22 Cross-Cultural Forays: Commentary by Keith Oatley (Toronto)

download 22 Cross-Cultural Forays: Commentary by Keith Oatley (Toronto)

of 4

Transcript of 22 Cross-Cultural Forays: Commentary by Keith Oatley (Toronto)

  • 7/25/2019 22 Cross-Cultural Forays: Commentary by Keith Oatley (Toronto)

    1/4

    This article was downloaded by: [Gazi University]On: 19 August 2014, At: 08:03Publisher: RoutledgeInforma Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: MortimerHouse, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

    Neuropsychoanalysis: An Interdisciplinary Journalfor Psychoanalysis and the NeurosciencesPublication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rnpa20

    Cross-Cultural Forays: Commentary by Keith Oatley(Toronto)Keith Oatley

    a

    aDept. of Human Development & Applied Psychology, OISE-University of Toronto, 252

    Bloor Street West, Toronto, Canada M5S 1V6

    Published online: 09 Jan 2014.

    To cite this article:Keith Oatley (2000) Cross-Cultural Forays: Commentary by Keith Oatley (Toronto),Neuropsychoanalysis: An Interdisciplinary Journal for Psychoanalysis and the Neurosciences, 2:2, 238-240, DOI:

    10.1080/15294145.2000.10773314

    To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/15294145.2000.10773314

    PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

    Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the Content) containedin the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and our licensors make norepresentations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose ofthe Content. Any opinions and views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors,and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Content should not be reliedupon and should be independently verified with primary sources of information. Taylor and Francis shallnot be liable for any losses, actions, claims, proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and otherliabilities whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to orarising out of the use of the Content.

    This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematicreproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in anyform to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions

    http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/15294145.2000.10773314http://www.tandfonline.com/action/showCitFormats?doi=10.1080/15294145.2000.10773314http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditionshttp://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditionshttp://dx.doi.org/10.1080/15294145.2000.10773314http://www.tandfonline.com/action/showCitFormats?doi=10.1080/15294145.2000.10773314http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rnpa20
  • 7/25/2019 22 Cross-Cultural Forays: Commentary by Keith Oatley (Toronto)

    2/4

    238

    Cooper, A. M. 1991), Evaluation of the 37th IPACongress.

    Final overview paper. Buenos Aires, August 2

    Edelman, G. E. 1992),

    Bright Air Brilliant Fire. On the

    Matter

    of

    the Mind. New York: Basic Books.

    Erdely, M.

    H

    1985), Psychoanalysis: Freud s Cognitive

    Psychology. New York: Freeman.

    Erdheim, M. 1992}; Spatadoleszenz und Kultur. In: Phan

    tasic und Realitat in der Spatadoleszenz

    ed. M. Leu

    zinger-Bohleber

    E. Mahler. Opladen: Westdeutscher

    Verlag, pp. 129-142.

    Fischer, S., Greenberg, R. P., Eds. 1978),

    The Scientific

    Evaluation

    of

    Freud s Theories and Therapy: A Book

    of

    Readings.

    Hassocks, U.K.: Harvester.

    Green, A 1999), The greening of psychoanalysis: Andre

    Green in dialogues with Gregorio Kohon. In:

    The Dead

    Mother: The Work of ndreGreen

    ed. G. Kohon. Lon

    don: The New Library

    of

    Psychoanalysis.

    Habermas, J 1968),

    Erkenntnis und Interesse.

    Frankfurt

    am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Hampe, M., Lotter, M., Eds. 2000): Die Erfahrungen, die

    wir machen, sprechen gegen die Erfahrungen, die wir

    haben. Uber

    Formen

    der Erfahrung in den Wissenschaf

    ten., Berlin: Duncker Humblot.

    Kline, P. 1972),

    Fact and Fantasy in Freudian Theory.

    London: Methuen.

    Lear,

    J

    1995), The shrink is in.

    New Republic 25:18-25.

    Leuschner, W., Hau, S., Brech, E.,

    Volk, S 1994), Dis

    sociation and reassociation of subliminally induced stim

    ulus material in drawings of dreams and drawings of

    waking free imagery. Dreaming 4: 1-27.

    Leuzinger-Bohleber, M. 1995), Die Eizelfallstudie als psy

    choanalytisches Forschungsinstrument. Psyche

    49:434

    481.

    Pfeifer, R. submitted), Remembering a depressive

    primary object? Memory in the dialogue between psy

    choanalysis and cognitive science.

    Internat. Psycho

    Anal.

    Schneider, M.,

    Pfeifer, R., Eds. 1992), Two

    Butterflies on My Head. : Psychoanalysis in the In

    terdisciplinary Scientific Dialogue.

    New York: Springer.

    Cross-Cultural Forays

    Commentary by Keith Oatley Toronto)

    Paul Whittle has written an eloquent piece about the

    fault that runs through psychology, as tectonic faults

    run through communities or raise mountain ranges be

    tween nations. He characterizes what lies on either

    side of the fault in psychology land. His article identi

    fies how the fault both can and cannot be crossed, how

    Keith Oatley

    Lorenzer, A. 1987), ZumWiderstandspotential der Psycho

    analyse.

    Fragmente

    19:185-197.

    Masling, J., Ed. 1983), Empirical Studies ofPsychoanalytic

    Theories Vol. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Modell, A. 1984), Psychoanalysis in a New Context. New

    York: International Universities Press.

    Moser, U. 1992), Two butterflies on

    my head, or why have

    a theory in psychoanalysis? In:

    Two Butterflies on My

    Head.

    :

    Psychoanalysis in the Interdisciplinary Sci

    entific Dialogue

    ed. M. Leuzinger-Bohleber, H. Schnei

    der,

    R Pfeifer. New York: Springer.

    von Zeppelin,

    I.

    Schneider, W. 1991),

    Cogni

    tive-Affective Processes: New Ways of Modeling.

    New

    York: Springer.

    Pfeifer, R., Leuzinger-Bohleber, M. 1986), Application

    of cognitive science methods to psychoanalysis: A case

    study

    of

    some theory.

    Internat. Rev. Psychoanal.

    13:221-240.

    Scheier, C. 1999),

    Understanding Intelligence.

    Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Rosenfield,

    I.

    1988),

    The Intervention of Memory: A New

    View of the Brain.

    New York: Basic Books.

    Roth, M. S., Ed. 1998),

    Freud: Conflict and Culture.

    New

    York: Knopf.

    Rothstein, A., Ed. 1985),

    Models of the Mind: Their Rela

    tionship to Clinical Work.

    New York: International Uni

    versities Press.

    Sarnoff, L. 1971),

    Testing Freudian Concepts: nExperi

    mental Approach.

    New York: Springer.

    Shevrin, H., et al. 1996),

    Conscious and Unconscious Pro

    cesses: Psychodynamic Cognitive

    and

    Neurophysiologi

    cal Convergencies.

    New York: Guilford.

    Strenger, C. 1991), Between Hermeneutics

    and

    Science:

    nEssay on the Epistemology of Psychoanalysis.

    Madi

    son, CT: International Universities Press.

    Wegman, C. 1977), A computer simulation

    of

    Freud s

    counterwill theory. Behav. Sci., 22:218-233.

    Marianne Leuzinger-Bohleber

    m Eberfeld

    la

    D-60488 Frankfurt am Main

    Germany

    it both can and cannot be transcended, and does so

    better than any other article to date.

    Whittle at last has situated the debate in the right

    place: the problem is a matter

    of

    culture. Within the

    culture

    of

    experimental psychology one adopts shared

    values and beliefs. Enculturation takes 3 or 4 years,

  • 7/25/2019 22 Cross-Cultural Forays: Commentary by Keith Oatley (Toronto)

    3/4

    Ongoing Discussion: Paul Whittle

    more if one continues with a doctorate. Psychoanalysis

    takes a comparable time in personal therapy, added to

    which may be a period of

    training. Whittle gets it ex

    actly right: one adopts one culture or another, just as

    one adopts a national or religious culture, according

    to accidents of temperament and life.

    A culture affords not only an identity with shared

    values, a common language, and a discourse commu

    nity, but also a containment, an emotional belonginess;

    and jus t as culture contains, it excludes. So it is not

    surprising to see exclusionary tactics at the border.

    To cross borders one needs a certain temperament-a

    restlessness with the world as given-and it means

    hazarding

    one s

    containment and identity.

    Whittle, one must suppose, has this temperament.

    I share it. I have even emigrated to Canada, a land

    dedicated to multiculturalism, that includes an uneasy

    alliance

    of

    French and English in proximity to a pow

    erful neighbor, the United States. A joke that goes

    around is that for Canada there s the best of all worlds:

    the English political system, American economics,

    and French culture. Unfortunately it didn t quite turn

    out like that. What we got is the English economic

    system, American culture, and French politics.

    In my personal acculturation into academic life,

    I started in medicine, and then joined experimental

    psychology at Cambridge. I later trained in psychoan

    alytic psychotherapy at the Philadelphia Association

    (whichWhittle mentions in a footnote). Just as, despite

    my Canadian citizenship, I haven t given up my Euro

    pean Union passport, so despite my involvement in

    the arts and psychoanalytic psychology, I have not

    given up my membership of academic psychology.

    Border life is, however, always an oddity. In psycho

    analysis there is even a personality type called

    bor

    derline, which is a semiderogatory term meaning on

    the border of psychosis. Whittle puts it more politely:

    to be on the border carries the risk of being seen as

    unsound. But he understates it. It is not just a risk.

    From the point

    of

    view

    of

    either culture, borderline

    types can never be quite sound.

    My understanding of cultural choices was illumi

    nated by an experience in 1979 when, traveling by

    myself, I reached Hong Kong from where, for the first

    time, it had just become easy to take trips into main

    land China. One simply had to present

    one s

    passport

    at the Chinese Consulate and 3 days later one could

    set off on a package tour. I went in a group of 30 to

    Canton (now Guangzhou) for 4 days. Our train

    stopped at the barbed wire fenced border, where we

    got off. We filed into a hut to be inspected by gun-

    9

    bristling soldiers

    of

    the Red Army, then got into an

    other train on the Chinese side.

    Here a fifth of the world s population lived in a

    manner totally unlike anything in the West. Through

    the train s windows I saw terraced fields on which

    crowds of people bent down to tend individual rice

    plants. We were shown a factory where people built

    trucks entirely by hand; I watched a man make a

    crankshaft on a lathe. We visited a farm in which, it

    was said, all decisions were made by the collective. I

    remember looking from the bedroom window of the

    new concrete hotel where our tour group was housed,

    to see people on their way to work on bicycles, like

    flocks of starlings. We were taken to peep into a cot

    tage in which a peasant mother cooked over an open

    hearth. On several days I absented myself from the

    group and walked the back streets where people in

    sheds were making machine parts by hand.

    All my fellow tourists were Americans. One was

    an economist who would offer comments:

    The

    chil

    dren have

    shoes-being

    barefoot is an important index

    of poverty, and They ve not turned the corner of

    industrialization. He managed to locate and become

    a drinking friend

    of

    the Polish Consul. There was also

    a young man from Boston, Bob, a student of Oriental

    medicine in Macau where he had lived for 6 years.

    There were schoolteachers from Illinois, businesspeo

    ple from Texas, retirees from Oregon. Back in Macau,

    after the trip, Bob introduced me to a wizened Chinese

    woman who had adopted him. Before this adoption,

    with its entry to family membership, he was, he said,

    simply a nonperson in Chinese society. I also had in

    teresting talks with two other medical students, not in

    our group, but from French-speaking Zaire who had

    scholarships at the medical school in Guangzhou, and

    who would come to the new Western-style hotel in

    the evenings in order, as they put it, to get laid occa

    sionally, to chat with people other than Chinese

    (whom they found unfriendly), and to escape the con

    fines of six-to-a-room living.

    I marvel at how compelling American culture is.

    It is not only irresistibly attractive to outsiders all

    around the world,

    it s

    even irresistible to insiders. As

    one distinguished American psychologist says to me

    each time I see him, every few years: Don t you

    think America is the best? One of the many cultural

    fascinations on my Chinese trip was a couple-I can t

    remember where they were from, let s say Iowa-who

    were uninterested in trucks and collective farms. What

    they liked was to take on one side the numerous inter

    preters who accompanied our group to tell them what

    a great place America was.

  • 7/25/2019 22 Cross-Cultural Forays: Commentary by Keith Oatley (Toronto)

    4/4

    240

    Most

    of

    our group were just tourists, peering at

    one culture from the capsule

    of

    another. Only Bob

    was prepared to live on the border. But he was full

    of

    ambivalence. Like the Zairean medical students, he

    did not much like Chinese society; for him it lacked

    warmth. At the same time he was deeply attracted to

    the tradition

    of

    Chinese medicine.

    So, although it is perhaps a scandal that the two

    aspects

    of

    psychology are distrustful of each other.

    Whittle is right, these are not jus t aspects, but self

    sufficient cultures. In Canada, for all our talk

    of

    multi

    culturalism, we have not yet managed to become com-

    Jaak Panksepp

    fortable with the fault-line that runs between the

    Anglos and the French, let alone with our many other

    cultural splits. Within psychology, we are not comfort

    able with our split, but perhaps by recognizing it as a

    cultural one, we psychologists can know that the move

    to make is toward multiculturalism.

    Keith Oatley

    Dept. of Human Development

    Applied Psychology

    OISE University

    of

    Toronto

    252 Bloor Street West

    Toronto Canada M5S

    V

    On Preventing Another Century of Misunderstanding: Toward a Psychoethology of Human Experience

    and

    a Psychoneurology

    of

    Affect

    Commentary by

    Jaak

    Panksepp (Bowling Green, Ohio)

    Whittle s gentle complaint provides fertile ground for

    sharing some of my own thoughts on this contentious

    topic the chasm between analytic-dissective and

    synthetic-integrative approaches to understanding the

    mind. I will take this opportunity to share what has

    been on my mind for the last 30 years rather frankly

    concerning our continuing failure to have a unified

    and coherent mind-brain-behavior science.

    The one thing all might agree on is that the exper

    imental psychology that emerged during the past cen

    tury has yet to give us a lasting and coherent science

    of

    the human or animal condition. In my estimation,

    this is largely due to the fact that it never really came

    to terms with the evolutionary dynamics and epige

    netic complexities

    of

    ancient regions of the mamma

    lian brain. All too often it skirted the most profound

    and central issues

    of

    our

    lives the

    clarification

    of

    the

    many internal impulses and feelings that guide the

    intentional actions and choices we routinely make

    each day. For quite a while, neuroscience has also

    followed that same pattern, pretending that the dy

    namic, evolutionarily provided integrative statesof the

    nervous system are of little importance for under

    standing what the brain does. In fact, the probability

    high that the brain generates a great deal of its

    magic not simply through information transmis-

    Jaak Panksepp is Distinguished Research Professor

    of

    Psychobiology,

    Emeritus, Department

    of

    Psychology, Bowling Green State University,

    Ohio.

    sion, but through massive, coordinated operationsof

    enormous ensembles of neurons that create global and

    organic neurodynamics (states of being) that constitute

    the forms

    of

    affective consciousness, not capable of

    being reproduced, so far as we know,

    on

    digital com

    puters. Those global, evolutionary dynamics are the

    fundamental fabric of mind, which comes to be richly

    embellished and besmirched by the vast complexities

    of individual experiences information that is more

    readily reproducible computationally.

    Psychoanalysis addressed many

    of

    these issues

    but all too rarely in ways that helped create a rigorous

    culture of consensual

    truth

    that is the hallmark of

    modern scientific thought (Macmillan, 1997). Experi

    mental psychology became a fledgling memberof the

    scientific community early in the twentieth century,

    not because of any coherent sc ientific insight and syn

    thesis it generated concerning the nature of mind or

    the natural behaviors organisms exhibit, but rather be

    cause of its willingness to implement generally ac

    cepted experimental and statistical methodologies in

    its search for lasting knowledge. Indeed, its analytic

    success during the twentieth century was largely based

    on

    barring

    the door to the darker affective corners of

    the mind and keeping its attention focused obsessively

    on those peppercorns of behavioral and cognitive evi

    dence that strict-minded experimentalists could agree

    upon. Both behaviorism and cognitivism agreed, at

    times all too explicitly, that emotions and other af

    fective processes were issues too murky or difficult to