A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

28
8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP) http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 1/28 Two Paths of Agrarian Capitalism, or a Critique of Chayanovian Marxism Author(s): David Lehmann Source: Comparative Studies in Society and History, Vol. 28, No. 4 (Oct., 1986), pp. 601-627 Published by: Cambridge University Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/178884 Accessed: 23/04/2010 14:33 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cup . Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Cambridge University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Comparative Studies in Society and History. http://www.jstor.org

Transcript of A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

Page 1: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 1/28

Two Paths of Agrarian Capitalism, or a Critique of Chayanovian MarxismAuthor(s): David LehmannSource: Comparative Studies in Society and History, Vol. 28, No. 4 (Oct., 1986), pp. 601-627Published by: Cambridge University PressStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/178884

Accessed: 23/04/2010 14:33

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at

http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless

you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you

may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at

http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cup.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed

page of such transmission.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of 

content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

Cambridge University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to

Comparative Studies in Society and History.

http://www.jstor.org

Page 2: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 2/28

Two Paths of AgrarianCapitalism,or

a Critiqueof ChayanovianMarxismDAVID LEHMANN

Universityof Cambridge

I. INTRODUCTION: UNEQUAL EXCHANGE AND PEASANT

ECONOMY--UNDERLYING ASSUMPTIONS

Inthe ideologyof "dependency"andthe "worldsystem" thepreservation fa compradorbourgeoisiehighly dependenton its controlof thestateapparatusperpetuateshe condition of underdevelopmento the benefit not only of thatclass but also of the worldcapitalistsystem, andobviouslyto the detrimentofthe remainder of the population of poor countries (Wallerstein 1984).

Accordingto these theories, the conditionof dependency s sustainedalso bythe perpetuationof petty-commodityproductionand otherprecapitalistrela-

tionships.In his enumerationof the implicationsof accumulationn "sociallyandsectorallydisarticulated conomies" (thatis, thirdworldcountries),Al-

ain de Janvry, who places himself, with some reservations, in theworld-system school, states that "subsistence agriculturebecomes the ulti-mateembodimentof the contradictionsof accumulation n the disarticulated

economies; . . . the peasanthouseholdconstitutesan articulated-dominated

purveyorof cheap labour and cheap food [even though] subsistence agri-cultureslowly disintegratesunderthis dominationas it performs ts essentialstructuralunctionunderdisarticulatedaccumulation"(1981:39). ForImma-nuel Wallerstein, the state-class relationshipand the persistence of petty-commodityproductionare both features of the "peripheralcondition" and

explainwhy it is so difficult (thoughnotabsolutelyimpossible)in his schemafor countriesto graduate rom his peripheryandsemiperipheryo the core ofadvancedeconomies. The argumentruns as follows: in its expansionacrossthe globe the capitalist world economy creates social structuresand statestructures hat fit the needs of the core economies by establishinga rulingclass in control of the state and holding monopolypower withinthe national

economy. These relationshipsareparticularly uitable for the provisionof the

primarycommodities and low-productivity goods requiredby the core, but

theyalso

placethe

rulingclass in a

positionwhereit can extract

surpluseven

thoughits industriesare unproductiveand inefficient in internationalerms.These industriesareunderpinnedby state subsidies andstate-guaranteedmo-

nopolies. Thus the interestsof every majorpartyare satisfied:the dominant

0010-4175/86/4120-0231 $2.50 ? 1986 Society for ComparativeStudyof Society andHistory

6oi

Page 3: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 3/28

602 DAVID LEHMANN

corporationsrom thecoreget cheapgoods as inputs,and thecapitalistsystemis not threatenedby a revolt of the peripheryover primary-commoditypricesbecause the people in charge of the peripheryare successfully co-opted,living as it were "on the difference" throughtheir controlof the terms onwhich goods enter and leave peripheralcountries. (Countryin this contextrefersmerely to the territorydefined by one state's monopolyof legitimateviolence andby no othersignificanteconomic or culturalhomogeneity.)Thecore proletariats likewise co-opted since it has common interests with thecorecorporations gainstthe periphery,while the peripheryproletariathardlyexists at all. Instead, the subordinateclasses in peripheralcountriesare the

peasantryandworkers n the urban nformalsectorwho are

caughtin a web of

exploitationbased on those very householdproduction ystemswhichtendtoisolatethemand thusdeprivethem of the basis for sustainedsolidaryaction.

Thus the theoryof dependencyis structured n such a way that it simplydoes not allow for the possibility thatthe poorcountriesmightextract them-

selves, short of an apocalypticchange in the entire world system-worldsocialism, Wallersteinterms it, while rapidly conceding that there is nochance of it ever arising.This is a farcry from Marx's own view of capitalistdevelopment, thoughthatin itself need not be a basis for objection. Authors

in the dependencyandworld-systemschools clearlydo not believe that "thecountrythat is the more advancedindustriallyonly shows to the less devel-

oped the image of its own future" (Marx 1976:91). They also depart quiteseriouslyfrom Marx's view of the state in capitalistdevelopment.ForMarx,the action of the state was crucialat the stage of "primitive" or "original"accumulation;he stateopened the way for capitalistrelations of productionwith whatever violence was necessary, by wrenchingthe peasantryoff the

land and otherwise creatinga "free" labour force. Thereafter,the market

would look after itself. Wallerstein's image of the state's nonautonomous,

incestuousrelationshipwith theentrepreneuriallasses as a permanent,defin-ing featureof peripheral ormationsis radicallydifferent.

Theimportantelationshipntheseargumentss thatestablishedbetweenthe

existence of precapitalistmechanismsandthe claim thatthey arethe element

that contributesdecisively to the perpetuation f poverty.The implicationsof

theworkof WallersteinandSamirAmin arethatif the state didnotoperate nthe monopolisticandalmostfeudalway that characterises t in the periphery,thenthe fruitsof capitalistdevelopmentwouldspreadevenly acrosstheglobe,andalso thatthe state cannotoperateotherwise; ts functioning s, so to speak,

overdetermined.Likewise, it is preciselytheprecapitalist-or perhaps"non-capitalist"-elements in the organisationof peasantproduction hatareboth

sustainedby the capitalist system and also perpetuatethe poverty of the

peasantry.Statedthus, the thesis implies that the solutionfor the peasantrysnot the advent of socialism but merely the lifting of the barriersto their

Page 4: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 4/28

TWO PATHS OF AGRARIAN CAPITALISM 603

becomingcapitalists.This is wherewe confrontthe Chinese Wall thatcannot

be penetrated.A deeply held assumption in the discourse concerning the

peasantrys thatpeasantsaresituatedat a pole oppositeto capitalistson everydimensionrelevantto the characterisation f either modes of productionorunits of production,and that the "logic" or "rationality"of peasantproduc-tionprevents hemfrombecoming capitalists.When it is pointedout thatthis

posesdifficulties, say, in the case of a verysmallproducerof coffee, or indeedof cocaine, for the worldmarket,thenall mannerof embarrassment nsues. Inthefollowingparagraphs show thatone can haveaviabledefinitionof peasantformsof productionwithoutriskingsuchembarrassment, ut that an ideologi-cal shifton the

partof the adherentsof

dependencyand

world-systemstheories

is probablyrequired f they are to accept it.

"The costs of productionon a peasant farm are lower than those of a

capitalist armproducing he samecropon the samepiece of land." If thereis

one pointon which all relevantschools of thoughtareagreed n their accountsof peasanteconomies it is this. For A. V. Chayanov(1967) this explainsthesurvival of the "labour farm" or peasant enterprise; or MichaelLiptonit isan argumentfor the redistributionof land (1974) or for the redirection ofstate-controlledresources fromthe city to the countryside(1977); for Amar-

tya Sen (1966) it also explains the survival of peasant producersand thepersistenceof institutionssuchas sharecropping;or Alainde Janvry 1982) itis an element in the functionalrelationshipbetween peasant productionand

capitalism.Inall theseanalyses, the low costs, translatednto low outputpricesand the

low cost of peasantlabour(when it is the subjectof a markettransaction),arisefrom and areexplainedby the fact (orassumption) hat labour n peasantproduction s unpaidbecause of its family, domestic, or household character.This is takento implynot thatit is cost-free butthatit is less costly thanwage

labour.The wage a peasant's labourmight fetch if it were sold on the openmarket-its opportunitycost-is presumedto be very small because of the

extremelyhigh rates of unemploymentattributed o pooragrarian conomies.In contrastto peasantproducers,the capitalist employer is assumedto incuradditionalcosts of recruitment ndsupervision,and mustpay a wage of some

sort;this wage will be higherthanthe irreduciblesubsistence costs incurred

by peasanthousehold producersbecause it will reflect the compulsions of

disciplineand regularitiesof timetableimposed upon workers in a capitalistfirm. It is assumed that these "external" constraints,like "economising"

behaviour,cease to apply at the gates of the peasantfarm: within a peasanthouseholdaltruism,joint utilities, and internalisednorms take the place of

optimisingbehaviour(Folbre 1985).The definition of a peasant (better used as an adjective, for example,

peasantproducer)sharedby these writers, then, insists on the domestic and

Page 5: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 5/28

604 DAVID LEHMANN

unpaidcharacterof labour in peasant units of production,and the conse-

quenceof this characteristics said to be thatthose unitssupply productsand

even labour o the rest of society at pricescheaperthanthey would be if theywere producedby "proper"capitalists.This consequenceis elevated into a

functionparticularlyby K. Vergopoulosand by Alain de Janvry,for whom

peripheral apitalismdependson a reservoirof cheap labourand has no needfor the demandthat improvedincomes for labourersmight bringabout;this

labour,which can be drawnon seasonallyor cyclically, is reproducedby the

peasantsector at little or no cost to the capitaliststhemselvesor to the cap-italist state. In addition, it is claimed that the differencebetweenthe surplusthat would be transferred

y capitalistagricultural roducersand thatwhich is

actually transferredby peasant producersis something in the nature of a

"peasant" surplus(my term). This peasant surplusis different in origin but

similar in functionto the surplusvalue extracted from wage workers.' For

these writers, and indeed for Samir Amin, it is the hallmarkof peripheralcapitalism that it relies on these disarticulatedmechanisms, and on pre-

capitalistmechanismsof all kinds, to sustainits rhythmof accumulation.If it

reliedexclusively on wage labourandprofitto extractsurplusvalue it would

neithersurvive norfulfill its role in the worldcapitalistsystem. The othersdo

not pursuethe implicationsto quite such an all-embracinglevel, but theirview of the role of the peasantry n the economy is constructedon the ideaof

its cheapnessnonetheless. Abhijit Sen would say that the landlordbenefits

from the relativecheapnessof labourused undersharecropping.Liptonmain-

tains that small agriculturalproducersuse their labour very intensively to

extractunparallelledevels of productivity rom theirland andcapital,but he

does not attribute o this the cheapness of their productsor their labour;to

explain these he adduces discriminatory,misguided, or even perversestate

policies designed to extractmaximumresourcesfrom agriculture n general

for the ultimatebenefitof certain strataof urbanconsumers.He differs fromsuch as de Janvry or Vergopoulos (1978) in believing that both peasant

producersand the restof society wouldbenefit fromthe peasants'high yieldsif the state allowed them to do so, whereasde Janvrywouldclaim thatin the

logic of capitalist development peasantproducerswill use land and capitalmoreproductively hancapitalistsbutcannotexpectto obtaincorrespondinglyhigher incomes. Not merely "poor but efficient," as Theodore Schultz

(1964) would have hadthem, but "poor, efficient, andthereforeexploited";andeven here the wordefficientis somewhatmisusedbecause it is the inten-

sity of the use of land and capital, at the expense of a highly inefficient (ifmarketpriceswere applied)use of labour,which is being pinpointed.Lipton

ultimatelybelieves that a rational and benign state is at least in principlea

possibility, whereas the likes of de Janvry view the state as at best the

I For a critique,see HarrietFriedmann 1980) and David Lehmann(1982a).

Page 6: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 6/28

TWO PATHS OF AGRARIAN CAPITALISM 605

harbingerof an inevitably uneven capitalist development and at worst the

agentof the immediateinterests of the capitalistclass.

Amongthose who place themselvesexplicitly in the Marxist radition,whouse the Marxistvocabularyself-consciously and with much care, Utsa Pat-naikwould say that it is not so much the domestic characterof labouras the

conditionof massunemploymentwhich enables landlords o extracta supple-

mentaryor "precapitalist"rentfrom their tenants(1983). But she does not

pursuethe functionalistargumentas do de Janvryand Vergopoulos,and she

studiously, perhapsadvisedly, avoids the word peasant. Henry Bernstein,

writingfrom a moreorthodox Marxistperspectivethanmost, also avoids thefunctionalist

formulation,but in his account he

emphasisesthe

relationshipbetweenthe high productivityof land and capital among simple commodityproducers(read "peasant producers") and the logic of subsistence which

characterises heirproductionas opposedto the logic of surplusappropriationwhich characterises ull commodity production thatis, capitalistproducers).He also discusses the cheapnessof migrant abourandpeasant products,andstates that "the abilityof simplecommodity producers . . to produce n theface of deterioratingerms of exchange, means thatthey competeeffectivelywithcapitalistenterprisesproducing he same commodities" (1979:429). Al-

thoughhe seems to have decidedconsciouslynotto enter thediscussionaboutthe relative efficacy (let alone functionality)of this capacity for capitalistdevelopment, he does state that surplus value is transferred rom simplecommodityproducers o capital, forbetteror for worse. The Brazilianecono-mistGrazianoda Silva takes a similarpositionwhenhe states that there is nocontradictionbetween the claim thatcapitalismin certaincircumstances"re-

producespetty production"and the claim that it bringsaboutproletarianisa-tion: the former is part of the latterprocess, broadlyconstrued(1981:51).

Despite theirdifferences, it seems to me that there is an underlyingcom-

monideologicalelement in the writingsof de JanvryandVergopoulos,Bern-stein and Graziano da Silva. This element-as befits an ideological mo-ment-is the attemptto resolve a contradictionbetween the observation hat

peasantproducersarehighly productive(in terms of yields) and the assump-tionthatcapitalism s attherootof all poverty(if not all evil). Thisnotionthat

capitalismis at the root of poverty is not a traditionalMarxist one: on the

contrary,several antirevisionistwritershave recentlybeen at pains to tell us

(cf. Warren1980; Smith 1980), thatcapitalismis the source of most of thewealth we can observe in the world today. It is a notion which originatesin

PaulBaranandreceived its headline-hitting ormulation rom A. G. Frank nthe mid-1960s. Now, having admittedthat peasant producersare very pro-ductive andyet thatthey remainextremelypoor, the heirs to Frank'straditionhad to find some systemic, structuralmechanism in the capitalist systemwhich-operating in a law-like manner akin to the law of surplusvalue-would explain this. For this they turnedto Chayanov.

Page 7: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 7/28

606 DAVID LEHMANN

II. THE CAPITALISED FAMILY FARM AS A WAY THROUGH THE

CHINESE WALL

The outcome is the idea of a Chinese Wall that will totally preventpeasantproducers rom becomingcapitalists.The assumedmechanismshere are de-rivedfromChayanovanddependencytheoryin proportionshat,thoughtheymay vary, will always leave a taste of an ill-conceived cocktail. From

Chayanov s derived the concept that a peasantfarmproducesonly up to the

pointwhere the extra unitof drudgery s not worthwhilewhen set againstthe

correspondingreduction in the distance between the producer'sfamily andtheir desired level of consumption. The implicationof this is that peasant

producerswill accumulatecapital only if they get a windfall. Inotherwords,in normaltimes, they are not interestedin such things. From dependencytheoryis derived the idea that the state is controlledby interests which willensurethatprices-not to speakof thepoliticalsystemandthebureaucracy-areconsistentlyunfavourableo peasantproducersand thattherefore hey willnot have the slightestchance of reaching arbeyondtheirdesiredconsumptionlevel even at the best of times. Thus their high-yielding labours will be

exploitedto the full by a treadmillmanipulatedby therulingcapitalistclasses.And just as dependenciahas difficulty accommodatinga dynamic class of

indigenouscapitalists(preferringo describe them as a congeriesof parasitesbaskingin the protectiveshadeof the state) so this intersectoralversion has

difficulty in accommodating he realityof farms that areclearly capitalistin

their marketbehaviouryet employ hardly any wage labour,andcertainlyno

permanentabour,outsidethe nuclear amily. In the LatinAmerican iterature

they are variously described as unidadesfamiliares capitalizadas, novo camp-

ones, or, in Spanglish,farmers.They are seen as an anomaly.In this article I

develop a theorythat tries to dispel this anomalous status.

In an articlepublishedin 1982 I elaborateduponthe idea of a capitalised

familyfarm as a typeof productiveunitwhich is capitalistbutuses little hiredwage labour romoutside the household.In thisI was not alone. Otherarticles

and books (such as the study by David Goodman and Michael Redclift

(1981)) writtenat about the same time, and whose authorsclearlysaw them-

selves as bearersof a Marxistor at least a Marxisant tradition,were also

developingsimilartheories,usuallyembellishedwith a ritualreverence n thedirectionof remarksby Leninabout the UnitedStates. Little didwe know thatwe would have done best merelyto 'rediscover" andredisseminatea once-classic article by John Brewster that the Journal of Farm Economics

published n 1950, entitled "Machine Process in Agricultureand Industry."Inthatessay Brewsterexplainswhy mechanisationn agricultureeads to the

preservation f family units (of production)-an argument hat contrastsboth

withthe "Leninist" predictionof theirultimatedemise (allowing, it must be

said, that it may arriveonly in the very very long run)and with the expecta-

Page 8: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 8/28

TWO PATHS OF AGRARIAN CAPITALISM 607

tion of perpetualsurvivalwith perpetually ow-level technologies and livingstandards hat we find in the work of Chayanov'sMarxisant successors.

Brewster'sargument s rootedin a simpleobservation: hatboth before andafter mechanisationfarm operationsare widely separatedby time intervals

irredeemably mposed by biology and climate. In agriculture,he says, tech-

nological advance does not acceleratethe functionaldivision of labour and

specialisation, since operationsare not concurrentas they are in industry.Rather, t allows a familyto reduceits hiringof wage labour. So long as farms

specialise as single enterprisesrather than diversifying, and thereby hold

supervision requirements n check, mechanisationmilitatesagainst the pro-cesses we now call

proletarianisation.In my 1982 article I suggest that the capitalisttransition n agriculture n

today's low- andmiddle-incomecountriesfollows two mainpaths:"both the

dominance of capitalizedfamily farms and the 'involuted' dualisticpatternare possible in long-settled areas where peasantriessurvive" (1982a:158).The word involuted s usedto refer to areas wherelarge-andsmall-scaleunits

of productioncontinue to coexist conflictively, with a modernisationof the

formeranda rapidproliferationof the latter.The termcapitalised amilyfarmis used to refer to units in which capital is used far more than the popular

imageof a peasantfarm would lead one to expect, and labour s hiredonly insmall quantitiesor for brief but intense periods such as harvest, much as

Brewster would have it. The article is essentially speculative, drawing on

strands n the literature o develop an hypothesisabout the rangeof possible

patternsof agrarianstructure hat might develop as capitalismadvances in

agrariansocieties. It is also an attemptto break out of a methodologicalstraightjacketwhich has recentlybeen well describedby David Booth(1985):where muchpreviousliterature especially thatwhichplaced itself broadly n

the Marxisttradition)had been strugglingunderthe weight of the idea that a

theory was worthwhileonly if it was a theory about the inevitable,2 it ex-pressly outlined two possible polar paths of agrariancapitalism, with the

implication hattherewas a rangeof possibilitiesbetween the two poles. It did

notattempt o define thepriorhistoricaland structural onditions underwhich

one or the other path might occur. The present essay pursuesand developsthese ideas and, with the help of our observations n the Ecuadorianprovince

2 Inorder o satisfytherequirementhat the inevitableconsequenceof capitalistpenetrationna peasant economy was the emergence of two opposedpolarclasses, despite the observationof

proliferatingpeasant enterprisesin many poor and middle-incomecountries, authorscame toredefine migrationas a form of proletarianisation,and also to describe peasantproducersas

"wage-labourequivalents"or like terms(cf. Bernstein1979). These formulationshadmorethana grain of accuracy; migrantsdo become proletarians at least intermittently),and frequentlypeasantproducersare eitherpart-timewage labourersor subjectto variouscontrols over their useof theirlands. But to lump all these variationstogetheris to miss the opportunityof detectingvariations n processes of change and thus of explainingthe changes observed.

Page 9: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 9/28

608 DAVID LEHMANN

of Carchi,offers anaccountof some of the mechanisms hatcome intoplay inthe transition o an agrarian tructuredominatedby capitalisedfamily farms.

Before entering into detailed discussion it is important o note that thecontrastbetween the two pathscannot and must not be reducedto a contrastbetween peasant enterprisesand capitalised family farms at the enterpriselevel. It is a contrastbetween agrarianstructuresand the dynamicforces of

changewithin them-conditioned to varyingdegreesby the politicalecono-

my of the larger society and of the world system. The contrastingagrarianstructuresare characterised s dominatedby modernisedestates (in the invo-

lutedpath)andcapitalisedfamily farms(in the pathwhich bears thatname),but there is no reason

why peasant producersor

capitalised familyfarm

producersshould not be present in both. A distinction is therefore drawnbetweenpresenceanddominance,and between agrarian tructuresand unitsof production-the agrarian tructurebeing defined as a particular ombina-tion of type of class structureand the inner workings of productionunitswithin a region.

III. LABOUR RECRUITMENT AND CONTROL ON PEASANT FARMS AND

ON CAPITALISED FAMILY FARMS

The capitalisedfamily farm(CFF) is a unit of production hat, like the com-monly held stereotypeof a peasantfarm, relies principallyon kinshipties in

the recruitment f labour,butunlikethatsame stereotype,also uses fixed and

variablecapitalin accordancewith its endowmentsand with the opportunitiesoffered by the market. Whereasthe common view, accurate or not, is that

peasant armsrarelyhirewage labourbecause it is not "in their nature"to do

so, I argue, with reference to the CFF, that it does without wage labour

because of the cost and that it invests in capital if necessary. The CFF

therefore akesfully into account the marketcost of the labour t does nothire

andmakesa capitalist profiteven withouthiring any wage labour. It recruitsprimarilynot so much from among a network of kin but from within the

nuclear amily, whereasthepeasantfarm recruits rom bothand,even when it

pays wages, recruits hrougha (wider)networkof primaryrelationships.We

therefore have a series of contrasts that confound common stereotypes:a

family farm which is clearly capitalistbut recruitshardly any wage labour,and a peasant farm which is perhapsnot capitalist, yet which may recruit

wage labour, doing so throughthe kinship network ratherthan the openmarket.The only commondividing factor thatcombinesand separates hese

featurescorrectly and resolves the anomaly previously alluded to, is theirinsertion n the labour market: hey seem to operatein differentsegmentsof

the labourmarket.Whether heone orthe otheris definitively capitalistor notis academic;bothcan be taken to exist in societies where the capitalistmode

of productionprevails.The crucial feature that distinguishes peasant producersis that they are

Page 10: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 10/28

TWO PATHS OF AGRARIAN CAPITALISM 609

morelikely to recruit abouramong groupsand forperiodsnot availableto the

labour market as a whole: women able and preparedto spend half a day

working for a kinsman, but not longer, and not for an unknown person;childrenwho spendtheirmornings n school;fellow farmerswho haveanodd

day or two to spare.The labourretainsits family characterbecause, whether

or not a wage is paid, the labourersare recruited hroughthe activationof a

range of primaryrelationshipsthat are usually either kinship ties or ritual

kinship relationshipssuch as compadrazgo.The terms amily andhousehold

should not be misunderstood.To Westernears, and certainlyto the Russian

writersof the turnof the centurywho fathered he theoryof peasanteconomy

andthe conceptof

a peasantfamily economy,these meana nuclear

familyor

at least a groupof people closely relatedto each other, living underthe same

roof and eating out of the same pot. From this stems the triple preconcep-tion-that the familyfarm(or "labourfarm" in Chayanov'susage)uses only

family labour,that family labour must come from this "one-pot, one-roof"

social unit, and that it cannot be paid in money (cf. Shanin 1973-74).Theseconsequencesneed notfollow; only a highlyethnocentricconceptof

family would restrict the categories of people covered by the termfamilylabourto the membersof the nuclear amily, andonly anequallyethnocentric

concept would presumethat family members are unpaid(in wages-profitshares or productsharesapart).The analyticallysignificant pointaboutthese

relationships,which indeed has not passed unnoticedby many followers of

Chayanovand othersinfluencedby him-from neoclassicaleconomists like

Lipton (1977) to Marxists or Marxisants like Vergopoulos (1978) and de

Janvry 1982) and others like AmartyaSen (1966)-is theireffect on thepriceof labour,namely, to cheapenit, explicitly or implicitly.

The authorsmentioned above makevarious claims: (1) that since the pro-ductive unitpays no money wages it has no labourcosts (Chayanov),(2) that

since it employs family labourit has lower labour costs thancapitalistunits(deJanvry, Vergopoulos),(3) that it has low labourcosts becauseit exists in a

sea of unemployment,and indeed survivesbecause it providesthe last mini-

mally secure refuge against that unemployment (AmartyaSen). The com-

monly held but never explicit assumption underlyingthese theories is that

people work for low wages or low returnswithin the family or householdeitherbecausethey love their families-which they often don't-or because

they automaticallyobey their fathersand husbands-also subjectat least todoubt. My claim is that the labouris cheaperon a peasantfarm than on a

capitalistfarm because peasant producershave access to those partsof thelabourmarket that others cannot reach, because it can employ people for

"peculiar"periods,becauseit uses kinshipandparakinshipies, in particularties of patronageandpersonal dependency,to keep the costs of labourdown.It follows from this, and in the light of Abhijit Sen's (1981) account of

sharecroppingand marketfailure, that landlordsand capitalistfarmerswill

Page 11: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 11/28

6IO DAVID LEHMANN

take advantageof these characteristics hrougha rangeof tenancyand sub-

contractingarrangementswith peasant producers.This image of a peasantfarm s basedon a more concrete and realistictheoryof "peasantmotivation"thanthat which underliesthe models of Chayanovand his followers. Theirtheoriesdependon notions which we tend to accept only becausethey ascribeto peasant producersand their families the motivation that Western ide-

ology-not Westernreality-ascribes to families in industrial ocieties. The

ironyis compoundedwhen we recall that these ideasoriginatewith populistshostile to, or distrustfulof, the consequencesof industrialisation.

It follows frommy view thatin peasantsocieties (a term used here to referto those societies which observerswould

intuitivelydescribe as such, rather

than to any rigorously defined groups) producersdo not necessarily relyexclusively on kin for labour,and certainlynot on close kin, and that evenwhenthey do recruitkin they maywell paythem a wage. But this does notbyanymeansexcludethe possibilitythat the recruitment f labour hrough heseties makes it cheaperto employ thanlabourrecruitedon the open market,ifsuch exists. The activationof kinshipties in the recruitment f labourmakeslabourcheaper in the short run for this purchaser han it would be for an

impersonalcapitalist operatinga small unit with no links to the networkof

relationships n which the workers move.The two provisos-the "short" run and the "small" unit-reveal key

aspectsof theargumentaboutcheaplabour.Althoughcheapin the shortterm,the labourpurchasedmayprovemoreexpensivethan it appearsat firstsight if

in the long runit involves the purchasern a web of costly or time-consumingcommitments o return avours or to dispensepatronage.The small size of the

unit is relevantbecauseit is on smallunits in particularhatlabour s requiredin small andirregularquantities,and it is preciselythese sortsof requirementsthat can be fulfilled (withoutincurring he excessive costs usuallyassociated

withsmalltransactions)by the activationof primaryoyaltiessuch as kinship,as mentionedat thebeginningof this section. Theownerormanagerof a largeunit would have little use for the dribs and drabsof labourtime thata small

unitneeds. Such a personmightwell find a bevy of hangers-onsomethingof

an irritation-though it is worthrecallinghow the movie moguls of Holly-wood's GoldenAge littered heirpayrollswith relativesnearand far. Evenso,the contention thatpeasant producersobtain labour at cheaperaverageunit

costs thancapitalistproducers,and thatthis is due to their access to a web of

primary oyalties (which is partof the definition of a peasant producer)re-

mains. Whether t follows from this that the smallerunit is actuallytherebytransferringurplusout to the rest of society, or to particularocial classes, is

extremelydebatable,since the relativelylow productivityof this labourmust

be takeninto account in makingsuch claims.

Inevitablythe small size of the unit has enteredinto the definition of the

peasantproduceror productionunit. At first sight this is unsatisfactory, or it

Page 12: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 12/28

Page 13: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 13/28

612 DAVID LEHMANN

family relationshipsmay be reinforcedby differentpatternsof capitalistde-

velopment in agriculture.In the involuted path, the mechanisms of labour

recruitmentust outlined may be reinforced, as Rodrigo Sanchez has elo-quently argued (1982), while in the capitalised family farm, those rela-

tionshipsconventionallyassociated with precapitalist amily farms-by, for

example, Shanin (1973-74)-are not only reinforced but also operate as

dynamicfactorsin the emergenceof capitalisedfarming.

IV. STRUCTURAL CONCOMITANTS OF THE INVOLUTED PATH:

PATTERNS OF MIGRATION AND LABOUR CONTROL

Theinvolutedpathis one in whichsmall-scale unitsproliferatewhile the largeunitspreserve heir dominantposition.They preserve t even though they alsoreducetheiraveragesize, shedding marginal andby distributingt to former

employeesor selling it off; theyeven preservetheirdominancewhen convert-ed fromlandlord'sestates to peasant-run o-operatives.Inaddition,theyraisetheircapital-labouratios often with the supportof cheap public-sectorcredit.The largeunits also tend to choose lines of production hat demand the least

labour,above all, permanent abour. Seasonal labouris drawn from neigh-

bouringor distantsmallholdingareas. Correspondingly, he labour force in

neighbouringsmallholdingareas faces poorlocal

opportunitiesfor

regularemploymentbut intense demandfor their labour at seasonalpeaks.3With this patterngoes a concomitant patternof migrationto cities, to

frontierareas,or to otherruralareas.Comingfromrelativelypoverty-strickenareas,migrants rom these involutedregions will often be too poorto gain asecure foothold in the city or to establish themselves as independent armersin frontierareas.Migration,it should be recalled, is not a cheap optionopento anyoneirrespectiveof means. The poorestoften dependon labourcontrac-tors to pay even theirfares (on credit)from theirvillages of origin, in which

case they migrate only seasonally and to work in periods of peak labourdemand on plantations; f they go to a city, migrantsfrom areas where the

involutedpath has dominated-such as Riobambain the highlandsof Ec-

uadorsouth of Quito(Burgos 1977)-tend to work in the extremelyinsecure

construction ndustryor in domestic service. The difficulty of obtainingse-

cureemploymentdeters them from selling their land, the small security theycan fall back on. Thus land markets tend to freeze and intergenerationaltransfersexacerbatefragmentationand subdivisionof holdings.

Migration o frontierareasis hardlya realistic alternative or people from

theseinvolutedareas. Theprospectof selling their landsto go andseek othersin frontierareas must seem daunting, especially in the light of the risks and

3 Examples of the involuted path include the northeastof Brazil (Lehmann 1982), the

CayambeValley of northernEcuador(see text below for furtherdetails), the Departmentof

Cajamarca n northern Peru (Taylor 1979); the southernhighlands of Peru (Figueroa 1982;Sanchez 1982).

Page 14: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 14/28

TWO PATHS OF AGRARIAN CAPITALISM 613

costs involved in the migrationprocessitself: the hiringof a lorryto transport

people and possessions and the dangersof bandits, thieves, and confidence

tricksters,all dissuade the very poorfrom such an adventure.This can be wellillustratedrom the BrazilianAmazonregion. Migrantsmovingto thatregionfrom the south sell their southernland, hire a vast lorry (pau-de-arara, or

parrot'sperch),andgo to a placewherethey have contacts and some expecta-tion of a piece of land far bigger than the one they have sold. These peopleoften even make an exploratory ripbefore finally setting off, somethingthe

poorsmallholdercould rarelyaffordto do. In contrast,the poorand landless

tend to migratealone, without families, in busloads, in searchof whatever

employment they can obtain. These featuresof Brazilianmigrationto the

frontier ndicatethe differentiatednatureof migrantexperience.The study by

WayneCornelius(1978) of migration romvillages in theregionof Jalisco, in

Mexico, to the United Statesoffers a striking llustrationof the importanceofthecosts of migration n determiningwho can migrateand underwhatcondi-

tions;it shows that these costs areso high-ranging as theydo fromtransportfees to bribes for frontier officials and paymentsto helpersor smugglers-that only the upperstrataof the villages can afford it. Poorervillagers no

doubt also migrate, but to less distant, and less lucrative,places andjobs.Outward

migrationrom involuted

areas, then,is a more

periodic,seasonal

affairthanelsewhere, andthereis also more returnmigration han one might

expect from the jeremiads about ruralpoverty provoking excessive urban

growth.A recentstudyof southernPeruby DanielCotlear(1984) emphasisesthe relationshipbetweenthe insecurerightsoffered by communaltenure and

both the impermanentnatureof migrationand the phenomenonof return

migration.My interpretations that it is the involutedcharacterof agricultural

development n the regionwhich offers the explanation,andthat the commu-

naltenure s butanepiphenomenon.Cotlearexplainsthereturnof migrants o

theirvillages by referenceto the insecurityof their inheritance;my claim isthat this would not matter o them if they had a secureurbanbase, given the

usually paltryamountsof land involved. The persistenceof communalten-

ure-with all the insecuritywhich it implies and which Cotlearrightly4em-

4 This is importantbecauseof the layersof ideologicalobfuscation hatsurround heuse of thetermcomunidad. To manypeople of variedpolitical persuasions t evokes an imageof securityandarcadian ogethernessandsolidarity.Inparticular, here is a very widely held belief thatthisinstitutionprotects rights in land. Yet we know that the institutionwas created by the Incacolonialstate, and laterre-created n the sameimageby thatstate'sSpanishsuccessor, in thispartof the world, as a basis for the provisionof tribute abour.Furthermore,he role of the chiefs ofthese base institutionshas always been subjectto the conflictingpressuresof a state-which co-opts them-and a communityof people who press themto defendtheir lands. The latterdo not

always win out (cf. Spalding 1973; Murra1977; Sempat 1982; and Sanchez-Albornoz1978).This line of analysisof indigenouscommunities,emphasisingtheroleof theirleadersas agentsofthe state and the internalconflict they contain, has been pursuedwith some vigour by Samuel

Popkinagainstthe purported omanticismof certaininterpretationsf Vietnameserevolutionarynationalism 1981) andagainstJames C. Scott's conceptof the "moraleconomy" of the peasant

Page 15: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 15/28

614 DAVID LEHMANN

phasises-is itself a consequenceorconcomitantof thepersistentcoexistenceof largeestates and areasof tiny peasant holdings. The fact thatan agrarianreform has transferredownership of those estates to peasant co-operativesseems to make no difference. Cotlear's evidence, therefore,provides some

supportfor the idea that an involutedpatternof development goes togetherwith nonpermanentmigration.This patternmay follow an annual, seasonal

cycle or a morelong-drawn-outone stretchingover an individual's life span.Migration rom areas where the involutedpathprevails, then, tends to be

more seasonal, more intermittent, han migrationfrom the countrysideas awhole. It tends to stimulate ratherthan stem the proliferationof smallhold-

ings, intensifyingrather han

relievingthe

pressureson the land

preciselyin

the areas where unequaldistribution s most acute and where thereforethat

pressurehas the most seriousconsequences.Under these conditions of involution, "peasant" practices in labourre-

cruitmentandcontrol,far fromdecliningunder he impactof capitalistdevel-

opment,maywell increase,as richpeasants akeadvantageof networksundertheir control to hire from the pool of underemployed abour. Involutionis

accentuated,as the estates develop their productiveforces and the richer

smallholders ind thatthey can expandproductionby recourseto the recruit-

ment of labourvia primaryrelationshipsrather hanby capitalinvestmentorincreasingcapital-labour atios.One frequentlyobserved featureof these rich peasant enterprises s their

involvement n a diversityof productmarkets:n agriculture, n dairyproduc-tion, in cattle breedingor fattening, in trade, in transport cf. Smith 1984).

They use networks of contacts and deals, and their economic activity is

markedby a seamless web of pay-offs and favours. They do not build up a

centrallymanagedbusiness with a clear objectiveof extractinga returnon a

given amountof capital.They maystrike t rich,butalwaysin the contextof a

networkof primaryrelationships hatmobilize both capital (throughvariousformsof sharecropping, haretrucking, harefishing,or short-term redit)and

labour (through their access to the peasant labour market.) Theirs is a

bricoleurcapitalism,but its peculiarcharacterarisesfromtheiraccess to the

peasant abourmarketrather han froma peculiar"rationality"different rom

that of any othercapitalist. (If they had a differentrationalityor logic would

they even so be human?)The temptation acing those writingaboutpeasanteconomies is to search

for a criticaldistinctionbetweenpeasantenterprisesandcapitalistenterprises

in terms of an immanentcharacteristicof what is sometimes called theirrationalityor their mode of calculation.This poses serious difficulties if onlybecause the taskof identifyingthe differentrationalitiesof individuals s both

dauntingand most likely impossible. Such a distinction can never offer a

(1976). Not that Popkin's rampantindividualism offers the solution to all these problemseither. ...

Page 16: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 16/28

TWO PATHS OF AGRARIAN CAPITALISM 6I5

reasonablemethod of classifying units of productionbecause it excludes a

priori hepossibilitythatout of a peasantsociety theremightemergecapitalistfarmers. Thus wherever rich peasants or small capitalists arise confusionabounds.In this essay a solution is adoptedwhich some mightlabel evasive:the distinctionbeing drawnis between types of agrarianstructureand rural

labourmarkets,not betweenenterprises.Thus the bricoleurcapitalismof rich

peasants s a featureof regionswith particular tructuresandmarkets,and is

not linkedto any immanentfeaturesof the producers hemselves.

V. STRUCTURAL CONCOMITANTS OF TH-E RISE OF CAPITALISED

FAMILY FARMS

There is little hope for the capitalisedfamily farm if the greatestates retain

their dominantposition; they must therefore enter into or be pushed into a

periodof decline, eitherby their internalcollapse or by an agrarianreform.Our researchin the Ecuadorianprovince of Carchi revealed an unexpected

process of this kind, for what is interestingand instructive about Carchi's

recenthistoryis that,when contrastedwith betterknownand morepublicisedagrarian eforms,the regionillustrates he consequencesof a redistribution fland in which the official apparatuschargedwith implementationof the re-

formplayed an indirect noninterventionist ole.The great estates of the province have essentially disintegratedunder the

weight of their own internal inanition. The whole highland region of the

provincealongthe callejo6 andino(Andean corridor)was once dominatedbythe HaciendaEl Vicundo, said to be the largestestate in Ecuador,but it was

dismembered n the 1930s. This dismembermentoccurredundertwo sets of

pressures,the death of an owner who left no direct heirs and the pressuresexerted by a local group, few of whom seem to have been in any sense

"indians," who claimedthat a portionof the estate's landsactually belonged

to an indigenouscommunity. Manyof those involved wereprobablymigrantsfrom over the border in Colombia. The pressureon the hacienda was in-

creasedby the interventionof thegovernment-at thattimerunby a reformist

militarygroup-itself pressedby people from the area.Finally,a largestretchof high, forested land was sold to a groupof purchasersat a cheap price andon concessionary terms. This was to become the Colonia Huaquena, re-nownedfor its potato production.At the time, the landseemed to be worth-

less, but when it was eventually cleared and planted, and above all whenfertilizerswere introduced n the 1950s, it turnedout to be extremelyfertile

andespecially suitablefor potato production.In Carchiprovinceas a whole,potatooutputhas multipliedseventeen times between 1961 and 1980, and theharvest of broad beans five times. During the 1960s and 1970s potatoesbecamealmost a monocropin the area, while barleyand wheat faded away,leaving only dairy cattle to compete with the tuberfor land. By 1980 even

very small producersreckoned to spend some U.S.$1,500 per hectare of

potato production in labour, chemical fertilizers, and (much abused)

Page 17: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 17/28

6I6 DAVID LEHMANN

pesticides. The potatohas, withoutdoubt, providedthe base for the rise and

expansion of a stratumof middling farmerswho now have displaced the

hacendadofamilies fromtheirpositionsof dominance n theprovince'shigh-landareas and can therefore no longer strictlybe called middling.

Anothersourceof pressureon the estatescame from theprospect,and laterthe reality, of agrarianreform in the early 1960s. Unlike the landlords of

Riobamba,who resisted or gave up only reluctantly,those in the northern

highlandsof the countryeitheractively co-operatedor took pre-emptiveac-tion. In the area of Cayambe, which lies between Carchi and Quito in thesame provinceas Quito, landownerswere quick to accept the reform,handover

marginalplotsto their

huasipungueros,or

dependentlabourers,and

concentrateand modernise their activities on dairy farming on the valleybottom. They in effect created a model of the involutedpath, and the pur-portedbeneficiaries of the reform have suffered as might be expected. Thebeneficiarieswere not helped by the government'srepressivemanipulation fthe reformin that area after the stirringsof unionismorganizedin the 1950s

by the CommunistParty(Salamea 1980). In Carchi,still further o the north,thegrass-rootspressurecame from what one mightcall the petitebourgeoisieof the townships, not from the dependentpeasantryon the estates. Artisans,

muleteers, barbers,carpenters,and even the supervisory employees of theestates themselves, both pressured he estates andoffered to pay for plots of

land. They obtained credit from banks for the purpose,and the owners, gladto be freed of the threat of government-imposedreform in a peaceful way,allowed easy repaymentterms. In some cases the owner was the Catholic

Church, in the shape of the local bishopric, or the Curia, as the peopledescribedit, which took a lead in making its land available to prospective

purchasers,though it was clearly not in the business of making outrightdonations. In other cases the owners were in any event losing interestin the

properties,buying elsewhere, or moving into professionalactivities in thecapitalcity, Quito. The outcome has been a redistribution f landfavourable

to the middlingfarmer-as our surveydatashow-but offeringvery little to

the formerhuasipungueros or whom the reformwas originallydesignedand

who have hardlyprotestedat all. The beneficiariesfirstorganizedthemselves

in co-operatives orthe purposeof buyingandpayingforthe land,butas soonas they had paid off the debt, or a sizeable portionthereof, they dividedthe

landinto private parcels, in which thereis now an active marketdespite the

often dubious legality of the title.5

5 This is the result of the unwillingness of the AgrarianReform Institute (charged with

implementinghe reform)to permitthe parcellisationof these lands. The initialdistributionwasto a cooperativebecause thisenabledpurchasers o obtaincertainexemptionsand also speededuptheprocedures.Unfortunately, t also restricts he purchasers' reedomof manoeuvre omewhat,but invariably hey proceedregardless,andthereare, as far as we could see, no disputesamongthemaboutlegal aspects of land tenure.

Page 18: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 18/28

TWO PATHS OF AGRARIAN CAPITALISM 617

Oursurveycovered two areas,one theparishof Huaca,the otherEl Angel,comprisingthe parishes of San Isidro and La Libertad.The disintegrationfromwithin of the greatHaciendaEl Vicundo had its impactin Huaca,whilethe agrarian eform had its impactin El Angel at a laterdate. Our datafromthe cadastreshow thatbetween 1920 and 1980 the categoryof medium-size6

holdingsrose from 32.7 percentto 41.6 percentof units in the two parishesnear El Angel, that this category's sharein the total value of unitsrose from21.5 percent o 37.6 percent.Inthatperiod,theabsolutenumberof largeunitsrose from thirteen to twenty-seven, but they fell from 4.4 percent to 3.0

percentof units, and their share of value droppedfrom 70.4 percentto 58.4

percent.In Huaca the data are not

quiteso

striking;in the

distribution,the

share of both units and value in the medium-sizecategoryremainedalmost

unchanged,while the small-sizecategory,which rose only from58.3 percentto 60.0 percentof units, increased its share of the land from 15.5 percentto20.0 percent.The share held by large-size farmshas remainedmore or lessconstantat about 1 percentof units and 20 percentof land. Althoughit mayappearthat Huaca has not changed at all, these figures probablymask amassiveturnoverwithinthe mediumcategory.The absenceof immiserizationcanbe gaugedby comparing heratioof theaveragevalue of smallunits to the

averagevalue of medium units in 1920 and in 1980. An averagemedium-sizeunitwas worth 18 times as much as a smallone in 1920, butonly 4.6 times asmuch in 1980. In El Angel, where the data on landdistribution howed the

emergenceof a middling stratum so well, the data on values show only asmallchange in ratios:the mediumunits were worth on average5.1 times asmuchas the small ones in 1920, and 6.6 times as much in 1980.

Thepressure rombelow in thisregionhasnot come fromthepoorestof the

poor. Indeed, there is some evidence that the petite bourgeoisie displacedindigenous communities from their lands, later to emerge as "peasants"

needing and fromthe agrarian eform!By theearly 1980s, ecologicaldeterio-rationwas beginningto tell, the result of massivedeforestationandexcessive

one-cropconcentrationduringthe previoustwo decades. Those who had themeansto do so were shiftingout of potatocultivationbecauseof its enormousand increasingrisks from blight, unsuitableweather,highly volatile productprices, and soaringlabour,fertilizer,andpesticidecosts. They were shiftinginto dairy farming, which requiredfar less labourand offered a secure in-come, benefitting rombothsubsidizedcredit for thepurchaseof cattle and an

officially fixed price for milk-though it may be a mistaketo regardthese

subsidies as a permanentarrangement.Obviously, most farmerswere not

6 For the sake of simplicity we divided the strataof landownersas follows: small-up to 5hectares, medium-5-100 hectares, large-more than 100 hectares. Although this divisionwould be too crude for detailed cross-section analyses (as in the sharecroppinganalysis inLehmann 1986) where a muchmorecomplex criterion s used), suchsimplicityis a virtue whencomparingdataof variablequalityacross a long time period.

Page 19: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 19/28

6I8 DAVID LEHMANN

going to establishcapital-intensivedairyfarms,but it seemed that the agrarianstructurewould be dominatedby this type of unit, and this expectation usti-fied the descriptionof Carchi as in transition o a structuredominatedby theCFF.

The contrastbetweenthis agrarian eformand thoseannouncedandappliedwith morebombast n Chile andPeru, or indeed the same legislationapplied

differentlyelsewhere in Ecuador,merits at least a passingcomment. InChile

and Peru the beneficiariesdid not purchasedirectly from the landlords; n-

stead, governments mposed compulsorypurchaseand then createdproduc-tionco-operativeson the expropriated states. Theirmotives were several: to

preservehe economies of scale attributed o theestates;to save on thecost of

delimitingand fencing in large numbersof smallholdings; o maintainsome

sort of political control;and perhapsto see that the benefits of reformwere

equallydistributedamongthe beneficiaries. In bothcases the economic per-formanceof the expropriatedunits was disappointing(Lehmann1974; Kay1982). In Perutheoverwhelmingmajorityof the ruralpoorwere smallholders

who were left out of the landredistribution lthough n Chile theydid benefit

from a massiveexpansionof credit, technicalassistance,and social mobiliza-

tion. The eventual, indirect-and, it must be said, much debated-political

consequences in Chile were nothingless than the destructionof electoral

politicsby a vengefulandthreatenedmilitaryand theirallies, while in Peruit

is not entirely fanciful to suggest thatSendero Luminoso,with all its indi-

genist integralism, s a consequenceof the attemptby the militaryto impose

technologicalandmanagerial hangeby bureaucraticmeansduring he period1968-75. Finally, when all is said and done, these reformshave led to the

expansion of the rural petite bourgeoisie-a result that could have been

achieved just as easily with less bombast, less political risk, and for that

matter ess risk to human life.

Clearlythereis no pathof development n which all of today's "peasants"canbecometomorrow's"farmers";proletarianisationoes occur in the tran-

sition to a CFF system, albeit in forms differentfrom those observed in the

involuted path, and the existence of an agrarianstructurewith relatively

egalitariandistributionof landduringa particularperioddoes not imply that

in the generationsand decades leading up to that time no producerswere

marginalized,or thatno families lost their land. If anything hecontrary s the

case; the disappearance f the peasantrymay be far more radical n this case

thanin the involutedpath. In thatpath, the processof proletarianisationwas

observed in the growing dependenceof independentpeasantproducersonincome fromwage labour.Althoughthey preserved ome of theirindependentstatus,theirunderlyingpositionwas more andmore akinto thatof purewagelabourers.In the rise of the CFF, the fate of many peasantproducers s more

drastic; hey lose their landcompletelybecausecompetitionmakesit impossi-ble for marginal producersto survive. There are two sides to a dynamic

Page 20: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 20/28

TWO PATHS OF AGRARIAN CAPITALISM 619

process-some prosper,while others are drivento the wall. In this case the

dynamismputs pressureon labour costs either directly or by reducingthe

periodbetween agriculturalcycles. This last forces the pace of mechaniza-tion, makingsurvival difficult and occasionally almost impossible for thosewho cannot affordadaptivenew technologies. A well-known case of this sortof process is thatof southernBrazil, especially the stateof Parana,where thecombined effect of frost and changing technologies has forced vast numbersof small coffee growers out of productionand indeed out of the region,sendingthem off to new areasin Amazoniaor to employment n the cities ofthe south(Lehmann 1982b:255-57). In the same regionthe establishmentofan annualcycle of soybean and wheat cultivation, with a rapidturnaround

betweenthe harvestof the one and the plantingof the other, has meantthatthose who cannot mechanize must sell out, because the turnarounds not

possible withoutmachinery.A second mechanism of proletarianisation,more violent, is the simple

expulsion by force of an autochthonouspopulationto make way for immi-

grantfarmers,as occurredin the ArgentineChaco between 1880 and 1911

(Carrera1981:242). There is some indicationof this in Carchi as well in the

disappearance f indigenouscommunal nstitutionsof land tenure n theearlydecades of this

century.VI. THE PROBLEM OF MOTIVATION IN FAMILY LABOUR: PERSONAL

DEPENDENCY AND PARTNERSHIP

As mentionedearlier, the CFF is a family farm in a much stricterand nar-

rower sense than is the peasant farm described above. It is a family farm

because it uses almost exclusively the labour of members of its owner's

nuclearfamily, and it is capitalistbecause it must deal with the priceof wagelabourandallocate resourcesaccordingly.But thereis more:where the peas-

ant household "socialises" commodity relations, the CFF commoditiseskinship relations. Where the one cheapens wage labourby persuadingthe

labourershatthey areperforminga serviceto a primarycommunityof which

theyform a part,the other retains oyaltyof the household membersby givingthem a quantifiablestake and proportionate ewards n a partnership.These

contrastingcharacteristicsare a concomitantof the different constraintsand

opportunitiesoffered by the agrarianstructureswithin which they exist.A strikingillustrationof the difference between areas where the CFF is

risingto a dominantpositionandthose where the involutedpatternprevailsis

to be found if we examine the usage of certain terms and the meaning ofcertainpracticesusually identified as peculiarlyAndean. We have seen howthe anthropologistsdescribe reciprocityin centraland southernPeru, and Ihave presentedan interpretation f that relationship n termsof its possibleinequalities.Needless to say, when we went to do our researchin the Ec-uadorianprovinceof Carchi we looked for these characteristicAndeanprac-

Page 21: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 21/28

620 DAVID LEHMANN

tises, andwe found an institutionknown as el diaprestado, borrowinga day'swork. This is a form of delayedandilliquid paymentfor a day's work, quitecommon in stereotypicalpeasanteconomies; but here it seemed to be ratherrare,and it did not seem to be embedded n a web of relationshipsof personaldependency.Third, it seemed that the advantage n the deal lay not with the

personwho delayedthe paymentof the day's work-since this usuallycon-stitutedonly a tiny proportion f his labourrequirements-but ratherwith theother person, who, by requestinga day's labour in paymentratherthan a

money wage, was securingfor himself a workerfor a date in the futurewhenthe labourmarketmightbe verytight. The readyacceptanceof a peon sent inlieu of the debtor himself--who

mightbe

busythat

day-illustratesthe

relativelyunimportantole of personaldependency n therelationship,as wellas its transitory haracter: nce the transactionhad been completedthat wasthe end of the story.

A similar contrastcan be found if we comparecommunal labour evies in

the Ecuadorianprovinceof Carchi with those describedfor Peru (see, for

example,Winder1978). InCarchithey are(confusingly)calledmink'a,whilein Peruthey are calledfaenas (literally, "tasks"). Now in Peru the impres-sion given is that underthe cover of comunidadorganisationa cliqueor cabal

of richerpeasantssucceed in havingwork carriedout which is of particularfnotexclusive benefitto themselves. An irrigation hannelhas to be cleanedor

built, a roadbuilt or repaired,or-above all-afiesta organisedwith all the

attendant itual and edible paraphernalia.The literature hows thatsuch ac-

tivities areof disproportionate,houghnot necessarilyexclusive, benefit to a

small minorityof comuneros(see, for example, the monographson various

communities n the ChancayValley, suchas Celestino 1972;Fuenzalidaet al.

1968;Grondin1978). InCarchi,in contrast,suchpublicworks areorganizednot by an independentcorporatecommunitybut by a cabildo, which is the

lowest rungof the administrativehierarchyof territorialunits into which thecountryis divided (ascending throughcantons, provinces, and the nation).The cabildo has no full-time officials. Its real effectiveness obviously varies

enormously,and it would be absurdto claim that its actions embody some

highidealof social equity. The crucialdifferencewithrespectto the Peruvian

model of a corporatecomunidad,of which there are plenty in Ecuadoras

well, is that it does not control land and only builds or repairs nstallations,such as roads or a church, which are clearly public goods. The cleaning of

irrigationditches or canals would be the business of the directbeneficiaries

andthecabildocertainlyhasnojurisdictionover land. Its activitiesaremostlyundertaken n conjunctionwith the state. Thus, if a small roadis to be built,the cabildo is committed to providingthe necessary labourfrom among itsmemberson a rotationbasis, while the stateprovidesthe materialsand ma-

chinery.Richerresidentsmightprovidea day's wage or some refreshmentn

lieu, but not necessarily. The practise in Carchi suggests that there is no

Page 22: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 22/28

TWO PATHS OF AGRARIAN CAPITALISM 621

necessary conflict between the fulfilment of an individual's obligation

througha paid workerand the public benefit of the works in question.7The instinctive reactionof most observers s to takean extremelydim view

of suchdeals-wage labourundermininghe solidarityof the communityandall that. But it is equally plausibleto arguethat the monetisationand relative

anonymityof such obligationsgoes some way to preventthe rich fromtaking

advantageof positions of authoritywithin the community to use for their

personalenrichment he work of the poor.Now this can hardly be a question of the difference between Peru and

Ecuadoras countriesor states. Innumerable ommunidatdesn Ecuadorareno

doubt in the hands of small cabalswho use them toget

workdone onprojectsof personal nterestas if they wereof publicbenefit.Theessentialpointis that

these comunidad institutions are privately appropriated bove all where the

involutedpathis sustained,whererelationshipsof personaldependency playan importantpartin labourrecruitmentand penetrateand sustainthe "pub-lic" facade of communalinstitutions.

As againstthe "personalisationof commercial relations" which we have

pointedto in peasanteconomies and in the involutedpath, Carchi exhibits

whatmightbe termed the commercialisationof family relationships.Against

the authoritarian nd arbitraryexercise of paternal authoritythat seems toprevail in the Chayanovianmodel of peasanteconomy, the pictureoffered

hereis of a family farm in which certaindevices exist to matchthe returns o

individualmembersagainsttheircontributions.The women not only milkthe

cows; they also retain controlover the income from sale of the milk. Whensons leave school they do not work for freeon their fathers'land; rather, hey

sharecropwith him. In such an arrangement here would be a lot of cost

sharing,and, according o ourdata,the contractsbetweenfathersandsonsdidnotexhibitany systematicdifferencesas compared o those betweennonkin.

These were not exploitative relationships n the sense commonlyconnotedbythe idea of sharecropping Lehmann 1986). A similar grasp of a capitalist

concept of equity is observablein inheritance.Women have equal rightsto

boththeirparents'property,as stipulatedby Ecuadorianegislation,but notas

practised n areasof Ecuadorwhere the involutedpathprevails,where womenare at a clear disadvantagein inheritance.Not only is a woman entitled to

acquireher equal share of her parents' property,she also, like her husband,

passes mostof it on to herchildren,not to herspouse, at herdeath,or earlierif she likes. Before the readergains the impressionthat this is some sort of

7 It may be relevant n this contextto note that the Ecuadorian abildo, as the lowest level ofterritorialadministrativeunit, is an institutionthat does have some status in law. unlike thePeruviancomunidades,each of which has its own idiosyncraticmodus operandi, land tenure

provisions, and rotation of offices. It is not, therefore, an autochthonous nstitution;but then

manywould questionwhether the comunidad s autochthonous n any meaningfulsense, havingbeen createdor shaped by the Inca and the Spanishto serve their needs for tributeandtaxes in arole akin to that of a subcontractor.

Page 23: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 23/28

622 DAVID LEHMANN

feministvalhalla,or that I believe it is, this image of equality, or at least of

matchingbargainingpower,needs to be

qualified,for once the CFF is

fullydeveloped, thingsmaychangefor its women. If, as is common in the Andes,

they have tended the cattle (and kept the revenue therefrom)in a mixed

agriculturaland dairyunit, they may lose their exclusive controlover thosecattle when theirspouses switch into specialised dairy production.The insid-ious bourgeoisfamily takes over.

A further llustrationof these contrasts s to be found in a paperby Lourdes

Arizpewhich comparesthe process of migration rom two Mexicanvillagesthatappear o fit roughlyouropposedcategoriesof involuted and CFFpaths.In

bothvillages migration s in some sense a familyaffair,butwhereas,in theone, the parentskeep a tightcontrol over the urbanactivitiesof theirchildrenand the incometherefrom,andbringthem back to the village to work on the

family holding when the season requires, in the other, migrantsuse familyconnections to set themselves up independently,though loosely connected

with their kin via urbancommercial networks(Arizpe 1981:119-44).

By emphasisingthe commercialisationof kin and otherpersonalor multi-

strandedrelations thatseem to be a featureof agrarian tructuresdominated

by the CFF, andprobablyalso a condition of a transition o such a structure,

do not mean to say thatthey do not employ wage labour. What counts in thecontrast with involuted structures s the mechanismof recruitmentof that

labour. In the transition to a CFF-dominatedstructure he mechanistnwill

become graduallymore anonymousand impersonaland less permeatedby

relationshipsof personaldependency.A CFF system must often have recourse to seasonalwage labourbrought

from other regions-especially from those where the involuted path pre-vails-because the cost of locally recruited labouris too high. This raises

intriguingquestions:the CFFsystem may well contribute o a preservation r

intensificationof the conditions of involutionin those regionsby strengthen-ing a stratumof rich peasantswho act as labourcontractors,and who maylend the workers some money for the trip and other expenses. By offeringseasonalincomescomplementary o those obtainedfrom subsistencecultiva-

tion it also perpetuatesthe existence of a class of semiproletarians.This

observation hows us how the two pathscanbe related o eachother,and neednot be analysedonly in terms of endogenous processes in the regions where

they exist.

VII. FACILITATING, BUT CRUCIAL, ELEMENTS IN THE RISE OF THECFF: MIGRATION AND SHARECROPPING

There are two mechanisms that seem to play a particularly interesting-andwithout doubt unexpected-role in facilitating the transition from landlord

domination o a CFF system:migrationand sharecropping. n contrast o the

patternof migrationdescribedearlierfor areas characterisedby the involuted

Page 24: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 24/28

TWO PATHS OF AGRARIAN CAPITALISM 623

path,the transition o a CFFsystemis facilitated f the migration romtheareais not only

quantitativelyhigh, but also qualitativelydifferent;it should be

permanent ather hantemporary,and it should be linkedwithupwardmobili-

ty, thus relieving pressureon the land market.A strikingfeatureof the datawe collected in Carchi is the contrastbetween the migrationpatternobservedthereand that describedearlier as characteristic f involuted areas. Ourstudyshows thatpeople from Carchihave a very strong propensityto migrateandalso that they tend not to return.We carriedout a survey of 100 owners of

land andinquiredabout the occupationof theiroffspring. Amongthe children

who lived elsewhere, almostexclusively in cities, the most frequentoccupa-tion was education:

theywere

attending secondaryschool in

Quitoor the

capital of the neighbouring province, Ibarra.This is not exceptional. The

poverty-strickencomunidadesof southern Peru also send children away to

study, beginningat primary-school evel, becauseof the inadequacyof local

provision.Butthechildrenwho are sent from thesecomunidadeshaveto earntheirway throughschool, by workingfor a relative, for example. The chil-dren fromCarchiare fortunate n the qualityof local primaryeducation,andthere is a very high rate of attendanceat that level (more than 70 percentof

childrenaged six to twelve attendschool); and when these childrengo to a

city to attendsecondaryschool theirparentspay their board and lodging, sothey have plenty of time to studyor, unfortunately, o dissipate. These chil-dren will not return to the countryside, nor are they expected to; on the

contrary,the secure establishmentof theiroffspringin an urbancalling is atremendous ource of prideforparents,andit is notonly the wealthywho are

prepared o spend vast sums to set their children on what they consider the

rightpath. When it comes to inheritance,these children will sell out to theheirs who have remained n the countryside. Obviously, this patternrelieves

pressureon the land. This outcome is favouredby a systemof land tenure hat

conforms to Ecuador'snational aws andnot to local custom, or to the manip-ulations of communityleaders as is often the case elsewhere. The system ofinheritancedecrees and obtains equal shares for male and female heirs andleaves to the parents hardly any say as to how their possessions will be

dispersedupondeath. This is importantbecause, as Sanchez's workshows forcertainpartsof Peru, and as might indeedbe learntfromthe agrarianhistoryof Ireland, nsecureor uncertain nheritanceprospectsdelay the age at whichthe next generationcan participate n the land market and make productiveinvestments.

The more transparent, ess opaque (Starobinski 1958) relationshipsbe-tween generations in Carchi are reflected in other more indirect and less

tangiblemechanismsof transmissionof wealth. As I try to show in anotherarticle(1986 forthcoming),sharecroppings a practise hatenables childrenoflandowners o participaten the land market ong beforeinheritingand, if theyareluckyandshrewd,to buildup substantialholdingsof land. One reason for

Page 25: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 25/28

624 DAVID LEHMANN

this is thatthey caneithersharecropwiththeir fathersor mothers,or theycan

sharecropwith others with the backingof theirparentsor other relatives. In

this way small- and medium-sized landownerscan rent land to these youngpeople, andeven advance the sharecroppers' hare of costs, without fear of

beingunableto recoupany losses. Ultimately,as oursurveyshows, inheritedland will makeup a tiny fraction of landowned by established farmers.I donot thinkthatthis would be the case in an area characterisedby the involuted

pathand its frozen land markets.

These sharecroppingarrangementsnvolve complex cost-sharingarrange-ments subject to negotiationand contractscovering one sowing only; theyinvolve

peopleof

roughlysimilar social

status,althoughhereis a

systematictendencyfor the ownerof the landto be betteroff than the sharecropper, ndthereis a systematic tendencyalso for those who rentin to be youngerthanthose who rent out. The conclusion from this analysis is that sharecroppingcan stimulate rather than impede commercialisation because cost-sharing

sharecroppingontractsrequirecareful calculationof inputcosts. Itmayevenbe that such practicesreinforcewhatone mightcall the capitalistcalculation

mentality(Lehmann 1986).In the final analysis, the question is whether these stories from Carchi

constituteanexception, the productof a rareandnonrepeatableoncatenationof circumstances,or whetherthey are an exampleof processesthat aregoingon in manyplacesbut that thepessimismwhich is frequentlya hallmarkof the

studyof developmenthas found it convenientto ignore. To say this is not to

denythat the involutedpath, with all its blockedchannels,exists; rather, t is

to express what some would regardas a naive faith in the entrepreneurial

capacitiesof poorruralproducers n poorcountries.It is also to say that the

fate of the peasantry s not merely dictated to them by the world capitalist

system or the exploiting classes and officialdom that run the countries in

whichthey live, but is also to some extent theirown creation.The problem sideological:if we areopposedto capitalismarewe thereforecommitted o the

view thatit impoverishesall of the poor, the saltof the earth?Are we thereby

precluded romallowingthe salt of the earthto becomecapitalists oo'?These

may, atone level, be ideologicalproblems,butwho is to say thatthe ideologi-cal attitudes hatunderlie our theoreticalpositionsare to be forever inscribedin tabletsof stone? That is why we do social research.

REFERENCES

Alberti,G., andMeyer, E. 1974. Reciprocidade intercambioen los Andesperuanos.Lima: nstituto e EstudiosPeruanos.Amin, Samir. 1976. Unequal Exchange. Hassocks, England:HarvesterPress.

Archetti, Eduardo,and Stolen, K-A. 1975. Explotaci6n amiliar y acumulaci6nde

capital en el campo argentino. Buenos Aires: Siglo XXI.

Arizpe,Lourdes. 1981. "Migraci6n porrelevos," in Economiacampesinay empleo,PREALC,d., 119-44. Santiago: REALC.

Page 26: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 26/28

TWO PATHS OF AGRARIAN CAPITALISM 625

Barsky,Osvaldo, andCosse, Gustavo. 1981. Tecnologiay cambio social: Las hacien-das lecheras del Ecuador. Quito:FLACSO.

Bernstein,Henry. 1979. "Concepts for the Analysis of ContemporaryPeasantries."Journalof Peasant Studies, 6:4, 421-44.

Booth, D. 1984. "Marxismand DevelopmentSociology: Interpretinghe Impasse."WorldDevelopment, 13:7 (July).

Brass,Tom. 1983. "AgrarianReformand the StruggleforLabourPower: A PeruvianCase Study." Journal of DevelopmentStudies, 19:3 (April), 368-89.

Brewster,John. 1950. "Machine Process in Agricultureand Industry."Journal ofFarm Economics, 32:162.

Burgos, H. 1977. Relaciones interetnicasen Riobamba. Mexico City: InstitutoIndi-

genista Interamericano.

Carrera,Nicolas

Inigo.1981. "El 'estado' en un

procesode creaci6n de condiciones

para la constituci6n de un sistema productivorural," in Economia campesina v

empleo, PREALC,ed. Santiago:PREALC.

Celestino,Olinda. 1972. Migraci6n y cambioestructural:La comunidadde Lampidn.Lima: Instituto de Estudios Peruanos.

Chayanov, A. V. 1967. The Theoryof Peasant Economy, D. Thorner,B. Kerblay,and R. E. F. Smith, eds. Homewood, Ill.: Irwin and Co.

Cornelius,Wayne. 1978. "Mexican Migrationto the United States:Causes, Conse-

quences, and U.S. Responses." Manuscript.Centerfor International tudies, Mas-sachusetts Instituteof Technology.

Cotlear, Daniel. 1984. "Desigualdad, derechos de propiedad y migraci6n en las

comunidadesandinas." Revista Andina, no.4, 435-75.Crispi, Jaime. 1984. "Nacimiento, vida pasi6n y. .. ? de un tipo de propiedad

familiar en Chile: Los parcelerosde la ReformaAgraria." Paper presentedto theconferenceon "Medium Farmers n LatinAmerica," Centre for Latin American

Studies, Cambridge.Figueroa,Adolfo. 1982. "ProductionandMarketExchange in PeasantEconomies,"

in Ecology and Exchange in the Andes, D. Lehmann,ed., 123-56. Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press.Fioravanti-Molinie,Antoinette. 1982. "Multi-levelled Andean Society and Market

Exchange: The Case of Yucay," in Ecology and Exchange in the Andes, D.

Lehmann,ed., 211-30. Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress.

Folbre, Nancy. 1985. "Cleaning House: New Perspectiveson Households and Eco-nomic Development." Paperpresentedto the conference on "New Directions in

DevelopmentTheory," MassachusettsInstituteof Technology, January.FonsecaMartel,Cesar. 1974. "Modalidadesde la mink'a," in Reciprocidade inter-

cambio en los Andesperuanos, G. Alberti and E. Mayer, eds. Lima: InstitutodeEstudios Peruanos.

Friedmann,Harriet. 1980. "HouseholdProductionand the NationalEconomy:Con-

cepts for the Analysis of AgrarianFormations." Journal of Peasant Studies, 7:2,158-84.

Fuenzalida,Fernando,et al. 1968. Estructuras radicionalesy economia de mercado:

La comunidadindigena de Huayopampa.Lima: Institutode Estudios Peruanos.Goodman,David, andRedclift, Michael. 1981. From Peasant to Proletarian. Oxford:Blackwell.

Grondin,Marcelo. 1978. "Peasant Cooperationand Dependency:The Case of the

Electricity Enterprisesof Muquiyauyo," in Peasant Cooperationand CapitalistExpansionin CentralPeru, N. Long and B. Roberts, eds., 99-128. Austin: In-stituteof Latin AmericanStudies, Universityof Texas.

Page 27: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 27/28

626 DAVID LEHMANN

de Janvry, Alain. 1981. The Agrarian Questionand Reformism n Latin America.Baltimore:Johns Hopkins UniversityPress.

Kay, Cristobal. 1982. "Achievements and Contradictionsof the PeruvianAgrarianReform." Journal of DevelopmentStudies, 18:2 (January),141-70.

Lehmann,David. 1974. "AgrarianReform in Chile:An Essay in Contradictions," n

AgrarianReformandAgrarianReformism,DavidLehmann,ed., 71-120. London:Faber and Faber.

. 1982a. "After Lenin and Chayanov." Journalof DevelopmentEconomics,no. 1.

.1982b. "Peasantisationand Proletarianisation n Brazil and Mexico," inRural Poverty and AgrarianReform, Steve Jones et al., eds. New Delhi: AlliedPublishers.

. 1986forthcoming. "Sharecropping

and theCapitalist

TransitioninAgri-culture: Some Evidence from Highland Ecuador." Journal of Development

Economics.

Lenin, V. 1. 1946 [1914-15]. "Capitalismand Agriculture n the UnitedStates," inhis Capitalismand Agriculture,9-56. New York:InternationalPublishers.

Lipton, Michael. 1974. "Towards a Theoryof Land Reform," in AgrarianReformand Agrarian Reformism, David Lehmann, ed., 269-315. London: Faber andFaber.

. 1977. WhyPoor People Stay Poor: Urban Bias in WorldDevelopment.London:Temple Smith.

Long, Norman,and Roberts, Bryan,eds. 1978. Peasant Cooperationand Capitalist

Expansion n CentralPeru. Austin: Institute or LatinAmericanStudies, Universityof Texas at Austin.. 1984. Miners, Peasants, and Entrepreneurs:Regional Developmentin the

CentralHighlands of Peru. Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress.

Mallon, Florencia. 1983. The Defense of Community n Peru's CentralHighlands:Peasant Struggleand CapitalistTransition.Princeton:PrincetonUniversityPress.

Marx, Karl. 1976 [1867]. Capital, Vol.1. Harmondsworth: enguinBooks.

Murra,John. 1975. Formaciones econ6micas y politicas del mundoandino. Lima:Institutode Estudios Peruanos.

Patnaik,Utsa. 1983. "ClassicalTheoryof Rentand ItsApplication o India." Journal

of PeasantStudies, 10:2,3 (special issue on sharecropping ndsharecroppers), 1-

84.Popkin,Samuel. 1981. TheRational Peasant: The Political EconomyofRuralSociety

in Vietnam.Los Angeles: Universityof CaliforniaPress.

Salamea,Lucia. 1980. "La transformaci6n e la hacienday los cambios en la condi-

ci6n campesina," in Ecuador: Cambiosen el agro serrano, FLACSO/CEPLAES,eds. Quito: FLACSO-CEPLAES.

Sanchez, Rodrigo. 1982. "The Andean Economic System and Capitalism," in

Ecology and Exchange in the Andes, D. Lehmann, ed., 157-90. Cambridge:CambridgeUniversity Press.

Sanchez-Albornoz,Nicolas. 1978. Indiosy tributosdel alto Peru. Lima:InstitutodeEstudios Peruanos.

Schultz, Theodore. 1964. TransformingTraditionalAgriculture.New Haven: Yale

University Press.Scott, James. 1976. The MoralEconomyof the Peasant. New Haven: Yale University

Press.

SempatAssadourian,Carlos. 1982. El sistema de la economia colonial. Lima: In-stitutode EstudiosPeruanos.

Sen, Abhijit. 1981. "Market Failure and Control of Labour Power: Towards an

Page 28: A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM  1986  (28 PP)

8/7/2019 A CRITIQUE OF CHAYANOVIAN MARXISM 1986 (28 PP)

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/a-critique-of-chayanovian-marxism-1986-28-pp 28/28

TWO PATHS OF AGRARIAN CAPITALISM 627

Explanationof 'Structure'andChangein IndianAgriculture."CambridgeJournal

of Economics (September),201-28.

Sen, Amartya. 1966. "Peasants and Dualism with or without Surplus Labour."Journalof Political Economy,74:425-50. Reprinted n his Resources, Values,and

Development(Oxford:Blackwell, 1985).Shanin, T. 1973-74. "The Nature and Logic of Peasant Economy." Journal of

Peasant Studies, 1:1, 63-80, and 1:2, 186-206.daSilva, Graziano.1981. Progreso tecnicoe rela(oes de trabalhona agricultura.Sao

Paulo: HUCITEC.Smith, G. A. 1984. "Confederationsof Households: ExtendedDomestic Enterprises

in City andCountry," in Miners,Peasants, and Entrepreneurs.RegionalDevelop-ment in the CentralHighlands of Peru, N. Long and B. Roberts, eds., 217-34.

Cambridge:Cambridge UniversityPress.

Smith, Sheila. 1980. "The Ideasof Samir Amin: Theoryor Tautology?"JournalofDevelopmentStudies, 17:1 (October), 5-21.

Spalding, Karen. 1973. "Kurakasand Commerce:A Chapterin the Evolution ofAndeanSociety." Hispanic AmericanHistoricalReview, 53:4 (November), 581-99.

Starobinski, Jean. Jean-Jacques Rousseau, la transparence et l'obstacle. Paris:P.U.F.

Taylor,Lewis. 1979. "MainTrends in AgrarianCapitalistDevelopment:Cajamarca,Peru, 1880-1976." Ph.D. diss., Universityof Liverpool.

Vergopoulos,K. 1978. "Capitalismand PeasantProductivity."Journal of Peasant

Studies, 5:4, 446-65.Wallerstein, Immanuel. 1984. The Politics of the World Economy. Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press.Warren,Bill. 1980. Imperialism,Pioneer of Capitalism.London:New Left Books.Winder,David. 1978. "The Impactof the 'Comunidad'on LocalDevelopment n the

MantaroValley," in Peasant Cooperationand Capitalist Expansion in CentralPeru, N. Long andB. Roberts,eds., 109-40. Austin: Institute or LatinAmericanStudies, Universityof Texas at Austin.