answered byconsidering the class of active constitutional rights.Such rights, when molded under the influence ofthese claims, are the kind of right involved. Theirexistence is a necessary element in a morally validclaim’s being (or becoming) a natural or a hu-man right.

If a particular constitutional right is missing ina given country, then lacking this necessary ingredi-ent, the incipient natural right will fail to jell or itwill dissolve, for that country or for that time andplace. And we are at best left with a moral claim

Page 32: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

N o n f i c t i o n C l a s s i c s f o r S t u d e n t s3 1 8

(presumably valid) that something should be a con-stitutional right.

The basic contention, then, which forms thebackdrop of this entire study is that natural orhuman rights necessarily have an institutional sideand that, on this side, they would have in a givensociety the form of constitutional rights. We recog-nize, of course, that even in a well-ordered societythere may be some constitutional rights which donot have the sort of direct backing, in a valid anduniversal moral claim as determined from the per-spective of the original position, that we have beendiscussing. These would not, then, be called naturalrights. Natural rights are confined to those constitu-tional or basic structure rights that have the appro-priate moral support. I will restrict my discussion inwhat follows to things that are natural rights in thisprecise sense.

It is often asked what something that is other-wise a human or natural right would be in a societyin which the relevant constitutional right was lack-ing. The answer is that it would be merely a morallyvalid claim there. Or to be exact, it would be a validclaim that holds, insofar as practicable, for each andevery person in that society, against the governmentthere (and in many cases against private personsalso). The claim would hold simply in virtue of itsfollowing from accredited moral principles. And theclaim would be that the thing identified as the claim-to element (e.g., a given basic liberty as specified inRawls’s first principle) should be established as anoperating basic structure or constitutional right inthat society.

Any such claim would have an important useinsofar as it was or could be acknowledged bypeople in that society. (And it would most likely beif the conventional morality of that society is suchthat the first principle would be affirmed when thatconventional morality was carefully reflected upon.)For it would provide a realistic and reasonable basisfor criticizing the conduct of government or ofpeople generally in that society. Thus, the govern-ment could be criticized for failing to promote andmaintain a course of action, or a way of beingtreated, that was incorporated in law as somethingto be promoted and maintained. Or it could becriticized—that is, the society in question could becriticized—for having failed to take even the firststep, that of incorporation into the basic structureand, hence, of authoritative recognition in law.These criticisms would be perfectly sound insofaras they followed from accredited principles (as

developed in critical morality, e.g., in the originalposition) and insofar as they really could be made toconnect up with the normative direction that wasprovided to people in that society by their existingmorality or by their system of law.

Thus, for instance, on the assumption that thereare morally sound arguments (in the original posi-tion, as incorporated in the first principle) againstthe practice of slavery, we could say that slaves (inthe United States in the late eighteenth or earlynineteenth century) had a morally valid claim topersonal liberty despite what the United StatesConstitution said or implied (or despite what intel-lectual defenders of slavery, such as Aristotle, mighthave said). More important, there was a morallyvalid claim that this particular liberty should beembodied as a constitutional or civil right (specifi-cally as a right not to be enslaved) for every humanperson in that society. The intended result of au-thoritatively acknowledging this claim in that soci-ety is that slavery would cease to exist there (butuntil it did so, the right established by that acknowl-edgment would be, to some degree, a nominal one).We could expect, then, that the personal libertywould become in time a proper or full-fledgedright—that is, an active constitutional or basic struc-ture right there.

The moral soundness of this criticism of slav-ery does not require that there be some rightsuperordinate to conventional morality or to exist-ing systems of law. Indeed, legally sanctioned slav-ery may violate no one’s rights in those cases wherethe relevant liberties have not been incorporated asbasic structure rights. Nonetheless, the crucial pointremains that legally sanctioned slavery is alwaysunjust (a point that I will argue more fully in the nextchapter). But whether or not something is a rightraises a somewhat different set of questions. Naturalrights are not simply demands of justice, not even ofdistributive justice. Rather, as I have argued in thissection, the crucial issue here is whether appropriatepractices of recognition and promotion are in placefor that kind of right. For without such socialrecognition and maintenance, whatever was said tobe justified, on moral grounds, would not be aproper right.

There is, we see on reflection, an irreducibleduality to human or natural rights. On the one side,they are morally validated claims to some benefit orother. On the other side, such rights require recogni-tion in law and promotion by government of the

Page 33: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

V o l u m e 3 3 1 9

claimed way of acting or of being treated. Neitherside is dispensable in a human or natural right.

On its legal side a human or natural right wouldhave the form of a constitutional right. If there areany natural rights at all, it follows that there areactive constitutional rights in at least some coun-tries. There will be such rights in all Rawlsian well-ordered societies.

This concludes my line of argument and my useof that argument to interpret Rawls’s notion ofnatural rights. One caveat is, perhaps, in order.Rawls says that ‘‘the liberties of equal citizenshipmust be incorporated into and protected by theconstitution’’; this is often interpreted as requiringtheir incorporation into a bill of rights. Thus, itmight appear that Rawls’s account requires, as amatter of justice, that a well-ordered society have awritten constitution. But this is a considerable over-simplification. (Though we can say that, wherethere is a written constitution, it should incorporatethe liberties that are listed in the first principle ofjustice.)

What Rawls’s position requires, fundamen-tally, is the rule of law; with his emphasis onpublicity it would follow that such rules will beexplicitly formulated—or at least the more impor-tant ones are required to be. Among these importantlaws will be some that are regarded as basic (e.g.,laws in a representative—parliamentary—democ-racy that set the term of a parliament, that identifythe frequency of elections, that stipulate how orwhen a parliament may be dissolved, etc.). Thus,whatever counts as the basic laws in a society, thoseare to include laws that formulate and afford protec-tion to the basic rights. Accordingly, a country likeGreat Britain, which has no written constitution,could incorporate universal political—that is, con-stitutional—rights into its basic laws and therebyconform to Rawls’s requirement.

It is even possible to imagine nonlegal sourcesof constitutional rights. Their principal formulationcould occur in a religious book or code or in a workof philosophy (such as Mill’s On Liberty). Or itcould occur in some political document (such as theDeclaration of Independence or the Federalist Papersor Lincoln’s Gettysburg Address) which lies largelyoutside the law. And it could occur outside the usuallegal context of explicit constitutional provisions orvalid statutes (as, for one example, the United StatesSupreme Court’s assertion of a fundamental ‘‘rightof privacy’’ does or, for another example, as doesthe considerable codification, by the Executive

Branch, of rights to ‘‘affirmative action’’). What isimportant is that basic rights be formulated, thatsome formulation be authoritatively recognizedwithin the standard political and legal channels of asociety, and that, within these channels, governmentbring its powers to bear so as to promote andmaintain the rights that are authoritatively recog-nized. It is this kind of commitment to basic rights,which can control the political process and is nevertaken lightly by the political agencies, that Rawlshad in mind. (And, we should hasten to add, manyof these rights will also normatively direct theconduct of individual citizens as well.)

Rights that are so understood become, literally,a part of the basic structure. The way of thinking Ihave tried to portray here is very like the ancientGreek conception of a constitution (politeia) as thatwhich concerns the principal parts of the polis—orof the state, as we would call it. If we keep in mindthe Rawlsian idea that constitutional rights are basicstructure rights, we will not depart too far from thisfundamental conception.

This brings us back to the main contention thatI have tried to advance in this section: namely, thatfor Rawls, basic moral rights—natural rights—arebasic structure rights (and in that sense constitu-tional rights). And I have sketched out a rathercomplex argument, both to interpret Rawls’s idea ofnatural rights and to support his insistence on theexplicit formulation by government of rights in thebasic structure and of the development there ofattendant political institutions for the promotion andmaintenance of these rights. I have argued that atheory of natural rights would fail insofar as itleaves out these latter features, of appropriate socialrecognition and protection, which are essential toany proper right. For without such measures, therecould be no basic structure guarantee to an individ-ual of what was justifiably claimed as his due, andhe could not count on getting what was claimed.There would be no legitimate expectation, hence notrue right as part of the basic structure, in theabsence of such formulation and maintenance.

Admittedly, the basic liberties are understoodas explicitly stated in the first principle of justice(though their formulation there is a rather looseone). This initial formulation does occur, and canonly occur, in the original position. But there are nomechanisms for protection in the original position.It is merely anticipated that there will be some suchdevices. The original position exists simply so thatthe principles of justice can be stated (and can be

Page 34: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

N o n f i c t i o n C l a s s i c s f o r S t u d e n t s3 2 0

seen, as stated, to be reasonable and well founded).Hence the liberties that are listed from the perspec-tive of the original position can be, when in theoriginal position, at best merely morally valid claims.Even if we were to waive the requirement of socialrecognition, letting the formulation of these libertiesin the original position stand as surrogate, the rightsthere would still be analogous to constitutionalrights that were merely nominal. This gives thereason, then, why it is empty to regard the firstprinciple of justice, when merely formulated in theoriginal position, as itself a basic right, or as listingbasic rights, in any full and significant sense.

But the liberties, as listed in the first principle,can be built into the basic structure of a society, andwhen they are incorporated in the way I havespecified, they become proper rights. They becomeconstitutional rights, parts of the basic structure.

3. Global JusticeFor Rawls all natural or fundamental rights,

insofar as they are rights, strictly conceived, arenecessarily embedded in the basic structure ofsociety—that is, of some particular society. Thebasic liberties are goods of all people, everywhereand at all times. But they are realized as goods onlyin society—and for any individual, that means insome specific society. Thus, when we look at basicliberties, not as liberties but as constitutional rights,there is an important sense in which they are not‘‘globalized,’’ not spread, as it were, to the fourcorners of the earth as a single blanket of rightscovering all peoples. As proper natural rights suchrights enjoy, and can only enjoy, a local existence,in the basic structure of a given society.

Why should this be? Because, as I argued in theprevious section, Rawls apparently believes that thebasic liberties are inadequately determined—notproperly identified or distributed or guaranteed toindividuals—in a setting that lacks mechanisms fordefining rights: for setting their scope, for adjustingthem one to another, for assuring that they will bedistributed to actual individuals, for enforcing andprotecting that distribution, and so on. Individualpolitical societies—states—have such mechanisms.They are, given their relative independence andself-contained character, the largest such entities,and the most important ones, that do have theappropriate mechanisms. Thus, the same reasonwhich underwrote Rawls’s claim that the basicstructure of a society is the first subject of justicealso underwrites his housing of natural rights—

basic liberties as constitutional rights—within dis-crete political societies.

The motivation is practical, not logical. Theworld itself could be the locus of natural rightsif there were a world government. But there isn’t.There is no basic structure—no politicalinfrastructure—for the globe. The largest viableunit today is the nation state.

This does not mean that a larger, more inclusivepolitical society would be inappropriate, nor does itmean that one should not work to achieve a largerframework. Indeed, if we take seriously the idea thatthe basic liberties should be rights of all people, thensuch a global framework might well be indicated.(Though, equally, it might be indicated that theliberties should be incorporated into the basic struc-ture of every existing political society.) But thepoint is that the possibility of a global framework isvery remote at present.

Suppose, though, that one wanted to work nowto help globalize the basic liberties as rights at somefuture date. How should one best go about this?Rawls’s answer seems to be—I am theorizing here—that a plausible procedure would be for individualstates to strive (where their traditions and institu-tional development permitted) to conform them-selves to justice in their basic structure. This mightwell constitute a necessary first step. After that,some further move might be possible—perhaps aninternational association of such states and the de-velopment of a new political infrastructure, actingdirectly on individual persons, within that associa-tion. Something like this further move is afoot inwestern Europe today, though what has resulted sofar is much more like a confederation of states thanlike an individual state.

A good argument could be made, then, thatdirect moves to a global state—or to a large confed-eration of inevitably and radically unlike-mindedstates—from where we are today is not wise. Also,it would not be practical. Nor would it be likely tohelp achieve anything like the end in view: theglobalization of basic liberties as rights for allpeople everywhere.

All this is useless speculation, however, if welose sight of the main point. Basic liberties cannotbe rights except in a suitable institutional context.They cannot be effective constitutional rights ex-cept in the basic structure of a political society. Wemust confine ourselves, then, to consideration ofsuch basic structures. Insofar as we are interested in

Page 35: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

V o l u m e 3 3 2 1

institutional design that has any prospect of practi-cal application, we must not outrun the range ofexisting or feasible basic structures. Thus, we arenecessarily concerned with the largest viable politi-cal societies—independent states—and their basicstructures. This precludes, for the foreseeable futureat least, any serious program for designing a globalor even an ambitious confederative scheme of basicliberty rights.

The same inhibitions that I have just described,as existing for the basic liberties of the first princi-ple, will also exist for the other primary goods asdetermined in the second principle (under its twomain headings, fair equality of opportunity and thedifference principle). The operation of these twofeatures are equally meant to be confined to thebasic structures of particular societies. And for thesame reason: namely, that today the necessary po-litical infrastructure exists only in these societiesand not globally.

It could, of course, be urged that economicallythere is at present a great mutual interdependenceamong peoples of the earth. But even if globaleconomic interdependence is a fact, two pointsremain germane.

First, we can speak from the perspective of theoriginal position. The parties there would be con-cerned about the well-being of persons in anysociety—hence in all societies, whether or not thesesocieties and these persons were economically in-terdependent. The whole point of formulating prin-ciples of justice, it seems to me, is to identify areasof appropriate concern for the well-being of personseverywhere insofar as that well-being is a matter ofbasic fairness. The fact of economic interdepend-ence on a global scale is quite irrelevant to thisconcern. It can become relevant, but only dependingon what the unit of application is. If the unit ofapplication is the existing market (or the multina-tional firm or capitalist society), then the fact ofglobal economic interdependence is clearly rele-vant. But if the unit of application of the differenceprinciple is the basic structure of a political society,then equally clearly it is not.

The perspective of the basic structure of societyis the second one that we can take and must take inorder to determine which unit of application is theappropriate one. Suppose the basic structure is aswe’ve already described it (in the earlier discussionin this section of basic liberties); one would have tosay in such a case that there is no world-widepolitical structure that answers to the global eco-

nomic community. Accordingly, there can be noworld-wide application of the difference principletoday. There cannot be; for that principle, in order tobe applied, requires political mechanisms, not merelyeconomic ones. The relevant political mechanismsexist, for now at least, only in independent nationalstates (or perhaps in certain federations of these) butnot globally, not in any single, all-encompassingpolitical regime. And what is true for the operationof the difference principle holds also for fair equal-ity of opportunity: the political mechanisms re-quired for its application do not now exist, to anypractical degree, except in particular societies, inindependent states.

So, the Rawlsian concentration on the basicstructure of a particular society, which I have triedto bring out through my analysis of natural rights,limits the application of the preferred principles ofjustice in a very fundamental way. For direct globalapplication is ruled out—once, that is, we takeaccount of the actual character of the contemporarypolitical world. And I will observe this limitation—in effect a limitation to the basic structure of someparticular political society (or state)—throughoutmy discussion of the application of the two princi-ples of justice.

In the analysis of this and the previous section,we have a setting for Rawls’s discussion of basicliberties as rights. I will turn to a more exactingaccount of these liberties in the next chapter.

Source: Rex Martin, ‘‘A Theory of Justice and Rights,’’ inRawls and Rights, University Press of Kansas, 1985, pp.21–44.

Sources

Barry, Brian, The Liberal Theory of Justice: A CriticalExamination of the Principal Doctrines in ‘‘A Theory ofJustice’’ by John Rawls, Clarendon Press, 1973, p. ix.

Davion, Victoria, and Clark Wolf, eds., The Idea of aPolitical Liberalism: Essays on Rawls, Rowman and LittlefieldPublishers, Inc., 2000, pp. 1, 3, 14.

Freeman, Samuel, ed., John Rawls: Collected Papers, Har-vard University Press, 1999, pp. ix, xii.

Martin, Rex, Rawls and Rights, University Press of Kansas,1985, p. vii.

Rao, A. P., Three Lectures on John Rawls, Indian Philosoph-ical Quarterly Publications, 1981, p. 1.

Schaefer, David Lewis, Justice or Tyranny?: A Critique ofJohn Rawls’s ‘‘A Theory of Justice,’’ Kennikat Press, 1979,pp. ix, 105.

Page 36: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

A T h e o r y o f J u s t i c e

N o n f i c t i o n C l a s s i c s f o r S t u d e n t s3 2 2

Wolff, Robert Paul, Understanding Rawls: A Reconstructionand Critique of ‘‘A Theory of Justice,’’ Princeton UniversityPress, 1977, pp. 3, 16.

Further Reading

Alejandro, Roberto, The Limits of Rawlsian Justice, JohnsHopkins University Press, 1998.

Alejandro provides critical discussion of Rawls’stheory of justice in relation to the American legalsystem.

Corlett, J. Angelo, ed., Equality and Liberty: AnalyzingRawls and Nozick, St. Martin’s Press, 1991.

Corlett provides a collection of essays addressing thethemes of justice, equality, and liberty in the works ofRawls and his primary critic, Robert Nozick.

George, Robert P., and Christopher Wolfe, eds., Natural Lawand Public Reason, Georgetown University Press, 2000.

George and Wolfe provide a collection of essays thatfocus on the themes of natural law, liberalism, andreason in the work of Rawls.

Page 37: A Theory of Justice by John Rawls

Nonfiction Classics forStudentsProvides detailed literary and historicalbackground on the most commonlystudied nonfiction essays, books, biog-raphies and memoirs in a streamlined,easy-to-use format. Covering 15-20works per volume, this reference seriesgives high school and undergraduatestudents an ideal starting point for

class assignments, term papers and special projects. Entriesprovide: a brief author biography; a general introduction toand summary of the work; an annoted list of principal charac-ters; general discussions of the organization and construction,historical and cultural context, and principal themes of thework; and original critical essays written by academics in thefield, supplemented by excerpted previously published essaysand a list of sources for further reading. In addition, entries typically include information on media adaptations; readingrecommendations; a list of study questions; and more.

Novels for StudentsContains easily accessible and context-rich discussions of the literary and historical significance of major novelsfrom various cultures and time periods.Entries provide: a brief author biogra-phy; a general introduction to andsummary of the work; an annoted listof principal characters; general discus-sions of the organization and con-

struction, historical and cultural context, and principal themesof the work; and original critical essays written by academics inthe field, supplemented by excerpted previously publishedessays and a list of sources for further reading. In addition,entries typically include information on media adaptations;reading recommendations; a list of study questions; and more.

Drama for StudentsFeatures detailed coverage of the playsmost frequently studied in literatureclasses. Entries provide: a brief authorbiography; a general introduction toand summary of the work; an annotedlist of principal characters; general discussions of the organization andconstruction, historical and culturalcontext, and principal themes of the

work; original critical essays written by academics in the field,supplemented by excerpted previously published essays; a list ofsources for further reading; and more.

Short Stories forStudentsEach volume presents detailed infor-mation on approximately 20 of themost-studied short stories at the highschool and early-college levels. Entriesprovide: a brief author biography; ageneral introduction to and summaryof the work; an annoted list of princi-pal characters; general discussions of

the organization and construction, historical and cultural context, and principal themes of the work; and original criticalessays written by academics in the field, supplemented byexcerpted previously published essays. In addition, entries typi-cally include information on media adaptations; reading rec-ommendations; a list of study questions; and more.

Epics for StudentsThis reference is designed to providestudents and other researchers with aguide to understanding and enjoyingthe epic literature that is most studiedin classrooms. Each entry includes anintroductory essay; biographical information on the author; a plotsummary; an examination of the epic’sprincipal themes, style, construction,

historical background and critical reception; and an originalcritical essay supplemented by excerpted previously publishedcriticism. In addition, entries typically include information onmedia adaptations; reading recommendations; a list of studyquestions; and more.

Shakespeare forStudentsThese accessible volumes provideessential interpretation and criticismof the Shakespeare plays most oftenstudied in secondary schools andundergraduate curricula. Each play istreated in approximately 50 to 75pages of text. Entries feature an intro-duction to the play, including a plot

summary, descriptive list of characters and outline of the generalcritical issues related to studying the play; annotated criticismreprinted from periodicals and academic journals and arrangedby general topic/theme; and lists of sources for further study.

Gale Group’s “For Students” Literature Guides

Visit us on the Web at www.gale.com